Sie sind auf Seite 1von 9

An Ars Oblivionalis? Forget It!

Author(s): Umberto Eco and Marilyn Migiel


Source: PMLA, Vol. 103, No. 3 (May, 1988), pp. 254-261
Published by: Modern Language Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/462374
Accessed: 31-08-2016 00:47 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

Modern Language Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to PMLA

This content downloaded from 128.148.252.35 on Wed, 31 Aug 2016 00:47:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
UMBERTO ECO

An Ars Oblivionalis? Forget It!

O NCE, AS A JOKE, some friends and I in- principles of a process that was artificial and in-
vented advertisements for university posi- stitutable at will-that would permit one to forget
tions in nonexistent disciplines. We divided in a matter of seconds what one knew. Imagining
these disciplines into four departments: adynata, aor possible formulation (without success) provided
impossibilia, containing sciences that were histor- me with hours of amusement. The Latin memory
ically impossible, such as history of the wheel in the treatises advised, for example, that one should as-
pre-Columbian empires, history of painting on sociate a given syllogism or element of factual
Easter Island, Aztec horse racing; oxymoronica, knowledge with a monstrous bleeding image in the
containing sciences that were self-contradictory and third room on the right in an enormous palace. We
analytically impossible, such as nomadic urban can understand why evoking that scene could recall
studies, institutions of deviance, binary logic of the to mind the piece of information idiosyncratically
included middle; byzantinica, containing sciences linked to it or why, by cultural convention, Diana
of utter uselessness, such as potiosection, or the art running in the midst of barking dogs could bring
of cutting broth; and tetrapiloctomia, or the art of hunting to mind. But it is difficult to imagine how
quartering a hair, containing sciences of excessive reevoking the same monstrous image could cancel,
subtlety, such as microscopy of indiscernibles. repress, abolish the notion previously associated
One of the most interesting subjects was the ars with it. It is true that the same memory treatises,
oblivionalis, as opposed to the mnemonic arts. We when it is necessary to free a system of loci or mem-
had to decide whether this art should be classified ory to make room for other notions, advised that
in the Department of Adynata or in the Depart- one should imagine a man who removed images
ment of Oxymoronica. The uncertainty, as we shall and tossed them out a window. But this technique
see, is of no little import. allows one not to forget something but to remem-
The ars oblivionalis was to elaborate techniques ber that one wanted to forget it.
for forgetting. I repeat: techniques. In fact, it is pos- I reflected at length on the physiological and psy-
sible to forget accidentally, as a consequence of chological reasons for the impossibility of an ars
repression, drunkenness, drugs, cerebral lesions. oblivionalis. I believe that in both cases there is a
But these are natural events, which do not concern dialectic of contiguity and similarity. If object x has
us here. Not only do Jakobson and Halle teach us been in some way imagined to be in contact with ob-
that aphasia has numerous causes, but Johannes ject y, or if object x presents any sort of homology
Spangerbergius in his Libellus artificiosae mem- with object y, every time object x is evoked, object
oriae 'Book of Artificial Memory' already noted y will be as well.
that it is possible to forget on account of degener- But I do not see how one can imagine an object
ation, decline (owing to old age or illness), and the x that, duly evoked, acts in some way on the cere-
removal of cerebral organs. Mnemonic techniques bral center to cancel object y. The Jakobsonian
cannot provide remedies for feebleness and surgi- dyad explains how aphasia (and therefore forgetful-
cal excision, but they can offer rhetorical precepts ness) manifests itself but does not tell us how to pro-
to make up for deterioration that causes us to for- duce aphasia and forgetfulness artificially. Or at
get things in the past. least it does not explain how to reproduce them as
The problem was to establish the principles of a cultural and voluntary phenomena. Neurophysiol-
technique and of a rhetorical art-and therefore ogy can at best tell us how to act on the cerebral

254

This content downloaded from 128.148.252.35 on Wed, 31 Aug 2016 00:47:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Umberto Eco 255

centers to produce natural causes of forgetfulness alphabets in the forms of animals, vegetables,
effectively. minerals, etc.).
It is nevertheless not by chance that Jakobson The fact that mnemotechnics are a semiotic
took recourse in two linguistic-semiotic categories phenomenon was known also to the ancients, who
to explain the internal mechanism (if not the cause) insisted on the analogies between mnemotechnics
of a neurophysiological phenomenon like aphasia. and writing (Rossi 137, 144, 160, passim). Even the
This suggests that we might see the art of memory memory arts of the Renaissance, which cast them-
(and consequently both recall and forgetfulness) selves no longer as a simple practical instrument but
not in neurophysiological or psychological terms as a source of cosmic knowledge or as an organic
but in semiotic terms. imago mundi, take as their basic assumption the
I examine two problems: (a) to what extent a idea that the world is a divine writing. Mnemotech-
mnemotechnics is a semiotics and (b) why a semi- nic signifiers do nothing other than reproduce an
otics, and therefore a mnemotechnics, is an appara- original cosmic writing, a tangle of signaturae, an
tus inherently ill-suited to stimulate forgetfulness. organic labyrinth of significant similarities. As Ra-
Finally, even if in a tentative and less than satisfac- mus already noted, memory is the shadow of order
tory manner, I examine the way in which a semiotics (dispositio), and order is the syntax of the universe.
can be used, if not to forget, at least to render re- To say that a mnemotechnics is a semiotics means
call more difficult. that one is dealing with an apparatus that orders a
plane of expression, form, and substance and that
this plane of expression is linked to a plane of con-
I. Mnemotechnics as Semiotics tent, form, and substance. Naturally, since the art
of memory is a connotative semiotics, it has a cru-
When I say that a mnemotechnics is a semiotics, cial function that institutes the expression of its pri-
I use the term semiotics in the sense given it by mary content (intuitively understandable) and its
Hjelmslev: a mnemotechnics is a connotative semi- secondary content (the res memorandae) in
otics.' To assert that the arts of memory are a functives.
semiotic phenomenon is little more than banal. A mnemotechnics is essentially a semiotics be-
Linking y with x in some fashion means using one cause, in its most elaborate form, it uses a syntac-
as the signifier of the other. The fact that the signi- tic system of loci (rooms of a palace or a theater,
fier is frequently a mental image (a memory place heavenly structures, etc.) destined to hold images,
can be either real or imaginary) does not change which assume the function of lexical units. These
things. From Ockham to Peirce we have assumed images are in turn linked to a system of res
that a mental icon or concept can be understood as memorandae, which represent the corresponding
a sign as well. At most we can ask ourselves, when units of content. At times these sematic units are ar-
places and images are only mental, what one must ranged in structural relations and organized in a sys-
do to remember the signifying apparatus if one tem of content that appears homologous to the
wishes to evoke the signified associated with it. This system of loca. Thus the relation appears double:
not inconsiderable problem is addressed, for exam- between syntax of expression and syntax of content
ple, by Cosmas Rossellius in his Thesaurus artiflcio- on the one hand and between "lexemes" and "se-
sae memoriae. Rossellius suggests remembering a memes" on the other.
system of places in alphabetical order. This sugges- There are mnemotechnics that choose another
tion reveals that a mental mnemotechnics requires expression for their own content-for example, the
a mnemotechnics of activation in order to be used, verse that represents the various figures of the syl-
which in turn requires another mnemotechnics of logisms (Barbara Celarent Darii Ferio) or those
activation, and so on ad infinitum, with all the verses that serve to recall the names of the seven
paradoxes that arise from every argument of the notes (ut queant laxis resonare fibris, etc.). Here, an
Third Man. In fact, even though Rossellius con- expression like the three a's of "Barbara" or the ut
siders the mnemotechnics by mental signifier, he of the first verse, attributed to Guido d'Arezzo, is
judges more efficacious, even if clumsier, the a linguistic expression that stands, in the first case,
mnemotechnics that use places and images for a logical expression and, in the second, for a mu-
represented concretely, such as objects, paintings, sical expression. The relation is motivated by the
statues, letters of the alphabet, or literaefictae (i.e., identity of expressive substance. The a of "Barbara"

This content downloaded from 128.148.252.35 on Wed, 31 Aug 2016 00:47:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
256 An Ars Oblivionalis? Forget It!

is basically identical to the A of the traditional analyzing according to degrees of iconicity. Even
Aristotelian logical square, and at this point the per- the ancients knew that any thing, given a certain
son using this mnemotechnic device knows that a description, can be similar to any other. For exam-
syllogism in "Barbara"' is composed of three univer- ple, Cosmas Rossellius, after having affirmed that,
sal affirmatives. To this category of the vocalis "positis figuris, nunc consequenter quomodo ad
similitudo belong the associations by partial pho- memoranda efficientur, dicendum restat" 'given the
netic identity as well, such as hell for health. Some- figures, it now remains to explain how they aid
times the initial of the name of the thing stands for memory,' and having noted that the best similes are
the letter of the alphabet, and the thing is those that are in re, admits that it is necessary to
represented by an image. Cosmas Rossellius sug- realize "quomodo multis modis aliqua res alteri sit
gests imagining an ass, an elephant, and a rhinoc- similis ratione" 'how in many ways a thing can be
eros in order to remember the word aer. similar to another from a given point of view' (2.8).
Mnemotechnics that link one syntactic system to Let it suffice to leaf through the Idea del theatro
another deal with relations between two forms of of the most audacious among the authors of mem-
expression. An example of such a device would be ory treatises, Giulio Camillo Delminio, to see how
a labyrinth with binary disjunctions that helps one freely the most varied rhetorical practices come to
recall a system of phonologically distinctive fea- be grouped together beneath the rubric of similar-
tures. The real semiotic difficulties arise when one ity. Even in a rapid reading of several chapters, one
establishes the relations between expressive images finds:
and res memorandae. In the classical arts of mem- similarity of morphological traits: the centaur for
ory, which emphasized the liveliness of the expres- horse racing, the sphere for astrology;
sive image, the relation was often idiosyncratic and similarity of action: two fighting serpents for the
idiolectical. The image of a beautiful maiden on military arts;
which Peter Tomasi of Ravenna insists with such metonymy for historical or mythological con-
sensuality in his Foenix could be linked to any con- tiguity: Vulcan for the arts of fire;
tent: passages of canonical law, verses of the clas- metonymy for cause: silkworms for clothing;
sical poets, philosophical adages, and Ciceronian metonymy for effect: the flayed Marsias for the
sententiae. Likewise, the relation between the sys- scene of a massacre;
tem of loca and the content form could be arbitrary. metonymy for ruler and ruled: Neptune for the
It is with Renaissance mnemotechnics, with Bruno nautical arts;
and with the followers of the Baroque "pansophia," metonymy for agent and action: Paris for the
that there comes to be a rigorous relation (a "real tribunal;
connection") between shadows and idea, between metonymy for agent and end: a maiden with a
signaturae and signata, between symbols and res, vial of fragrance for perfumery;
so that it is possible to have "a building whose struc- antonomasia: Prometheus, giver of fire, for the
tures mirror exactly the structures of reality" (Rossi artisan;
112). vectorial iconism: Hercules drawing an arrow
There arises, then, the problem of the rules for with three points and aiming toward the heavens for
establishing and institutionalizing the similarity the sciences of heavenly things;
among the functives of the sign function. The re- direct inference: Mercury with a cock for trade.
lation between the syntax of expression (the system A chain of inferences based on narrative frames:
of loca) and the content form is normally estab- Europa on the bull for conversion and assent of the
lished on the basis of projected homologies and is will but also for holiness and religion because
explainable in geometrical terms. The grid of a
Pythagorean table is homologous to the grid of an
Europa . . . per lo mare portata riguardando non la
urban settlement organized on an orthogonal plan,
parte alla quale ella e portata, ma quella onde ella si e
or on the plan of a Roman military camp.
partita, e l'anima portata dal corpo per lo pelago di
More complex is the problem of the similarity be- questo mondo, la quale si rivolge pure a Dio, terra
tween expressive images and units of content. We sopraceleste.
know that in the Renaissance the notion of similar-
ity was fluid, not reducible to the figure of meta- Europa, . . . who, as she is carried over the sea, looks
phoric similarity or to any of the forms of iconism not in the direction in which she is being carried but
that we habitually use today as a rigorous way of toward the place from which she departed, is the soul, car-

This content downloaded from 128.148.252.35 on Wed, 31 Aug 2016 00:47:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Umberto Eco 257

ried by the body figurative


over the logic, high
are to a great sea
degree subjective.
of this The wo
looking toward God, the land above the heavens.... emblematic tradition ends up institutionalizing
(81) them more on the grounds of inherited convention
than on the grounds of any observable motivation.
From this last comparison we see how the excess of Rossi (143-45) notes that, at least from Bruno on,
codified and conventionalized traits from mythol- images substitute for terms and topics substitute for
ogy can permit absolutely unforeseeable interpre- analytics; traditional rhetoric had always classified
tive chains. It is unforeseeable that the cock with the tropes and figures, though in an unsystematic way,
lion should recall the principality. The reason is that according to a recognizable typology, while it seems
that mnemotechnics establishes associations with-
out taking account of such categories.
[n]on solamente Plinio apre questa significazione, ma
Rhetoric, when brought into play, appears unob-
lamblico platonico e Lucrezio ancora dicono che, quan-
tunque amendue questi animali siano solari, nondimeno
trusively. Note how Spangerbergius lists among the
il Gallo porta negli occhi alcun grado eccellente del sole, various kinds of simile effictio corporum (gray hair
nel quale riguardando il Leone si umilia a lui. and trembling in the aged), notatio adfectum (the
wolf is voracious, the hare is timid), etymology
not only does Pliny broach this meaning, but lamblicus (Philip as the lover of horses), onomatopoeia and
the Platonist and Lucretius also say tlhat, though both of rerum effectus (effect for cause or the activity itself
these animals are solar animals, the cock nevertheless has for the specific actor).
in his eyes something of the sun's excellence, so that the The author I have found most systematic is per-
lion, when he looks upon this, humbles himself before the
haps Rossellius (but we will see how asystematic
cock. (94)
and casual his system is). He lists the following
correlations:
by a sample: a quantity of iron
Furthermore, in order to recall
contex
mine appropriateness or similarity, because under iron;
Prometheus the cock signifies the principality but by similarity, which in turn is subdivided into
under Pasiphae it signifies the excellence, superi- similarity of substance (the human being as the
ority, dignity, and authority of humankind (94-95). microcosmic image of the macrocosm) and of
The elephant is traditionally a highly religious an- quantity (ten fingers for the ten commandments);
imal, but under Mercury it signifies religious fable by metonymy and antonomasia: Atlas for the as-
telling and under Prometheus religion toward the tronomers or for astronomy, a bear for the angry
gods of the fables (79). man, the lion for pride, Cicero for rhetoric;
In fact, it seems that all arts of memory unite ex- by homonymy: the animal dog for the dog star;
pression and content in a way that is quite adven- by irony and contrast: the fool for the wise man;
turous and asystematic. They try to link the form by vestigial traces: the track for the wolf, the mir-
of memory places and of images to the form and ror in which Titus admired himself for Titus;
furnishings of the world by establishing chains of by a word of different pronunciation: sanguine
homologous relations. But the arts of memory seem for sane;
reluctant to elaborate a rhetorical logic of chains. by similarity of name: Arista for Aristotle;
Rather they set into play what I would call an in- by genus and species: the leopard for the animal;
terpretive hermeticism: everything can be the sign by pagan symbol: the eagle for Jove;
of everything else, and therefore the play of cor- by peoples: the Parthians for arrows, the Shiites
respondences becomes Proteus-like. Thus at the for horses, the Phoenicians for the alphabet;
very center of a metaphysics of the correspondence by zodiacal sign: the sign for the constellation;
between the order of representation and the order by relation between an organ and its function;
of the cosmos one is witness to a kind of theater of by common attribute: the crow for Ethiopia;
deconstruction and of infinite regress. The relation, by hieroglyphic: the ant for prudence;
even when it seems founded on historical and and finally, the association that is totally idiosyn-
mythological data that are quite institutionalized, cratic: any monster of any sort for anything to be
remembered.
turns idiosyncratic, even when the idios is not an in-
dividual but a historical and cultural setting. Con- Although the rules of association may be fluid,
sequently, the established associations, instead of an art of memory is a semiotics for another precise
being similarities of continuities supported by a reason. Cosmas Rossellius understood this point

This content downloaded from 128.148.252.35 on Wed, 31 Aug 2016 00:47:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
258 An Ars Oblivionalis? Forget It!

with particular clarity. The complexity of the ex- vast and elaborate systems of essential things. But
pressive syntax he draws on in his Thesaurus is very the problem, it seems to me, is pragmatic. There is
striking. To remember something, one must be fa- a virtual competence that regards every aspect of
miliar with systems of loca that are quite the universe, but one uses a very localized segment
complicated-so complicated, in fact, that for of that competence. The reasons for doing so are
those systems that can be visualized easily, Rossel- fortuitous: one remembers what one already
lius must produce theaters of planetary structures, remembers in order to remember another thing,
heavenly hierarchies, infernal circles; for those that which by chance one does not remember. The avail-
are less given to representation by diagram, such as able pieces of information, potentially preexistent,
the series of animals, plants, and illustrious men, can exchange semiotic function among themselves,
he is forced to rely on alphabetical classifications. according to the weakness or strength of our mem-
This brings us to the first problem, already men- ory. If for one person it can be useful to associate
tioned above: that of the techniques for remember- the series of planets (known) to the series of angelic
ing the expressions of an art of memory. hierarchies, for another it can be useful to associ-
The second problem arises when Rossellius de- ate the series of angelic hierarchies (known) with the
fines the images to be inserted in the memory loca. series of planets. In Rossellius's semiotics, nothing
Units previously found among the loca (or the syn- is inherently expression or content, and everything
tactic units) can also be used as figures (that is, as can assume the function of one or the other as one
lexical units). A given fish can be the locus in a syn- likes, by a conventional decision, even if the poten-
tactic system that uses the animal kingdom, in tial correlation is based on some perceived ap-
which the lexical units are, for example, minerals propriateness.
and the content to be represented is the angelic hi- Paradoxically, the instruments of the art coincide
erarchy. But a fish can also be the lexical unit in- with the totality of the content to be remembered.
serted in the loca represented by infernal circles, for But one never even touches on the paradox of an ex-
example, in order to signify biblical precepts-even pression that is remembered from the start and is
if, in principle, memory treatises advise maintain- more complex than the content to be remembered.
ing a certain appropriateness between expression Both coincide, and memorans and memorandum
and content. As a locus, the lion serves to represent are constituted as such entirely on the basis of our
the letter L, but as a figure it stands for the devil. local competence and our practical necessities.
Figures of imaginary objects can stand for un-
known letters of the alphabet; absinthe can stand
for aloe. But it is clear that it is possible to proceed II. Semiotics as the Means of Making Present
conversely. If there is one expression that recurs fre-
quently in Rossellius it is "e converso" 'and vice If an art of memory is a semiotics, then we can
versa! (or its equivalents). Xcan stand for Yor "vice understand why it is not possible to construct an ars
versa." Rossellius's mnemotechnics is a semiotics oblivionalis on the model of an art of memory. If
because a sign function, not the nature of the thingone did, the ars oblivionalis would also be a semi-
otics, and it is proper to a semiotics to make present
itself, determines expression and content. Anything
can become either expression or content: "Ne something absent.
mireris, quod quae pro locis supra posuimus, pro Language-like all semiotic systems-has the
figuris nunc apta esse dicamus. Loca enim praedicta ability to render present what is not present (even
pro figuris (secundum diversos respectos) servire if only in the possible world circumscribed by our
poterunt" 'Do not look to the fact that what we assertions). Because of this, says Abelard, the ex-
considered fitting as the memory places above we pression "nulla rosa est" ('there is no rose,' 'such a
now declare to be fitting as figures. The above- thing like a rose has never existed') in some manner
mentioned places then could serve as figures (ac- brings to our mind the rose. And though the
cording to the context)' (78). Rabelaisian question "utrum Chimera, in vacuo
The condition laid down here is crucial, because bombinans possit comedere secundas intentiones"
an art of memory like that of Rossellius is not only 'whether a chimera humming in the void can con-
a technique but also a cosmic representation. In ab- sume second intentions' refers to a nonexistent
stract terms, we could say that to remember a few thing, it renders present both the chimera and the
insignificant things one would need to remember second intentions, not to mention the impossible

This content downloaded from 128.148.252.35 on Wed, 31 Aug 2016 00:47:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Umberto Eco 259

humming that tonomasia)


the and between an expression
chimera and two sig-
ought to p
void. nifieds, notions, or definitional contents (as, for
Thus the logical discussions about existential example, when one does not remember whether
presuppositions appear naive and senseless, as do fraise means "blackberry" or "blueberry").
such discussions about the truth value of the as- Neither of these phenomena ever appears by sub-
sertion traction (there was something that then disap-
1. Yesterday Peter met his aunt peared); rather, they appear by addition (two
if one were able to assert truthfully that notions or terms are superimposed in memory, and
2. Peter has no aunts, therefore 1 is false or one can no longer tell which is right). Normally the
meaningless. phenomenon appears when we make an error the
In fact, no one is so silly as to respond to 1 with 2, first time or the first times; then we are given the
and one will more likely respond with 3, 4, 5, or 6: right information, and from that moment we
3. What aunt are you talking about? (assuming remember both the error and the correction with-
an error in the identification of the individual); out remembering which is which.
4. You must have dreamed this up (referring to The first time I dealt with a circuit breaker to
the existence of the aunt in a possible world); reactivate the electricity after a short circuit, I did
5. What do you mean by "aunt"? (assuming a not know whether I was supposed to push the green
lexical error); button and leave the red one up, or vice versa, to
6. I didn't know that Peter had any aunts (cor- bring the light back on. I was told of course what
recting one's own beliefs). the right combination was. But since then, every
Situations 3 to 6 occur because every assertion, time I find myself in the same situation, I remem-
more than presupposing, posits the entities that it ber the problem rather than its solution. The psy-
names; it renders them present in the universe of chological explanation for this is obvious: the
discourse with semiotic force, even if only as the en- problem made a greater impression on me than its
tity of a possible world. And if we do not wish to solution did, and therefore it is the problem that im-
argue extensionally, let it be said that every enun- pressed itself in my memory.
ciation of terms posits their intention. And if inten- There is a game in which the dealer (who does not
tions are not material facts, they are at least, in some participate in the game) takes a very difficult word
fashion, psychic facts, or they can be postulated as from the dictionary and announces it to the players.
such. This means that every expression determined Each player must give a definition that he or she be-
by a semiotic sign function sets into play a mental lieves or knows to be false but that seems absolutely
response as soon as it is produced, thus making it plausible. Then each votes for the definition that he
impossible to use an expression to make its own or she holds to be true. The player who receives the
content disappear. If the arts of memory are semi- most votes-that is, the player who imagines the
otics, it is not possible to construct arts of forget- most plausible false definition-wins. On a num-
ting on their model, because a semiotics is by ber of occasions I have received a word whose
definition a mechanism that presents something to meaning I knew, though the word was unusual and
the mind and therefore a mechanism for producing difficult; after I maliciously constructed a good
intentional acts.2 false definition, I was unable to remember which of
the two definitions was the right one.
Thus, it is possible to forget on account not of de-
III. Strategies for Producing Oblivion fect but of excess, just as, though it is not possible
to destroy the meaning of an assertion pronounced
It is possible, however, to use a mnemotechnics aloud, it is possible to pronounce another assertion
(and, in general, a semiotics) to confuse memories, in the same moment, so that the two assertions are
even if not to forget. superimposed. There are no voluntary devices for
Let us consider several mechanisms in which a forgetting, but there are devices for remembering
notion or expression is not forgotten but comes to badly: it is necessary to multiply the semiosis. I can
be confused with other notions or other expres- try to forget the syllogisms of the first figure by
sions. The confusion can arise both between expres- training myself to pronounce repeatedly, day after
sions (confusion caused by pseudosynonymy, as day, "Birbiri Celirant Doria Fario" (rather than
when I confuse the words paranomasia and an- "Barbara Celarent Darii Ferio") until I become in-

This content downloaded from 128.148.252.35 on Wed, 31 Aug 2016 00:47:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
260 An Ars Oblivionalis? Forget It!

capable of remembering which of the two versions phabets that are difficult to learn, memorize, and
is the right one. I would be effecting a sort of can- interpret. Steganography might be the opposite of
cellation by the multiplication of false synonyms. the art of memory, because the latter art seeks to
One forgets not by cancellation but by superim- render present while the former seeks to hide. But
position, not by producing absence but by multiply- there are many links-hermetic links-and many
ing presences. And this explains why the authors of mnemotechnics sought basically to make memora-
the treatises on memory feared that one might ble to a few what could not be made memorable to
remember so much as to confuse one's ideas and, many, while steganography in the end postulates a
therefore, for all practical purposes, to forget. It sender and an addressee capable of understanding
seems, in fact, that at a certain point in his life Giu- the message clearly. To the extent that both arts
lio Camillo apologized for his confusion and his multiply their devices, they can lead to the confu-
slipping memory, blaming them on his long and sion already noted-but, once again, by excess and
frenetic dedication to the theaters of the world. On not by defect of semiosis.
the other hand, Agrippa asserts, in his polemic So it has been established why an ars oblivionalis
against mnemotechnics, that the mind is made ob- is not possible. It belongs to the Department of
tuse by these monstrous images and that, over- Adynata because it cannot be realized. But if we un-
loaded, it is led to madness (and, I deduce, to an derstand it to be a semiotica oblivionalis, it belongs
insane loss of memory). to the Department of Oxymoronica, because a
Another means of forgetting, also based on an semiotics is by definition a device that stalls natu-
excess of semiosis, is that of transforming an ars ral processes of oblivion.3
memoriae into a steganography, as happens in
Porta, Trithemius, Schott, and Kircher but as would Milan, Italy
seem to happen also in Rossellius's Thesaurus. In
order to remember the obvious, one invents al- Translated by Marilyn Migiel

Notes

1 For this discussion, I am of course indebted to the fun- when I see them connected to Prometheus am I brought to ac-
damental works of Rossi and Yates. tivate a given zone of my competence and to recall the princi-
2 A mnemotechnics has another characteristic that is typical
pality. Mnemotechnic cleverness, like the cleverness of every
of every semiotics. A correlation is based not on a simple and textual strategy, consists in fixing in some way the distinctive fea-
automatic equivalence but on a principle of inferentiality, how- tures that have to be recalled in the course of remembering, to
ever elementary it may be. If the sign were based on the simple the detriment of other features. In order to associate Proserpina
equivalence and on the absolute synonymy (of the type /man/ with the underworld, an art of memory must establish that the
= "mortal rational animal," /Zeus/ = "Jove"), mnemotech- rape of Proserpina, not the fact that she is a woman, is of prime
nics could not function (nor could a language function, for var- importance. The memory treatises tell us how to select these fea-
ious reasons put forth elsewhere [Eco]). In order to associate the tures for the image we wish to impress in our memory, even if
definiens with the definiendum one must know both in advance; they do it in a highly unsystematic way, while contemporary
it is also necessary to know in advance that the expression x representations of meaning used in semiotics and artificial in-
stands for the content y. In a semiotics based on the principle telligence seek optimal representations on which even a machine
of inferentiality and realized in contexts and circumstances, how- could operate to make later selections.
ever, the sense of an expression is a packet, potentially a quite Only in this way, by learning the signifier, as Peirce argues, do
vast bundle of instructions for interpreting the expression in di- I learn something more; and I learn this something more, basi-
verse contexts, drawing from it (as Peirce wishes) all the most dis- cally, by learning something less-that is, by excluding all the
tant illative consequences or, in other words, all its interpretants. other interpretations of the same expression that I could have
In principle, we know every possible interpretant of an expres- offered. But such oblivion is transitory; it is a side effect provoked
sion, and in practice we know that segment permitted by our in- by the interpretive economy. In order to work, a semiotics presup-
dividual or group competence, that is, by our encyclopedia. poses the possession of an encyclopedic information. The pro-
Interpreting the expression in context means magnifying certain cess of production and of interpretation of texts, by contrast,
interpretants and narcotizing others, and narcotizing them means encourages these passing pseudocancellations.
removing them provisionally from our competence, at least for 3 This essay was first presented at the Symposium on Semi-
the duration of the interpretation taking place. I can know every- otics and Memory. Centro di Semiotica e Linguistica. Urbino,
thing about cocks and not remember that in a given mnemotech- July 1966.
nic system they are meant to recall the principality. And only

This content downloaded from 128.148.252.35 on Wed, 31 Aug 2016 00:47:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Umberto Eco 261

Works Cited

Agrippa, H. C. De incertitudine et vanitate scientiarum. Opera. rales artes. Frankfurt: Wechel, 1581.
Lyon: Beringos, 1600. Rosselli[us], Cosma[s]. Thesaurus artificiosae memoriae. Vene-
Delminio, Giulio Camillo. La idea del theatro. Tutte l'opere. zia: Paduanius, 1579.
Venezia: Giolito, 1567. Rossi, Paolo. Clavis universalis: Arti della memoria e logica com-
Eco, Umberto. Semiotics and the Philosophy of Language. binatoria da Lullo a Leibniz. 1960. 2nd ed. Bologna: Mu-
Bloomington: Indiana UP, 1984. lino, 1983.
Hjelmslev, Louis. Prolegomena to a Theory of Language. Trans. Spangerbergius, Johannes. Libellus artificiosae memoriae. Wit-
Francis J. Whitfield. Madison: U of Wisconsin P, 1943. tenberg: Seitz, 1570.
Jakobson, R., and M. Halle. Fundamentals of Language. The Tomasi, Pietro [da Ravenna]. Foenix. Venezia: de Chrois, 1491.
Hague: Mouton, 1956. Yates, Frances. The Art of Memory. London: Routledge, 1966.
Peirce, Charles Sanders. Collected Papers. 4 vols. Cambridge: . Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition. London:
Harvard UP, 1934-48. Routledge, 1964.
Ramus, Petrus [Pierre de la Ramee]. Scholae in tresprimas libe-

This content downloaded from 128.148.252.35 on Wed, 31 Aug 2016 00:47:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen