Sie sind auf Seite 1von 19

European Journal of Pragmatism and

American Philosophy
IV-2 | 2012
Wittgenstein and Pragmatism

Streams and River-Beds


James’ Stream of Thought in Wittgenstein’s Manuscripts 165 and 129

Anna Bocompagni

Electronic version
URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/718
DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.718
ISSN: 2036-4091

Publisher
Associazione Pragma

Electronic reference
Anna Bocompagni, « Streams and River-Beds », European Journal of Pragmatism and American
Philosophy [Online], IV-2 | 2012, Online since 24 December 2012, connection on 20 April 2019. URL :
http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/718 ; DOI : 10.4000/ejpap.718

This text was automatically generated on 20 April 2019.

Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right
of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-
NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License.
Streams and River-Beds 1

Streams and River-Beds


James’ Stream of Thought in Wittgenstein’s Manuscripts 165 and 129

Anna Bocompagni

Introduction
1 Ludwig Wittgenstein’s interest in the writings of William James characterizes the whole
of his philosophical work. We know from a letter to Bertrand Russell that as early as 1912
he was reading The Varieties of Religious Experience, a book that gave rise to his attraction
for mysticism,1 and that he later warmly recommended to his friend Maurice Drury. 2
After his return to philosophy, in his notebooks and typescripts he refers to James and
particularly to The Principles of Psychology (PP) 3 from the beginning of the Thirties to the
end of his life.4 Furthermore, we know that he even thought of using it as a textbook for
his lessons in Cambridge, though according to some critics more as a set of examples of
the mistakes of psychologists than as a handbook in the usual sense. 5 Wittgenstein’s
interest in James’ psychology, far from diminishing, even increased in the last years of his
life, and was at its greatest after the Second World War: the notes from his 1946-47
lectures collected by his students Peter Geach, Kanti Shah and A. C. Jackson6 are full of
explicit and implicit references to James, as well as the RPP (1946-48) and generally the
manuscripts of those years; besides, one should not forget the influence of James’ thought
on some relevant, though often neglected, concepts of the later Wittgenstein, such as
those of patterns of life, the indeterminacy of psychological concepts, the connection
between emotions and the expression of emotions.7
2 In spite of some early positive comments, notably not belonging to the Wittgensteinian
tradition,8 Wittgenstein’s attitude towards James and towards the PP has often been
described by Wittgenstein’s scholars as merely critical and negative. Peter Hacker, for
example, mentions James may times in his extensive commentary on the PI, but usually
as a negative counterpart of Wittgenstein’s ideas, sometimes identifying him with one of
the invisible interlocutors against which the philosopher battles in his remarks. 9
Regarding the stream of thought, Hacker depicts it as “philosophical confusion” and even

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 2

bluntly affirms that it is “largely a meaningless babble.”10 But, as more recently stated by
some other commentators,11 Wittgenstein’s attitude should be better described as
twofold: although he criticized James in many respects, he also appreciated James’
masterpiece, particularly for its richness of examples, its freshness, depth and also for the
“humanity” of its author.12
3 The PP chapter on the stream of thought is one of the main objects of concern for
Wittgenstein. It is here that we find some examples that he often cited and criticized,
such as that of the “and-feeling,” the “if-feeling” and the like (PP: I, 245; cf. PI: part II, 155,
RPP: I, §§ 331, 334), the recalling of a forgotten name or meaning (PP: I, 251; RPP: I, §§ 174,
180), the feeling connected to the intention of saying something (PP: I, 253; RPP: II, §§
242-3, PI: part I, §§ 591, 633, part II, 155, 182), and the case of Mr. Ballard as showing the
possibility of there being thought without language (PP: I, 266, PI, part I: § 342).
4 Strangely enough, James’ image of the stream has only rarely13 been associated with
Wittgenstein’s use of the metaphor of the flux or of the river. The latter uses this image in
various periods and with various meanings. During the phenomenological years of the PR,
he speaks about the flux of experiences and of the vagueness of immediate experience:
here the theme is connected to the question whether it is possible or not to have a
language of immediate experience. In these years Wittgenstein sometimes holds that it is
only in the flux of experience that any sentence can be verified, though it is constitutively
impossible for language to directly denote the elements of the flux.14 The reading of
James’ PP may hold some responsibility for the emergence of this set of problems. When
Wittgenstein’s interest turns from the phenomenological language to the ordinary
language, the image of the flux turns from the flux of experiences to the flux of life and
discourse. Again, it is probably James that Wittgenstein has in mind when he points out
that the meaning of any expression is not to be found in the flux of experiences but in the
context of the discourse and, more generally, in the context of life, with its linguistic
games and its background of know-how and culture.15 So, as Steiner (2012) elegantly
surmises, what enables our understanding of psychological concepts and phenomena is
not a mental immanence, but an anthropological-normative immanence: a logical-
grammatical context together with an anthropological background.16
5 What is still missing in the secondary literature, as far as I know, is a comparison between
James’ stream of thought and Wittgenstein’s river-bed of thoughts, which he describes in
OC with the aim of distinguishing between logical and empirical propositions. In
discussing the river-bed of thoughts Wittgenstein does not explicitly address James. But
the choice of the image and the words used to describe it can and do suggest such a
connection. Is it possible to find in the Nachlass details or evidence pointing in this
direction? Can Wittgenstein’s river-bed be read – among other things – as a direct
comment on James’ stream? As we shall see, the comparison and this conclusion are
legitimated by two remarks contained in Manuscripts 165 and 129. 17

1. The Nachlass
6 The name “James” appears 90 times in Wittgenstein’s Nachlass, from 1932 18 to 1950-51.19 In
particular, considering both the English expression “stream of thought” and its
equivalent in German “Gedankenstrom,” we can find four contexts in which Wittgenstein
makes use of James’ metaphor, some of which recur more than once.20

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 3

7 The first entry is in Item 120 (1937-38), a manuscript which is well-known because it
contains three drafts of the future preface of the PI. On February, 27th 1938 Wittgenstein
wrote a dozen pages in the manuscript, and it is here that we find the word
“Gedankenstrom” in the context of a discussion concerning if and when a man can be said
to be wrong when speaking about a pain that he is feeling. In the case of something
suspending or changing the direction of the man’s attention, Wittgenstein says, “the
stream of thought is interrupted, and we can only guess how it could have proceeded.”21
Here, it seems, the meaning of Gedankenstrom is not in question: Wittgenstein is using it
as a unproblematic concept, within the discussion of a peculiar language game. I shall call
this use of James’ expression “the unproblematic stream.”
8 The second occurrence is in Item 124, a manuscript volume containing remarks mostly
from 1944. After considering the problem of the relation between expectation and
fulfillment, and stressing the importance of the circumstances in which an expectation
takes place, Wittgenstein writes: “Here one could speak of the stream of thought, of
which James talks, and point out that, when a well-known name is mentioned to me, my
thoughts pour forth into a series of canals, and they continue to run in them, and that the
meaning of the name is revealed in these streams.”22 In the following lines there is a
critique to James: “He should tell us what happens, while he only tells us what must
happen – Wittgenstein writes –. He wants to communicate an empirical fact, but he slips
and makes a metaphysical remark.” I shall call this occurrence ‘the slippery stream.’
9 The third entry can be found in Item 165, a pocket notebook with remarks dating back,
again, mostly to 1944 and often mentioned in relation to the debate on following a rule
and on the private language argument. Many of these remarks are crossed through by
vertical or diagonal lines, and this is also the case of the passage we are going to cite.
Since this remark will appear again, with some variations, in a slightly later and more
accurate manuscript with no deletions, it is also worth working on this version, which is
very explicit about James’ ‘mistake.’ In discussing the relation between expectation and
fulfillment, intention and meaning, Wittgenstein proposes an example:
I’m waiting for two people A and B. I say: “When will he come!” Someone asks me:
“Who do you mean?” I say, “I thought about A.” And these very words have built a
bridge. Or he asks “Who do you mean?” I say, “I thought about…” a poem in which
there is this sentence. I make these connections among what I say in the course of
my thoughts and actions. (This remark is in relation with what W. James calls “the
stream of thought.” The mistake in his picture is that a priori and a posteriori
grammatical and experiential are not distinguished. So he speaks about the
continuity of the stream of thought and he compares it with that of spaces, not with
that of a sort of jet of water).23
10 The theme of expectation and fulfillment is often present in Wittgenstein’s writings; the
example with the expression “When will he come”! – without the explicit reference to
James’ stream of thought – recurs also in typescripts 211, 212, 213 of the beginning of the
Thirties, in various manuscripts of the Fourties and in Part I of the PI (§ 544).
11 The later manuscript which I mentioned is Item 129, a volume of the second half of 1944.
Correcting some previous misprints, Wittgenstein writes:
(I believe, that this remark is in relation with what W. James calls “the stream of
thought.” Even though he certainly does not distinguish a priori and a posteriori,
empirical and grammatical propositions).24
12 Again and with more clarity, Wittgenstein points out – although now without speaking of
a mistake – that James does not distinguish between a priori and a posteriori; and in this

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 4

case he speaks of grammatical and empirical propositions. I shall call this occurrence, in
the two formulations of MS 165 and 129, “the stream with no banks.”
13 In the same MS 129, only a few pages after what we have just read, we find the next entry.
“One could say – writes Wittgenstein –: I would not have an impression of the room as a
whole, if I could not let my glance wonder here and there and myself move around freely.
(Stream of thought.) James.”25 And he continues: “But how does it show that I have an
impression of it as a whole? In the naturalness with which I find my way in it; in the
absence of querying, doubting and surprise; in the fact that within its walls innumerable
activities are encompassed; and in the fact that I sum up all this as ‘my room’ in the
speech.” Here the stream of thought seems to correspond to a mentalist way of
conceiving what it is to know a certain meaning, a conception that Wittgenstein contrasts
by underlying the importance of actions and know-how. This last remark on the stream
of thought is repeated in Typescript 228 (1945-46), with no variations, and again, with
minor variations, in Typescript 233a, which was published as Zettel (in the published
edition we find it as § 203). I shall call this stream “the impressionist stream.”
14 Let us sum up. The first occurrence of the term seems, as we have seen, unproblematic:
Wittgenstein simply uses it in the context of the discussion of the meaning of internal
states such as pain and of the criterion of attributing truth or falsity to a man’s assertions
about his state. If meaning is to be found in the stream of thought, and the justification
for a true assertion too, then the interruption of the stream of thought may cause
problems in the identification of meaning and truth conditions. But is meaning to be
found in the stream of thought? This question, which is probably already implicitly
present in the “unproblematic stream,” is more explicitly addressed in what I have called
the “slippery” and the “impressionist” streams. In the first case, meaning is seen as the
streams and currents in which thought pours when a well-known name is mentioned. But
this characterization fails in its attempt to catch the empirical, experiential facts about
meaning, and becomes metaphysical. In the case of “the impressionist stream,”
Wittgenstein underlines the importance of some physical and active elements in the
determination of meaning (here, the meaning of a room, identified with the impression of
the room as a whole). Instead of accepting a private approach which stresses the role of
sensory impressions, Wittgenstein directs the attention towards the practical,
behavioural and linguistic elements in which the possession of the meaning shows itself.
15 The “slippery” and the “impressionist” conceptions of the stream as the inner place of
meaning (and, maybe, also the seemingly unproblematic first version) are both criticized
by Wittgenstein for their commitment to a psychologistic, internalist idea of the mind
and of meaning itself. The critique is addressed not only to James, 26 but also to
Wittgenstein’s own phenomenological phase: the argument against a private language
can be read as an implicit critique of the attempt to find truth conditions in the flux of
experiences or of thought, as this flux is intrinsically private and can rely on no public
criteria of assertibility or justification.27 A private language is impossible because, if it is
language, then it is not private:28 this is part of the grammar of the word “language.”
Thus, when James tries to explain meaning by referring to the stream thought, in
Wittgenstein’s view he misses the point. It is true that language and meaning belong to a
flux, but this is not the flux of thought: it is the flux of discourse and of life. 29 So, its depth
and richness notwithstanding, James’ psychology – in Wittgenstein’s view – remains
anchored to an introspective method which leads us astray (PI: §§ 411-14) and contributes
to the construction of the image of an internal realm, which is not so distant from the

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 5

classic Cartesian image. Two aspects must be, anyway, underlined: that James himself
tried to abandon the Cartesian concept of consciousness (Myers 1986: 61), and that his
appeal to experimental techniques and physiological theories aimed at a methodological
pluralism which mitigated the importance of introspection. Wittgenstein evidently
thought that it was not enough, and that James’ perspective was an example of a
discipline torn between “experimental methods and conceptual confusion,” as he
famously stated in the final paragraph of the PI.30
16 The remaining two occurrences of the “stream with no banks” are the remarks to which I
would like to dedicate the next section of this paper, for two reasons: because they allow
us to inquire further into one of Wittgenstein’s critiques towards James, which has not
yet been analyzed in depth; and because it can be fruitfully connected to Wittgenstein’s
own image of the river-bed of thoughts.

2. MS 165 and 129 as an Anticipation of the Metaphor


of On Certainty
17 Let us take a closer look at these two remarks. MS 165 attributes a mistake to James: that
of not distinguishing between a priori, or grammatical, and a posteriori, or empirical.
Mixing together these two aspects, Wittgenstein explains, James is not actually speaking
of a stream or of a jet of water; it would be more appropriate to say that he is speaking of
spaces and of the continuity of spaces. It is not easy to understand why it should be so.
Perhaps, we can argue, in the case of spaces it is correct not to distinguish between
something fixed and something variable: spaces have no banks, while streams do have
banks and stream-beds, they are defined by something that does not change – or at least
that does not change as rapidly as its content. In passing from MS 165 to MS 129, which
has the character of a more definite work, this reference to the continuity of spaces is
eliminated and the accusation is mitigated (there are no “mistakes” anymore), but, again,
Wittgenstein underlines the fact that James calls thought a “stream,” in spite of his not
distinguishing a priori and a posteriori. In other words, given his characterization of
thought, James should not have used the picture of a stream; conversely, if this can be
said to be a good image of thought, then James’ description of thought is fallacious.
18 The topic of the distinction between what is empirical (experiential, phenomenal) and
what is grammatical (conceptual, logical) is extensively treated Wittgenstein’s lectures of
the post-war years and in RPP, besides constituting one of the main themes of OC. In
Jackson’s notes of the lectures we can read, for example:
Now consider the suggestion: You’ve already thought the meaning before you speak
(James). Is this a psychological statement? If so, how many men does it apply to? Or
does it apply each time? If it’s a psychological statement it’s an hypothesis: but
James wishes to say something essential about thinking.31
19 Where is, then, the problem with James’ stream: in the description of thought, or in the
image? Evidently, for Wittgenstein, in the description. Indeed, it is exactly the image of
the stream that Wittgenstein himself will adopt, a few years later, in his own
characterization of thought. If read in this light, propositions 95 to 99 of OC not only give
a metaphorical description of thought and of the relation between the Weltbild (picture of
the world) and thought; but also constitute an implicit critique of James’ use of that
metaphor. Or, better said, they contribute to an implicit praise of James’ image, and an
implicit critique of James’ interpretation of his image:

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 6

95. The propositions describing this world-picture might be part of a kind of


mythology. And their role is like that of rules of a game; and the game can be
learned purely practically, without learning any explicit rules.
96. It might be imagined that some propositions, of the form of empirical
propositions, were hardened and functioned as channels for such empirical
propositions as were not hardened but fluid; and that this relation altered with
time, in that fluid propositions hardened, and hard ones became fluid.
97. The mythology may change back into a state of flux, the river-bed of thoughts
may shift. But I distinguish between the movement of the waters on the river-bed
and the shift of the bed itself; though there is not a sharp division of the one from
the other.
98. But if someone were to say “So logic too is an empirical science” he would be
wrong. Yet this is right: the same proposition may get treated at one time as
something to test by experience, at another as a rule of testing.
99. And the bank of that river consists partly of hard rock, subject to no alteration
or only to an imperceptible one, partly of sand, which now in one place now in
another gets washed away, or deposited.
20 Wittgenstein is here describing the difference and the relation between the propositions
of the world-picture and empirical propositions. The former are those which allow the
latter to work. Any empirical proposition is grounded in the common sense certainties
which shape our Weltbild, the way we see the world, the way we are minded, the picture
or the “mythology” which, so to speak, keeps everything together. Even when they look
like empirical propositions32 – “Here is one hand” is the classical example 33 – Weltbild
propositions are different in kind; it is meaningless to ask whether they are true or false,
as they form the background against which truth and falsity themselves are defined. They
are the hinges that must stay put, in order for the door to move.
21 The literature on Wittgenstein’s hinge propositions is vast and constantly increasing. For
its clarity and conciseness, it is useful to cite Danièle Moyal-Sharrock’s comment (2007:
72), according to which hinge propositions are:
- indubitable: doubt and mistake are logically meaningless;
- foundational: they do not result from justification;
- nonempirical: they are not derived from the senses;
- grammatical: they are rules of grammar;
- ineffable: they cannot be said;
- in action: they can only show themselves in what we say and do.
22 Hinges, says Moyal-Sharrock, even when they have an apparent propositional nature,
constitute non-propositional certainties, and are akinto instincts, ways of acting,
attitudes. Logic itself, since it is hinged on these certainties, belongs to the reign of
instinct and not to that of reason, and Wittgenstein could be considered the supporter of
a logical pragmatism which asserts the enacted nature of hinge certainties. 34
23 Logical propositions are not about facts in the world (notice how near this sounds to the
Tractatus). They work on the level of rules and normativity; it is the level of certainty,
which is categorically distinct from that of knowledge.35 Common sense propositions like
the Moorean “Here is one hand” or “The earth existed for a long time before my birth,”
except when they are said in peculiar contexts and circumstances, do not express a
genuine knowledge. In Moore’s (and James’)36 opinion, we know these propositions for
certain, even if we cannot prove them or give a ground for them. Wittgenstein denies that
we have an epistemic relation with what these propositions assert. The reason why we
cannot give a ground for these sorts of belief, is that the certainty which characterizes

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 7

them is itself a ground, and it shows itself in the ordinary “going without saying” of these
certainties. In everyday contexts, hinges work tacitly, they do not require to be
formulated; according to Moyal-Sharrock (2007: 94 ff.), they even require not to be
formulated, not to be said, because once said they would not go without saying. As Coliva
(2010: 151, 177) partially corrects, the only possibility for a hinge proposition to be
meaningfully uttered, is when it is used not in a descriptive but in a communicative and/
or normative manner.
24 In Wittgenstein’s metaphor, there is not a sharp division between the movements of the
waters in the river-bed and the movement of the river-bed itself; moreover, the banks of
the river are stratified, consisting partly of rock, partly of sand. This is not to be
interpreted as meaning that, at bottom, no distinction can be made.37 The distinction is at
the same time categorical and not sharp, because one and the same proposition can work
now as empirical and now as logical, but never as both. The shift from one to the other
uses may sometimes be due to slow changes in the Weltbild, as it is clear for example in
the case of Wittgenstein’s own certainty that man has never gone and never will be able
to go to the moon.38 But the change of the Weltbild (river-bed) does not occur at the same
empirical level as the change of what the Weltbild frames (waters).
25 Although Wittgenstein’s interlocutor in OC is primarily Moore, this is evidently the same
kind of objection that in the Manuscript notes he addressed to James. Besides,
Wittgenstein’s discussion of the Weltbild is particularly significant in the context of
psychological concepts and propositions, the “objectivity” of which, as Egidi (1995: 176)
puts it, “is not achieved by reference to objects, of both internal and external nature, but
depends on whether those sentences obey the system of rules of which they are part,”
which, in turn, imply a complex of “pragmatic criteria of significance.” Wittgenstein’s
discussion of psychology in his later years, then, in its connection to the theme of the
Weltbild and to the distinction between grammatical and empirical, can be read also as an
implicit critique of his phenomenological years and of the jamesian strand which can be
identified in his attempts to catch the flux of experiences. This is another reason which
contributes to the plausibility of reading the image of the river-bed as a sort of correction
of James’ image of the stream.

3. Is Wittgenstein’s Critique Justified?


26 In order to ascertain whether Wittgenstein’s critique of James is justified, we now need to
turn to the PP. In the chapter on the stream of thought, James, as is well-known,
characterizes it through five features (PP: I, 225):
- Every thought tends to be a part of a personal consciousness;
- Within each personal consciousness thought is always changing;
- Within each personal consciousness thought is sensibly continuous;
- It always appears to deal with objects independent of itself;
- It is interested in some parts of these objects to the exclusion of others, and
welcomes or rejects all the while.
27 It is in particular in the second and third characters, change and continuity, that James’
stream differs from Wittgenstein’s. Change is what may suggest, if ever, the comparison
between his stream and Heraclitus’ river, and indeed James is reminiscent of Heraclitus
when he writes that “no state once gone can recur and be identical with what it was
before” (PP: I, 230), that “there is no proof that the same bodily sensation is ever got by us

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 8

twice” (231), and of course when he affirms that “of the river of elementary feeling, it
would certainly be true to say, like Heraclitus, that we never descend twice in the same
river” (233). Wittgenstein, on the other hand, remarked that “The man who said that one
cannot step twice into the same river, uttered a falsehood. One can step twice into the
same river,” while explaining that “what we do is to bring words back from their
metaphysical to their normal use in language”39 (both Wittgenstein and James are
referring to a fragment of Heraclitus which is probably spurious, though since Plato on it
is widely accepted as the most famous expression of Heraclitus philosophy). 40 It is then by
an appeal to the “rough ground” (PI: § 107) of ordinary language that the metaphysics
implicit in the Heraclitean river is neutralized.
28 With regard to the feature of continuity, James, often compared to Henri Bergson, 41
defines the continuous as “that which is without breach, crack or division” (PP: I, 237),
and it is in these pages that he proposes to define consciousness as a stream (239).
Opposing the traditional psychologists and their empiricist background, James explains
that the image of the stream must convey not only the idea of pails or pots of water, but
also the fact that “even were the pail and the pots all actually standing in the stream, still
between them the free water would continue to flow,” because every image in the mind
“is steeped and dyed in the free water that flows round it” (255). By acknowledging this,
the vagueness that intrinsically characterizes our mental life can be re-instated in its
proper place (254). To describe this intrinsic vagueness – which, as Fairbanks (1966: 335
ff.) noted, is a very relevant aspect in Wittgenstein too – James (258) introduces the
concept of the fringe, synonyms of which are psychic overtone and suffusion; 42 images or
ideas in the mind do not possess definite contours, but fringed contours, they slowly pass
into each other with continuity, and this is due, physiologically, to the “faint brain-
process” that makes us aware of relations and objects only dimly perceived. The examples
and explanations that James uses in these pages are, as Wittgenstein underlines in
MS 165, to be connected more easily with spaces than with a stream. Indeed, he speaks for
instance about the relation between a thunderclap and the silence which precedes and
follows it (240); he compares the life of thought to the flight of a bird with its resting
places and places of flight (243); he mentions Zeno’s image of the arrow (244); he writes of
an “immense horizon” in which “the present image shoots its perspective before us”
(256) and of a “halo” that surrounds words and sentences (276). This spatial depiction
provides an immediate grasp of the key concept of the continuum, that James will later
(in RE) characterize as pure experience. We shall soon return on this aspect, which, as
Calcaterra (2010: 207) points out, is strictly connected to James’ (and more generally to
the pragmatists’) anti-dichotomic claims.
29 It must be noticed that James does not use the image of the stream without the awareness
of its implications: besides continuity and change, there are also other characteristics
which he is interested in highlighting and which this metaphor illustrates with clarity.
For example, when discussing attention and effort (I: 451-2) he again turns to his image:
The stream of our thought is like a river. On the whole easy simple flowing
predominates in it, the drift of things is with the pull of gravity, and effortless
attention is the rule. But at intervals an obstruction, a set-back, a log-jam occurs,
stops the current, creates an eddy, and makes things temporarily move the other
way. If a real river could feel, it would feel these eddies and set-backs as places of
effort.
30 We may wonder why he did not consider banks and stream-beds as equally relevant
features, besides currents and eddies. Is it that he simply did not see the role of the banks,

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 9

that is, the role of logic? This would be a hasty conclusion. In fact, in other parts of the PP
we can find the description of some elements that, in a sense, force the stream to flow in a
certain direction or according to certain rules.
31 The first connection that it is possible to make is with the chapter on habit, in which the
metaphor of a flow of water is used more than once to give account of what happens in
the brain, where, due to the plasticity of the nervous tissue, some “currents” shape,
through time, paths or channels.43 Here, if there is a distinction between brain-matter
and what flows through it, James also remarks that what seems fixed is not unchangeable.
Paths in the brain can be reshaped, and indeed a relevant part of the chapter is dedicated
to the importance of education and training in choosing, strengthen and, in some cases,
change the paths. Hence, if there is a distinction between river-beds and waters, change is
not the crucial element that discriminates between the two.
32 To find out something more about this distinction we can turn to the last chapter of the
PP, “Necessary truths and the effects of experience.” Here we are not dealing with
behavioural habits or instincts, but with thought and its laws; nevertheless, again, James’
account has to do with the conformation of the brain. The question from which his
argument starts, is whether necessary truths, due (as “universally admitted”)44 to the
organic structure of the mind, are explicable by experience or not. In the diatribe
between empiricists, who affirm that they are, and apriorists, who affirm that they are
not, James defends the apriorists’ side, but tries at the same time to give a naturalistic
explanation of the cause of these necessary truths. While a single judgment such as that
fire burns and water makes wet, or knowledge of time and space relations, may be caused
by objects with which we become acquainted, the categories for knowing and judging
need to be explained differently (PP: II, 632). It is the Darwinian mechanism of
spontaneous variations in the brain that James is thinking of, attributing to it the
responsibility of all the kinds of ideal and inward relations among the objects of our
thoughts which cannot be interpreted as reproductions of the order of outer experience.
Scientific conceptions, aesthetic and ethical systems are due to this category, as well as
pure sciences of classification, logic and mathematics, all of which are the result of the
fundamental operation of comparison. Comparison “is one of the house-born portions of
our mental structure; therefore the pure sciences form a body of propositions with whose
genesis experience has nothing to do” (626-7). James connects this theme with that of
meaning (a connection which may resemble Wittgenstein’s insistence on the difference
between the conceptual and the phenomenical), where he, for example, insists that we
know the difference between black and white without needing to consult experience: “
What I mean by black differs from what I mean by white,” and again “what we mean by one
plus one is two” because “we are masters of our meanings.” 45 Propositions expressing
time and space relations – summarizes James (644) – are empirical propositions, those
expressing the results of comparison are rational propositions. Yet, why is it that rational
propositions turn out to be in agreement with the empirical world? Why is it that the
straight line is effectively, every time we need to go from A to B in the real world, the
shortest way to connect the two points? “Luckily enough” (658), James answers, we find
that the space of our experience is in harmony with our rational suppositions. But we
must always remember that necessary truths are ideal relations and that they do not
reveal how things really are in the empirical world: they always have to be verified. As he
explains in relation to Locke’s conception, with which he seems to agree in this respect,
such ideas “stand waiting in the mind, forming a beautiful ideal network; and the most

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 10

we can say is that we hope to discover outer realities over which the network may be flung
so that ideal and real may coincide” (665).
33 We might conclude that in James’ text there is a precise and clear distinction between
empirical and logical levels. Are we to deduce that Wittgenstein’s critique is not justified?
Things are not as simple as they appear to be. As Myers (1986: 282) points out, in
distinguishing necessary truths from empirical facts, James did not mean to abandon a
naturalistic conception of science and of psychology as a science. Besides, these ideas are
necessarily true merely in a formal sense: it is only when they are confirmed by
experience that they can be said to be true in the proper sense; they should be regarded,
then, as “empirical hypotheses.”46 The primacy of the scientific point of view is not
dismissed, and the distinction between necessary truths and the effects of experience is
made within the scientific, naturalistic framework.47
34 This is not a framework that Wittgenstein could share. In an even more pregnant sense,
Wittgenstein’s critique of the confusion between the grammatical and the empirical can
be read as a critique of the confusion between philosophy and science.

4. Philosophy and Science


35 It is probably also (if not only)48 against James’ scientific attitude that Wittgenstein’s
numerous remarks about the importance, in philosophy, to refuse explanation and
embrace description, are directed. Indeed, in Manuscripts 130 and 131 (1946, partly
published in RPP), which contain a large amount of notes about James’ psychology and
related themes, Wittgenstein repeatedly argues against causal explanations and
hypotheses and in favour of description of linguistic games.49
36 Yet some clarification is needed, in order to gain a more accurate account of James’
position. That James, at least at the beginning of his career, meant psychology as
scientific, there can be no doubt. As early as 1867, in a letter to his father, he wrote that
what he was thinking about, as his object of study, was “the border ground of physiology
and psychology, overlapping both.”50 In the opening of the PP (I: 5) he clearly affirms that
“the psychologist is forced to be something of a nerve-physiologist” and that he has “kept
close to the point of view of natural science throughout the book” (Preface: v). But this
confidence in science and in the possibility of a scientific psychology later vacillates, and
in the Epilogue of the BC, written only two years after the publication of the PP, he
confesses that “the natural-science assumptions with which we started are provisional
and revisable things” (401), that metaphysics is inevitable because “the only possible path
to understand [the relations of the known and the knower] lies through metaphysical
subtlety” (399); and, eventually, that “this is no science, it is only the hope of a science.”
These very words testify, in a sense, that the perspective has not changed: the idea of
making psychology a science is still there, though only as a “hope.” In the same year
(1982), in fact, replying to George T. Ladd’s critical review of the PP, he remarked that
psychology, in order to be scientific, had to be kept separate from metaphysics51 and
defended the explanatory point of view. As Perry (1935: II, 119) puts it, “this controversy
establishes beyond any doubt the fact that James was looking for a psychology that
explained,” and particularly that explained scientifically the connections between mind
and body.

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 11

37 On the other hand, the impossibility of keeping philosophy and science independent from
one another is clear to James, and this is an aspect of the breadth and depth that
distinguishes his approach:
The popular notion that ‘Science’ is forced on the mind ab extra, and that our
interests have nothing to do with its constructions, is utterly absurd. The craving to
believe that the things of the world belong to kinds which are related by inward
rationality together, is the parent of Science as well as of sentimental philosophy;
and the original investigator always preserves a healthy sense of how plastic the
materials are in his hands.52
38 James did not put science on a pedestal, on the contrary, he often relativized its power
and its claims in respects to other modes of knowledge. This attitude parallels his way of
conceiving rationality: reason is not separate from feeling,53 it springs from feeling, and
again the continuum that characterizes human nature supports an anti-dichotomic
stance. James’ aim, then, can be better described as that of keeping science and
philosophy distinct, but not separate. It is this commitment that allows him to hold a
naturalistic viewpoint, and at the same time to give space to philosophy and metaphysics,
in a fallibilistic and anti-dogmatic spirit54 that Wittgenstein probably failed to see.
39 Goodman (2002: 71) affirms that the later Wittgenstein, too, was moving in James’
empiricist direction, in recognizing the contingency of language and in stressing the
importance of human natural history,55 but that at the same time he preserved the
distinction between concepts and experiences, which James did not. Actually,
Wittgenstein’s alleged empiricism is not so self-evident, particularly in his later writings.
Sometimes he had his doubts about natural history itself, and sometimes he even
explicitly stated that he did not mean to do natural history. 56 What is clear, is that he
retained James’ defense of the contiguity between science and philosophy as heralding
conceptual confusion, and James as unconsciously struggling with metaphysics:
Philosophical investigations: conceptual investigations. The essential thing about
metaphysics: that the difference between factual and conceptual investigations is
not clear to it. A metaphysical question is always in appearance a factual one,
although the problem is a conceptual one.57
40 How needed is the work of philosophy is shown by James’ psychology. Psychology, he
says, is a science, but he discusses almost no scientific questions. His movements, are
merely (so many) attempts to extricate himself from the cobwebs of metaphysics in
which he is caught. He cannot yet walk, or fly at all, he only wiggles [this sentence is in
English in the original text]. Not that that isn’t interesting. Only, it is not a scientific
activity.58
41 Yet James was not so unaware of the metaphysical side of his work, and was not so far
from a wittgensteinian perspective when he affirmed that “rightly understood,
[metaphysics] means only the search for clearness where common people do not even
suspect that there is any lack of it.”59 Moreover, he generally considered metaphysics as a
vision of the world or a set of beliefs, which could and should be deliberately chosen,
primarily because of their practical and ethical consequences.60 A complete account of the
two philosophers’ conceptions of metaphysics is, of course, beyond the scope of this
paper. It is nonetheless apparent that the different meaning and value that they assign to
metaphysics is one of the reasons why it is difficult to compare their attitudes towards
the relation between the empirical and the conceptual, science and philosophy.

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 12

42 One last remark on this topic is suggested by the phenomenological readings of the PP, 61
which often underline James’ progressive awareness of the weakness of science and his
deepening the metaphysical side of the inquiry. Wilshire (1968: 16) particularly focuses on
how James’ early project is wrecked because the scientific side of his researches is partly
overwhelmed by a sort of protophenomenology; but James’ desire to remain faithful to
his naturalistic project prevents him from fully developing his phenomenological
investigations (202). Now, we may ask, would phenomenology – or radical empiricism –
meet Wittgenstein’s demands? This is doubtful. It is indeed in the overcoming of
phenomenology, that Wittgenstein’s conception of grammar takes shape in the Thirties,62
and this step is never disowned in later years.
43 The point, which can only be roughly sketched here, is that the task of philosophy,
according to Wittgenstein, is somehow indirect. By describing linguistic games, it guides
our attention towards the background that sustains them. The method of perspicuous
presentation allows us to perceive the surroundings which define our linguistic practices
and the form of life within which they take place. It is here that we reach the bedrock
where “the spade is turned,”63 the subtle but always existing border between rules and
moves of the game, or, to get back to our metaphor, the banks and the river-bed of our
thoughts. To show these limits, in Wittgenstein’s perspective, is no task for any sort of
science, nor for any philosophical system as traditionally conceived.

Conclusion
44 Our aim was to show the possibility of comparing James’ stream of thought and
Wittgenstein’s river-bed of thoughts and to read the latter as an implicit comment on the
former. The analysis of some notes belonging to Wittgenstein’s Nachlass has proven that
there can be an effective connection between the two images. Wittgenstein’s river in an
implicit critique of James’ stream, and at the same time an insightful interpretation of the
virtues of that image, which James himself did not see. This is an example of
Wittgenstein’s general attitude towards James: he considered some of his intuitions as
brilliant, but in the main could not agree with him on the explicit formulation of his
ideas. Our inquiry has led us to deepen the analysis of James’ characterization of the
stream of thought and this, in turn, has widened our investigation to the topic of the
relation between science and philosophy. Wittgenstein held that James, in his attempts to
be scientific, often lost sight of the richness of his philosophical remarks, and confused
the two levels. The metaphor of the river-bed of thoughts, then, in its insistence on the
distinction between what is empirical and what is logical, also constitutes a warning
against the confusion between science and philosophy. James’ own treatment of this
matter is, we have argued, more complex than what it appeared to Wittgenstein’s eyes.
The latter fails to acknowledge the density and the ethical implications of James’
approach. Yet, Wittgenstein hits the mark in his underlying that James’ characterization
of the stream of thought lacks a conceptual vision of the relation between thought and its
rules, and of the embeddedness of these rules in the wider context of our form of life with
its linguistic practices. A fully pragmatist stance, one could say; save for Wittgenstein’s
negative attitude towards science, which marks the distance with respects not only to
James,64 but, probably, to pragmatism in general. In any case, this is a topic for a much
wider analysis, for which this paper can constitute only a hint.

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 13

BIBLIOGRAPHY
BAILEY A., (1999), “Beyond the Fringe. James on the Transitional Parts of the Stream of
Consciousness,” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6 (2-3), 141-53.

BONCOMPAGNI A., (2012a), Wittgenstein. Lo sguardo e il limite, Milano, Mimesis.

BONCOMPAGNI A., (2012b), “‘The Mother-Tongue of Thought’: James and Wittgenstein on Common
Sense,” Cognitio – Revista de Filosofia, 13 (2).

CALCATERRA R. M., (2008), “Truth in Progress: The Value of the Facts-and-Feelings Connection in
William James,” in Flamm M. C., Lachs J. & Skowroñski K. P., (ed.), American and European Values:
Contemporary Philosophical Perspectives, Newcastle-upon-Tyne, Cambridge Scholars Press.

CALCATERRA R. M., (2010), “Mente e natura tra metafisica ed epistemologia,” in Bufalo R.,
Cantarano G. & Colonnello P., (ed.), Natura storia società. Saggi in onore di Mario Alcaro, Milano-
Udine, Mimesis.

CHAUVIRÉ C., (2003), Voire le visible: la seconde philosophie de Wittgenstein, Paris, Presses
Universitaires de France.

COLIVA A., (2010), Moore and Wittgenstein. Skepticism, Certainty and Common Sense, Basingstoke,
Macmillan.

CROSBY D. A. & W. VINEY, (1995), “Toward a Psychology that is Radically Empirical: Recapturing
the Vision of William James,” in Donnelly M. E. (ed.), Reinterpreting the Legacy of William James,
Washington DC, American Psychological Association.

EDIE J., (1987), William James and Phenomenology, Bloomington, Indiana University Press.

EGIDI R., (1995), “Wittgenstein between Philosophical Grammar and Psychology,” in Egidi R., (ed.),
Wittgenstein: Mind and Language, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers.

FAIRBANKS M., (1966), “Wittgenstein and James,” The New Scholasticism, XL (3).

FLANAGAN O., (1997), “Consciousness as a Pragmatist Views It,” in Putnam R. A., (ed.), The
Cambridge Companion to William James, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

GALE R. M., (1999), The Divided Self of William James, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

GIORGI A., (1990), “The Implications of James’ Plea for Psychology as a Natural Science,” in
Johnson M. G. & Henley T. B., (eds.), Reflections on the Principles of Psychology, Hillsdale, NJ,
Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

GOODMAN R., (2002), Wittgenstein and William James, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

HACKER P. M. S., (1990), Wittgenstein. Meaning and Mind (An Analytical Commentary on the PI, vol. 3),
Oxford, Blackwell.

HACKER P. M. S., (1996), Wittgenstein. Mind and Will (An Analytical Commentary on the PI, vol. 4),
Oxford, Blackwell.

HILMY S. S., (1987), The Later Wittgenstein, Oxford, Blackwell.

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 14

JACKMAN H., (2004), “Wittgenstein & James’ Stream of Thought,” Saap 2004 Annual Meeting, [
ytorku.ca/hjackman/papers/WittJames.pdf].

JAMES W., (1884), “On Some Omissions of Introspective Psychology,” Mind, 9 (33).

JAMES W., (1890), The Principles of Psychology (PP), New York, Holt.

JAMES W., (1892/1984), Psychology: Briefer Course (BC), Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press.

JAMES W., (1897), The Will to Believe and other Essays in Popular Philosophy, New York, Longmans,
Green and Co.

JAMES W., (1907) Pragmatism (P), New York, Longmans, Green and Co.

JAMES W., (1912), Essays in Radical Empiricism (RE), New York, Longmans, Green and Co.

MYERS G. E., (1986), William James. His life and Character, New Haven, Yale University Press.

MONK R., (1991), Wittgenstein. The Duty of Genius, London, Vintage.

MOORE G. E., (1925/1959a), “A Defense of Common Sense,” in Philosophical Papers, 1959, New York,
Macmillan.

MOORE G. E., (1939/1959b), “Proof of an External World,” in Philosophical Papers, 1959, New York,
Macmillan.

MOYAL-SHARROCK D., (2003), “Logic in Action: Wittgenstein’s Logical Pragmatism and the
Impotence of Skepticism,” Philosophical Investigations, XXVI.

MOYAL-SHARROCK D., (2007), Understanding Wittgenstein’s On Certainty, Basingstoke, Macmillan.

NUBIOLA J., (2000), “Ludwig Wittgenstein and William James,” Streams of William James, 2 (3).

PASSMORE J., (1966), A Hundred Years of Philosophy, London, Duckworth.

PERISSINOTTO L., (1991), Logica e immagine del mondo. Studio su Über Gewissheit, Milano, Guerini.

PERRY R. B., (1935), The Thought and Character of William James, Boston, Little, Brown and Co. (2vv.).

PERRY R. B., (1958), In the Spirit of William James, Bloomington, Indiana University Press.

SCHUETZ A., (1941), “William James’ Concept of the Stream of Thought Phenomenologically
Interpreted,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 1 (4).

SCHULTE J., (1995), “Emotions: Remarks on Wittgenstein and William James,” in Egidi R., (ed.),
Wittgenstein: Mind and Language, Dordrecht, Kluwer Academic Publishers.

SHINER R. A., (1974) “Wittgenstein and Heraclitus: Two River-Images,” Philosophy, 49.

STEINER P., (2012), “Une question du point de vue. James, Husserl, Wittgenstein et le sophisme du
psychologue,” Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 1 (259).

STERN D. G., (1991), “Heraclitus and Wittgenstein’s River Images: Stepping Twice Into the Same
River,” The Monist, 74 (4).

STROLL A., (1994), Moore and Wittgenstein on Certainty, Oxford, Oxford University Press.

TER HARK M., (2004), “‘Patterns of Life’: a Third Wittgenstein Concept,” in Moyal Sharrock D., (ed.),
The Third Wittgenstein: The Post-Investigations Works, Adershot, Ashgate.

WERTZ S. K., (1972), “On Wittgenstein and James,” The New Scholasticism, XLVI (4).

WILSHIRE B., (1968), William James and Phenomenology: a Study of ‘The Principles of Psychology,’
Bloomington, Indiana University Press.

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 15

WITTGENSTEIN L., (1967), Zettel, Oxford, Blackwell.

WITTGENSTEIN L., (1969), On Certainty (OC), Oxford, Blackwell.

WITTGENSTEIN L., (1974), Letters to Russell, Keynes and Moore, edited by G. H. von Wright, Oxford,
Blackwell.

WITTGENSTEIN L., (1975), Philosophical Remarks (PR), Oxford, Blackwell.

WITTGENSTEIN L., (1977), Remarks on Colour (RC), Oxford, Blackwell.

WITTGENSTEIN L., (1980), Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology (RPP), Oxford, Blackwell.

WITTGENSTEIN L., (1981), Personal Recollections, edited by R. Rhees, Oxford, Blackwell.

WITTGENSTEIN L., (1988), Wittgenstein’s Lectures on Philosophical Psychology, edited by P. T. Geach,


Brighton, Harvester.

WITTGENSTEIN L., (2000), Wittgenstein’s Nachlass. The Bergen Electronic Edition (BEE), Oxford, Oxford
University Press.

WITTGENSTEIN L., (2001), Philosophical Investigations (PI), Oxford, Blackwell.

NOTES
1. Wittgenstein (1974: 10, 82).
2. Wittgenstein (1981: 121).
3. Hereafter, I will mention James’ and Wittgenstein’s major works by initials; see the
bibliography for details.
4. Goodman (2002: 17).
5. Monk (1991: 477).
6. Wittgenstein 1988.
7. Ter Hark (2004: 131, 137), Goodman (2002: 113), Schulte 1995.
8. Passmore (1966: 434), Fairbanks 1966, Wertz 1972.
9. Particularly in Hacker (1990: ch. 2), Hacker (1996: ch. 4, 5, 6); cf. also Hilmy (1987: ch. 4, 6) and
Gale (1999: 165).
10. Hacker (1990: 305).
11. Nubiola 2000, Goodman (2002: 63 ff.), Jackman 2004.
12. Wittgenstein (1981: 121).
13. Steiner 2012 is an interesting exception.
14. PR: §§ 52-5, 88, 213.
15. RPP: II, §§ 415, 504; PI: part II, 184.
16. Cf. also Boncompagni (2012a: 47, 154).
17. I’m citing 165 before 129 because 165 precedes 129 chronologically.
18. BEE, Items 114, 212, 302.
19. BEE, Item 176.
20. Hacker (1996: 476) affirms that Wittgenstein comments on James’ conception of the stream of
thought only in Manuscripts 124 and 129, and that in both cases he accuses him of conflating a
priori and a posteriori; as we shall see, there are a few more occasions in which James’ stream is
cited and a more complete analysis can show that it was not only with a critical eye that he
looked at this image.
21. “Ist der Gedankenstrom unterbrochen, so können wir nur vermuten, wie er weitergelaufen
wäre” (BEE: Item 120, 97r). I transcribe the original German version only for those parts of the

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 16

manuscripts which strictly relate to the stream of thought. Translations from the Nachlass are
mine, unless differently specified.
22. “Hier könnte vom Gedankenstrom, von dem James redet, gesprochen werden und man
könnte darauf hinweisen daß, so wie einmir wohlbekannter Name genannt wird, meine
Gedanken sich gleich in eine Reihe von Kanäle ergießen und in ihnen weiterlaufen und daß die
Bedeutung des Namens sich in diesen Strömen offenbart” (BEE: Item 124, 235).
23. “Ich erwarte zwei Leute A und B. Ich sage: “Wenn er doch nur käme!” Jemand fragt mich.
“Wen meist Du?” Ich sage, “Ich habe an den A gedacht.” Und diese Worte selber haben eine
Brücke hergestellt. Oder er fragt “Wen meinst Du” und ich antworte: “Ich habe an… gedacht,” ein
Gedicht in dem dieser Satz vorkommt. Die Verbindungen dessen was ich sage mache ich im Laufe
meiner Gedanken und Handlungen. (Diese Betrachtung hängt mit dem zusammen was W. James
“the stream of thought nennt.” Den Fehler in seiner Darstellung ist daß a priori und a posteriori
grammatisches und erfahrungsgemäßes durcheinander nicht unterschieden werden So redet er
von der Kontinuität des Gedankestroms und vergleicht sie mit der des Raums, nicht mit der eines
Wasserstrahles etwa.)” (BEE, Item 165: 24-5).
24. “(Ich glaube, diese Betrachtung hängt mit dem zusammen, was W. James “the stream of
thought” nennt. Wenn er freilich auch a priori und a posteriori, Erfahrungssätze und
grammatische, nicht unterschiedet)” (BEE: Item 129, 107).
25. “Man könnte sagen: Ich hätte keinen Eindruck von dem Zimmer als ganzes, könnte ich nicht
meinen Blick schnell in ihm dahin und dorthin schweifen lassen und mich nicht frei in ihm
herumbewegen. (Stream of thought) James” (BEE, Item 129: 114).
26. Goodman (2002: ch. 5).
27. Goodman (2002: 106), Gale (1999: 165).
28. Boncompagni (2012a: 106).
29. RPP: II, § 504; Steiner 2012. James will also speak of the flux of life in subsequent writings (see
for example RE: 93). The context is evidently different, but there are also some similarities. On
the continuity of James’ thought between the two works, see Crosby & Viney 1992; on the
discontinuity, Myers (1986: 78-80).
30. This paragraph, if read together with James’ characterization of psychology in the Epilogue of
the BC, really sounds like a comment on James’ words. Wittgenstein indeed says that “the
confusion and barrenness of psychology is not to be explained by calling it a ‘young science’; its
state is not comparable with that of physics, for instance in its beginnings” (PI: part II, 197); and
James had written that “at present psychology is in the condition of physics before Galileo and
the laws of motion, of chemistry before Lavoisier and the notion that mass is preserved in all
reactions” (BC: 401).
31. Wittgenstein (1988: 245; see also 92 and 205; and RPP: I, §§ 46, 173, 549; II §§ 214, 264, 321).
32. “I am inclined to believe that not everything that has the form of an empirical proposition is
one”: OC § 308 (emphasis in the original). Cf. also §§ 136, 319, 321, 401-2, 494, 569.
33. In Moore 1959b, originally published in 1939. Cf. OC: § 1. Wittgenstein’s remarks also refer to
Moore 1959a, originally published in 1925.
34. Moyal-Sharrock 2003.
35. In this distinction Stroll (1994: ch. 9) grounds what he calls Wittgenstein’s “heterogonous
foundationalism”: certainty can constitute a foundation for knowledge because it is not part of
knowledge.
36. James’ account of common sense (P: Lecture V), though presenting some affinities with
Wittgenstein’s approach, is much more similar to Moore’s, particularly in considering common
sense as a set of pieces of knowledge. Cf. Boncompagni 2012b.
37. Cf. Perissinotto (1991: 173 ff.).
38. There are many remarks on this in OC, the most striking of which is § 286.

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 17

39. BEE: Item 110, 34; see also pp. 39 and 155, and Items 116: 226; 120: 50v; 142: 116. The
proposition about metaphysics appears also in PI: I, § 116.
40. Interestingly, the previous formulation of James’ remark, contained in James (1884), is more
attuned with what critics consider the “true” Heraclitus, who spoke about a river which remains
the same with water which flows and changes; James (1884: 11) indeed stated that “of the mental
river the saying of Herakleitos is probably literally true: we never bath twice in the same water
there.” On the interpretations of Heraclitus and the connected images of the river in
Wittgenstein, see Shiner 1974 and Stern 1991. Unfortunately none of the two acknowledges the
importance that James’ image may have had on Wittgenstein’s account.
41. Passmore (1966: 105 ff.). On the relation between the two thinkers see Perry (1935: II, ch.
LXXXVI).
42. Cf. Bailey (1999: 145).
43. PP: I, 106, 107, 113.
44. PP: II, 617.
45. Respectively p. 644 and 655 (emphasis in the original). On James’ different conceptions of
meaning in the PP and in other writings, cf. Myers (1986: 285).
46. Crosby & Viney (1992: 111).
47. For a non naturalistic account, see Flanagan 1997.
48. Hilmy (1987: 207).
49. BEE: Item 130, 35, 71-2 (RPP: I, 46), 218; Item 131, 56 (RPP: I, 257).
50. Perry (1935: I, 254).
51. Giorgi (1990: 69 ff.).
52. PP: II, 667.
53. Cf. The Sentiment of Rationality, in James (1897: ch. 3).
54. Calcaterra (2008: 94 ff.).
55. PI: part I, § 415.
56. RPP: I, § 46; PI: part II, § XII; RC: part III, § 9.
57. RPP: I, § 949 (originally in MS 134: 153).
58. This remarks comes from the same Manuscript 165 (p. 150-1) in which is our first “stream
with no banks” occurrence. I am using, here, Hilmly’s (1987: 196-7) translation.
59. In a letter dated 1888 to the positivist psychologist Ribot, cited in Edie (1987: ix) and in Perry
(1958: 58).
60. For example in James (1897: ch. 1).
61. Schuezt 1941, Wilshire 1968, Edie 1987.
62. Cf. Egidi (1995: 174) and Chauviré (2003: 20).
63. PI: § 217.
64. Goodman (2002: 30) too considers the attitude towards science as one of the big differences
between the two thinkers.

ABSTRACTS
The influence of William James on Ludwig Wittgenstein has been widely studied, as well as the
criticism that the latter addresses to the former, but one aspect that has only rarely been focused
on is the two philosophers’ use of the image of the flux, stream, or river. The analysis of some

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012


Streams and River-Beds 18

notes belonging to Wittgenstein’s Nachlass support the possibility of a comparison between


James’ stream of thought, as outlined in the Principles of Psychology, and Wittgenstein’s river-bed
of thoughts, presented in On Certainty. After an introduction which offers a general frame for the
following work, the first section of the paper examines all the Nachlass entries that directly
mention James’ stream. Section 2 focuses on two remarks in which Wittgenstein explicitly
criticizes James’ concept and implicitly anticipates his own way of dealing with this matter.
These remarks, belonging to Manuscripts 165 and 129, both dating 1944, have not been published
in any of Wittgenstein’s edited books, nor is it possible to find the same argument elsewhere.
Wittgenstein’s critique concerns James’ lack of distinction between what is grammatical, or a
priori, and what is empirical, or a posteriori, a distinction which the image of the stream should
have suggested: a stream flows in a stream-bed and within banks. This is exactly the meaning
that Wittgenstein’s own metaphor of the river-bed of thoughts is intended to convey. Section 3
analyses James’ concept of the stream and its corollaries, in order to clarify whether
Wittgenstein’s critique is justified or not. James in effect draws a separation between a priori and
a posteriori, but this separation is conceived from within the framework of empirical science.
This analysis leads to the theme of the relations among science, philosophy and metaphysics,
which is the subject of section 4. The conclusion is that Wittgenstein did appreciate James for his
intuitions and for the power of his imagination: in a sense he even developed them; but he could
not agree on the explicit formulation of his ideas.

AUTHOR
ANNA BOCOMPAGNI
Università di Roma Tre
anna.boncompagni[at]uniroma3.it

European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen