Sie sind auf Seite 1von 20

Human Architecture: Journal of the Sociology of Self-

Knowledge
Volume 2
Article 14
Issue 1 Social Theories, Student Realities

2003

Marx, Gurdjieff, and Mannheim: Contested


Utopistics of Self and Society in a World-History
Context
Mohammad H. Tamdgidi
SUNY Binghamton, mohammad.tamdgidi@umb.edu

Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.umb.edu/humanarchitecture


Part of the Theory, Knowledge and Science Commons

Recommended Citation
Tamdgidi, Mohammad H. (2003) "Marx, Gurdjieff, and Mannheim: Contested Utopistics of Self and Society in a World-History
Context," Human Architecture: Journal of the Sociology of Self-Knowledge: Vol. 2 : Iss. 1 , Article 14.
Available at: http://scholarworks.umb.edu/humanarchitecture/vol2/iss1/14

This Article is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks at UMass Boston. It has been accepted for inclusion in Human Architecture:
Journal of the Sociology of Self-Knowledge by an authorized editor of ScholarWorks at UMass Boston. For more information, please contact
library.uasc@umb.edu.
HUMAN ARCHITECTURE: JOURNAL OF THE SOCIOLOGY OF SELF-KNOWLEDGE
A Publication of the Omar Khayyam Center for Integrative Research in Utopia, Mysticism, and Science (Utopystics)
Vol. II, No. 1, Spring 2003.
ISSN: 1540-5699. © Copyright by Ahead Publishing House (imprint: Okcir Press). All Rights Reserved.
HUMAN
ARCHITECTURE
Journal of the Sociology of Self-

allowed me to problematize and historicize


the taken-for-granted notion of “contesta-
tion” itself, questioning whether identities
have to be contested, even if they have un-
doubtedly been so, throughout millennia.
In what follows I will try to share with
Marx, Gurdjieff, and you in outline the argument advanced in
my dissertation research titled “Mysticism
Mannheim: and Utopia: Towards the Sociology of Self-
Knowledge and Human Architecture”
Contested Utopistics of Self (Tamdgidi 2002). Therein, I have explored
the utopistic theories of Karl Marx, G. I.
and Society in a World- Gurdjieff, and Karl Mannheim as contested
History Context1 efforts towards the good life in self and so-
ciety within a world-historical framework.
I argue that the three approaches—repre-
senting western utopian, eastern mystical,
and academic movements—are fragment-
M.H. (Behrooz) Tamdgidi ed microcosms of an otherwise singular
creative human search for the good life.
–––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– Their mutual alienations, I argue, are root-
This presentation is more an exercise in ed in fragmented philosophical, religious,
theorizing history (in this case the dialectics and scientific ideologies which have
of world-history and utopistic praxis) than emerged in conjunction with the broad his-
in historiography, though I am not sure if torical transitions of ancient civilizations to
the two can really be separated and dual- classical political, medieval cultural, and
ized as such. My concern here is with con- modern economic empires. Human archi-
tested identities (in a world-history tecture and the sociology of self-knowledge
context) of not just who we are, but who we are then introduced as creative conceptual,
can and should be. What attracted me to curricular, and pedagogical efforts beyond
this panel topic was in fact the ways in the contested terrains of fragmented uto-
which it could accommodate comparative pistics in favor of a just global society.
and cross-disciplinary discourses of self “Utopistics” is a term recently coined
and world on one hand and theory and by Immanuel Wallerstein denoting “the se-
practice on the other. Above all, however, rious assessment of historical alternatives,
from the standpoint of my applied socio- the exercise of our judgment as to the sub-
logical interest in comparative utopistics, it stantive rationality of alternative possible
historical systems. It is the sober, rational,
1.An earlier version of this paper was pre- and realistic evaluation of human social
sented to a gathering of sociology faculty at systems, the constraints on what they can
UMass Boston in March 2003. I’d like to take this be, and the zones open to human creativity.
moment to thank them all for their support. The
present paper is a revised version presented to Not the face of the perfect (and inevitable)
the “Contested Identities in a World-History future, but the face of an alternative, credi-
Context” panel of the World History Association bly better, and historically possible (but far
Conference, held June 26-29, 2003, at Georgia
State University, Atlanta, Georgia. I would like from certain) future. It is thus an exercise si-
to thank Fakhri Haghani, the organizer and multaneously in science, politics, and mo-
chair of the panel for making it possible for me rality” (1998a 1-2). I use the concept with
to share this brief summary of my dissertation
research with a broader audience. certain important qualifications, however.

Notice: Copyright of Human Architecture: Journal of the Sociology of Self-Knowledge is the property of Ahead Publishing House
(imprint: Okcir Press) and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright
holder’s express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.

102
First, utopistics in my view must simulta- happy when underclasses are not. In other
neously deal with macro and micro pro- words, the implicit value-judgments of our
cesses, with broad structural concerns as stratification theories, including those of
well as everyday interactive issues. Second, oppositional ideologies as advanced by
it must eschew ethnocentrism and actively Marx, is that somehow being upper-class
embrace comparative approaches across equates with happiness and being lower-
cultural traditions. Third, it must involve class does not—hence, the struggle to over-
both rigorous assessment and actual appli- throw one type of class privilege (private
cation. Utopistics, in my view, is the com- property) in favor of another type of class
parative applied sociology (or privilege (collective property as owned by
historiography—reflective and creative) of the victorious proletariat), in the hope that
the good life—of realistic seeking of opti- the latter will eventually lead to the disap-
mally better selves, persons, communities, pearance of class distinctions in general in
and worlds. The utopistic approach to ap- the course of a transition under the dicta-
plying sociology moves beyond either the torship of the proletariat. The underlying
mainstream or merely oppositional/anti- assumption of such a stratification theory
systemic modes of resolving concrete ev- of liberation, therefore, is that we need to
eryday problems; it seeks positive self and change the form of property ownership
social change by the example of its alterna- (from individual and private to social and
tive methodological, theoretical, practical, public) in order to rid society of the ills of
and inspirational innovations and solu- class division. What is problematized, in
tions. other words, is not the “possessive” atti-
My purpose here is to use Marx, Gurd- tude towards things, material or otherwise,
jieff, and Mannheim as representative in the first place. When a Native American
doors for entering the stratified building says, for instance, “Earth does not belong to
rooms of theories we have inherited from us, we belong to earth,” he or she is not con-
modern or traditional, western or eastern, trasting private with public property, but
spacetimes, critically assessing their useful- questioning the very possessive attitude of
ness in helping us effectively move beyond humanity towards things, individual or
our inner and broader social contestations collective—in this case towards the whole
and alienations in favor of the good life. I of nature and earth. Conversely, however,
will conclude with my translation of anoth- Marx’s “Workers of the World, Unite! You
er representative example from the mysti- have nothing to lose but your chains, but
cal poetry of Rumi with a brief note on his you have a world to win!” still carries the
poetic utopistics in a world-historical con- message that the goal is to possess the
text—one in which the audience is simulta- world albeit collectively, NOT to become
neously one’s own selves, the face-to-face free from possessiveness itself—as Fromm
“others,” and all future (and in remem- or Adorno would suggest, liberating our-
brance all past) human generations. selves from the “have” attitude towards
things in favor of the “being” attitude,
I away from the fetishism of things, from be-
ing habituated and attached to things, from
being dominated and controlled by things.
I begin my reflections on Marx’s theo-
Marx may have espoused a challenge to the
ries of social stratification and revolution
bourgeois form of materialism and proper-
with the perceived stereotyped assump-
ty ownership, but his proletarian material-
tions some carry, in the context of a deeply
ism, apart from the latter’s philosophical
materialistic culture, that upper classes are
content, still shared with the bourgeoisie

103
the notion that human happiness involves retical framework was in all its three politi-
primarily material wants, and that human cal, economic, and philosophical
liberation ultimately originates from and components. I have argued that the thesis
must be guided by a concern for material of the dictatorship of the proletariat is in-
interests and objectives. Marxism, after all, herently a contradiction in terms, since the
was a western artifact. propertyless class that assumes political su-
Marx’s mature theory of stratification premacy inherently metamorphises into a
and revolution is based on an assumed du- collectively property owning class whose
alized and stratified primacy of nature over characteristics cannot be, as even predicat-
humankind, of economy and politics over ed by the theoretical framework of Marx’s
culture, of matter over mind, of material- own historical materialism, the same as the
ism over idealism. The dualistic framework pre-revolutionary class. Note here that I am
of these oppositions are strongly present in not arguing for the historical contingency
the mature Marx (a distinction between of a misguided or degenerated proletariat
mature and young Marx is necessary of in Soviet Union, China, or elsewhere, but I
course, for the young Marx, influenced by am saying that the very theory of a prole-
Hegel, believed that the solution lies in nei- tarian dictatorship is inherently a contra-
ther materialism nor idealism, but in a hu- diction in terms and thereby flawed. The
manism which sees humanity as part of proletariat that assumes, in part or even as
nature, endowed with its powers). If mind an ideally international whole, political su-
was seen as a part of matter without any premacy and collective ownership of the
predetermination attached to the latter as- social means of production cannot by defi-
pect, then we may have found education, nition remain a propertyless, hence a prole-
literature, or poetry to have been at least as tarian class.
significant a weapon to wage the war for On the economic front, I have also ar-
the good life as the weapon of the arms. The gued that the very formulaic representation
most troubling aspect of Marx’s theory of of Marx’s theory of the falling general rate
stratification and de-stratification (through of profit in capitalism is a demonstration of
the agency of a revolutionary proletariat) the fact that the transition from capitalism
was its self-fulfilling prophetic logic which to socialism or communism can never be a
played into the hands of a materialistic purely economic act and thus objectively
bourgeoisie which equated material pos- inevitable, but cultural and political self-
sessions (albeit in collective ownership) awareness and organization of all classes,
with the human liberative agenda. That hu- including the revolutionary class, are
man liberation inherently is about libera- equally (if not more) important factors that
tion from unconscious attachment to things, can determine whether or not a transition
ideas, feelings, sensations, relations, and will take place at all. Culture is not a super-
processes, that human liberation is about structure flying overhead, but actually a
the power of the mind over matter, of intel- potentially determining material produc-
ligence and rational self-knowledge and tive force. The mechanistic “laws of motion
determination over purely “material” in- of society” theorization of the inevitability
terests to possess things, was regrettably re- of transition built into Marx’s stratification
pressed in the transition from the young to and revolution theories, in other words, is
the old Marx. inherently flawed for it relegates such a
Through a critical revisitation of how possibility to the a priori and predeter-
Marx constructed his theory of social strat- mined forces of an objectively developing
ification and revolution, I have tried to economic agency.
show how inherently inconsistent his theo- The dualism of economy/politics vs.

104
culture, I further argue, was rooted in an- other floors. Culture and knowledge can-
other fatal inconsistency in Marx’s philo- not be economic and political forces, econo-
sophical arsenal, which has escaped the my cannot be a cultural artifact, and radical
gnawing teeth of even the most critical of revolution cannot be based on purely cul-
post- or ex-Marxists, i.e., the dualism of ide- tural, educational, or artistic strategies. In
alism vs. materialism. What I find quite the dissertation I have exhaustively decon-
perplexing in my autopsy of Marx, is that at structed this stratified architectural meta-
the very same time Marx and Engels were phor in Marx, still a common schema used
preoccupied with rescuing human social subconsciously in even non-Marxist social
imagination from mechanistics of formal scientific discourses, in the hope of a radical
Aristotelian logic espousing either/or ar- remodelling of our subconscious visual ar-
gumentations—favoring instead a dialecti- tifacts in favor of more humanistic architec-
cal logic of identity of opposites—they tural pursuits to bring about creative social
increasingly fell trapped in the argument change simultaneously in personal and
that dialectical method must itself be either world-historical spacetimes.
idealist or materialist. The primacy of mat- My self-critique of Marx’s theory is not
ter over mind can only thrive in the onto- of course to be interpreted as a reversion
logical environment of dualized matter/ back to mainstream sociological theories
mind conceptions, since otherwise, if mind and practice, not historically as a reversion
is seen as a part of matter, as a material back to the outdated modes of capitalist or-
force of specific nature and vibration itself, ganization of the workforce, but as an effort
then the predetermined and universal pri- to search for alternative methodological
macy of one over the other would become a and theoretical tools needed in favor of the
tautological argument. good life. The defeat of Marxist theory, as
I have much respect for Marx, and in Marx himself would have proclaimed in his
many ways, as he advised through Engels, political writings, is not a defeat of revolu-
to be fateful to him is not to be a Marxist, tion, but the defeat of our own shortcom-
i.e., not to be habituated to his thought and ings and hesitations in pursuing it. In this
methods as levers for construction of truth. case, the obstacles were hesitations to see
My critique of Marx is a self-critique in oneself and one’s own theories as being im-
more personal terms as pursued in more plicated in the social reality we try to
detailed in my dissertation. Time does not change for the better, an approach which
allow me to dwell more on this personal was inherently missing from Marx’s objec-
side or on my critical revisitation of Marx’s tivist, nineteenth century classical scientif-
theory of history, but what I like to convey ic, paradigm of social change. Marx’s era
here is the proposition that Marx’s sociolo- was one in which social science was still
gy of stratification based on which he con- emerging from the midst of philosophical
structed the edifice of his applied sociology argumentations. Being trained in philoso-
of revolution, was itself dualistic and strat- phy himself, Marx had a deep-seated pro-
ified. The very “building” or “three sto- pensity to approach his science of
reys” metaphor used by Marx to construct revolution from a philosophical point of
his “guiding thread” and revolutionary view, involving pre-conceived ideological
paradigm in terms of economic base and argumentations—of course packaged and
politico-legal and ideological superstruc- legitimated in a framework conducive to
tures was an inherently dualized architec- proletarian interests and revolutionary
tural construct. In such a metaphor, what projects. Despite Marx’s considerable con-
exists on one floor, say in the foundation, tributions to social science, at its roots his
cannot be at the very same time present in paradigm was a philosophically inspired

105
western utopian project. orists, especially the Critical Theorists of
Paradoxically, however, Marx’s drive the Frankfurt School filled significant gaps
to seek an “objective” and scientific frame- in Marxist theorizing about the self and so-
work to pursue utopistics was made at the cial psychology of revolution; however, it is
expense of the individual self-reflexiveness important to still note the difference be-
that has traditionally been, somewhat, the tween the sociologies and social pyscholo-
preoccupation of philosophical tradition, gies of others’ selves on one hand, and the
albeit in abstract forms. Society for Marx sciences of self-knowledge and self-change
was about interpersonal relations, while found elsewhere such as in the eastern cul-
the intrapersonal reality was seen at best as tural traditions.
an automatic product of the outer social re- To borrow and revise Marx’s eleventh
ality and conflicts. Social stratification was thesis on Feuerbach, “Marxists interpreted
perceived as that between assumed “indi- and/or changed the world in various ways;
viduals,” whereby each person could easily the point, however, is to begin with oneself.”
be boxed into this or that class, group, or
party, if not sitting between the chairs of II
major social classes—as in the case of the
petty-bourgeoisie. Marx’s view of society
Gurdjieff, a strange Caucasian mystic
was atomistic and Newtonian, not relativist
of the late nineteenth and early twentieth
and quantal, not based on relationality of
century, who has been acknowledged by Ja-
selves that cross skin boundaries of visible
cob Needleman, a specialist in religion
bodies. In his theory of stratification, it was
studies, to be one of the founding sources of
not possible as a matter of rule for the same
the so-called New Religious Movements of
person to belong to multiple class group-
the past century, had a lot to say, and theo-
ings. It was no wonder then that revolu-
rize, about the inner fragmentation of the
tionary change was sought primarily in
human psyche. He was an Ashokh (or Ash-
outer interpersonal relations only, and not
ikh/Ashegh, meaning lover, as Persian or
simultaneously in the intrapersonal class,
Azeri speakers know them in the region),
gender, race, and ethnic stratifications of
but extraordinarily trained with traditional
our selfhoods and psychologies. Such a the-
sciences of human psyche, skills of hypnot-
orization, of course, was predisposed to al-
ic conditioning, and also the arts of mysti-
low the possibility and necessity of social
cal dance and music. It is sad that we
change through violence, for economic, po-
academics sometimes allow “disciplined”
litical, or ideological powers could be more
vocabularies and labeling practices to ex-
or less easily boxed into separate persons
clude many non-academics from entering
who could raise and use arms against one
our theoretical and curricular rooms. Of
another. That the person could be simulta-
these limiting and fragmenting architectur-
neously a member of dominated and dom-
al practices in our educational landscapes I
inating classes, oppressor and oppressed,
will say more later. Here I would like to de-
discriminating and discriminated, etc.,
scribe how wrapped in all sorts of deliber-
would have required much more than wag-
ately constructed mystical sayings,
ing a ruthless struggle against the so-called
Gurdjieff’s theory of the self advocates
“other.” It would have involved serious
viewing human individuality not as an as-
preoccupations with self-reflectiveness and
sumption, but as a destination of the jour-
change within—would have involved seri-
ney of human life course. Calling humans
ous needs to theorize not only a sociology,
“three-brained beings,” he proposes a view
but a self-reflective social psychology of
of the person as an ensemble of hundreds if
revolution. It is certainly true that later the-

106
not thousand of selves, clustered around self inside for being its “true self,” letting
three main centers of gravity which he la- her or him in as a temporary master passen-
bels as physical, intellectual, and emotional ger, to be soon replaced by another tempo-
centers. The fragmentation of these centers rary will. In this contemporary so-called
via all sorts of buffers, or what modern psy- “man” in quotation marks, the self that sets
chology would label as “defense mecha- the clock at night to get up early in the
nisms,” coincides with the fragmentation morning is almost always not the self that
of human consciousness into its so-called actually gets up in the morning, but one
instinctive (or unconscious), waking con- who decides to shut the alarm and go back
scious, and subconscious realms, relatively to sleep again. No one knows who or what
separate and independent functioning of one really is.
which allows the possibility and propensi- Human alienation for Gurdjieff has a
ty of the organism to become habituated, practical and specific meaning, the separa-
addicted, and attached to things, to live in tion and the alienation of our multiple self-
illusion, to live in sleep in waking life, to be hoods from one another, such that the
a machine in human guise, to be a prisoner liberation of the organism must necessarily
of an illusively free life. involve conscious labor and intentional
Using the allegory of a carriage driven suffering of self-knowledge and transfor-
by a horse in which the box symbolizes the mation by a deliberately evoked and
body, driver the mind, the horse the emo- trained, fourth, observing self which is the
tions, and the passenger the master self seat of the future permanent and unified
supposedly in charge of the whole system, “I.” Only such a unified organism in which
Gurdjieff argues that the human organism the three centers actually communicate and
is often fragmented into a box broken down blend with one another really has the right
needing lots of greasing and repairs, the to say “I am” and “I do.” The ordinary hu-
driver mind being almost always sleepy man organism does not “do,” things are
and drunk, the emotional horse wild and simply done to her or him. In ordinary ev-
out of control with its constant desires for eryday life, we all are each “We”s. Multi-
food and sex, and the master passenger lit- plicities of selves are not merely maladies
erally absent from the scene altogether. The of extreme pathological conditions, but a
shafts connecting the physical box with the fact of everyday life for each and every one
emotional horse, the reins connecting the of us, its architecture varying across body
emotional horse to the driver mind, and the organisms depending on their make-up
brake lever connecting the driver mind to and degree of efforts made in self-knowl-
the physical box, symbolize for Gurdjieff edge and change. Gurdjieff’s enneagram of
three qualitatively different modes of com- 21 human personalities, overly misused
munication among the three centers of the and popularized today, is actually con-
organism—but these too are broken down structed to take account of the varied forms
and imbalanced, making the person power- of architecture of the inner landscape of
less to know and change her or his physical, selves. The sociologist George Herbert
intellectual, or emotional habits. The organ- Mead, of course, agreed that in a sense
ism has been originally designed for super- “multiple personalities” are normal. But
natural journeys, but is alas broken down the difference here is that for Gurdjieff there
traversing wasteful terrestrial byroads. The is no presumption that the internalized
interstellar transport system that is the hu- selfhoods automatically converge in adult-
man organism is actually so fragmented hood to form a unified individual self-iden-
and absent of singular, individual will, that tity. For Gurdjieff, actually the opposite
it confuses any passerby outside or passing happens as a rule, since the very process of

107
individuation requires the person’s own tions of our unified and singular
volition to pursue the task of alchemical individualities in favor of recognizing our
self-knowledge and change. We of course inner multiplicities, we may be able to form
all know those so-called “mood swings” a new definition of society not as a system
we encounter in our every day lives, moods of individual interactions, but as a system
which Gurdjieff would literally associate of interactions of multiple selves, products
with multiple selfhoods manifesting them- of our contradictory, fragmented, alienated,
selves according to the blind necessities of and stratified socializations, which once
everyday time and space. In this sense, of formed confront one another as fragment-
course, Gurdjieff’s eastern mysticism pre- ed selfhoods. As Mead has argued, once a
dicts much of modern sociologies of sym- self arises from the context of our socializa-
bolic interaction including those of Blumer tions, it takes a life of its own. There is no
and Mead, predates Goffman’s dramatur- reason why the “individual” must be our
gical theory of social life as a theater, and in assumed unit of analysis and point of de-
many ways predicts (and I would venture parture for defining society and social in-
to claim surpasses in all practicality of its teraction.
healing strategies) much of Freudian theo- If we adopt an alternative definitional
ries of the subconscious and modern psy- framework for society, and thereby of soci-
chology. Sadly, our eurocentric prisms ology as the study of it, many “social” phe-
often prevent us from acknowledging in nomena that appear as inexplicable become
our cherished academic disciplines the pio- rather easily understood. Our severely de-
neering work of non-westerns. pressive mood changes, the loving mothers
Gurdjieff’s mysticism, as I have under- who suddenly drawn their children in
stood it, and aside from its otherwise seri- bathtubs, the friendly but unexpectedly ho-
ous problems and contradictions which I micidal neighbors, the quiet kids who sud-
have also exhaustively identified in my dis- denly bomb their classrooms and schools,
sertation, has an important message for our are not exceptions to our supposedly singu-
applied and clinical theories of self and so- lar individualities, but extreme examples of
cial change. This importance is as much our common lot as clusters of multiple and
about the inner nature of stratification of fragmented selfhoods, caught in the illu-
our assumed and supposed “individuali- sive shell of our alleged individualities
ties” into multiple selfhoods, as it is about with the aid of equally illusive ideologies of
undermining the very textbook definitions individualism, but in reality living the life
we have about society, and thereby sociolo- of fragmented selfhoods easily manipulat-
gy as the study of society. Any sociology able by all kinds of advertising, television
textbook today defines society as a system sitcoms, mass media news, and glamour
of relationships or interactions among indi- and fashion industries, not to speak of af-
viduals, or groups of individuals. This flictions with all sorts of habituations to
would be like the early classical scientific food, money, fame, sex, power, wealth,
view of nature as a system of bodies, of drugs, alcohol, and nicotine substances.
molecules, or at best of atoms. But further Despite its ideological rhetoric, capitalism
insight, as we know, led us to a different does not individuate persons, but frag-
view of matter and of nature, as a system of ments them into landscapes of fragmented
subatomic elements and currents, which and alienated selfhoods, within and with-
established a drastically different view of out. Colonialisms do not have to always
the universe while subsuming the earlier take place at the macro level of nation-
atomistic view into itself. Likewise, by re- states and civilizations. Imperialism has
laxing our a prior and ahistorical assump- long discovered, as Michel Foucault has

108
aptly reminded us, of the micro and intrap- human social reality which needs to be crit-
ersonal industries of control and inner colo- icized in theory and revolutionized in prac-
nialism. “Divide and Rule” is not only tice.
useful in classical or neo-, or even post-co-
lonial geometries of nation-states. It also III
works in the micro geometries of divided
and controlled selfhoods. How can we be
Western utopistics is concerned with
singularly willful and indivisible “individ-
how to possess and control the world, be-
uals” but not be able even to drop our cof-
ing caught in cycles of strivings for private
fee drinking habits!?
and/or collective possession of its resourc-
It is the tragic story of modern human
es, cultural artifacts, and instruments of
organism to be caught in a world-wide col-
power. Eastern utopistics, however, in its
onized web of multiple selfhoods, intra, in-
mystical varieties in particular, problema-
ter, and extrapersonal, with respect to
tizes that very possessive attitude towards
oneself, to others, and to our natural and
worldly objects, positing that attachments
built environments. Gurdjieff’s theory, al-
to the world are not only the root causes of
beit its shortcomings and misuses suffered
all suffering, but also the impediments to
at the hands of its inventive guru, and de-
seeking and exercising knowledges that
spite its mystical religious wrappings
can alone facilitate human spiritual perfec-
and—as in most mystical teachings—de-
tion. Karl Mannheim, to whom I turn now,
pendent and hypnotic modalities of teach-
would perhaps argue that each of the above
er-student relationships, gives us an
provides only a one-sided perspective on
alternative, eastern, approach to utopistics.
how to pursue the good life, their rational
Where Gurdjieff fails is the separation and
kernels becoming more fruitful when syn-
the stratification he introduces between this
thesized integratively into optimally ratio-
inner realm of human life and that taking
nal formulations about the utopistics of self
place inter- and extrapersonally in relation-
and society. But, how can the utopistics of
ship to others and the environment. The in-
self and broader social world be forged into
terplay of the inner and broader, micro and
a singular theoretical framework?
macro, social stratifications of the human
In my study of Mannheim, I have tried
life is thereby ignored in his mystical para-
to revisit not only the contributions of Man-
digm. As in most religions, for Gurdjieff the
nheim’s sociology of knowledge, but also
suffering in the broader social life is a giv-
the self-defeating elements of his argu-
en, a fact and fate to be reckoned with as an
ments, in the hope of rescuing the essence
inevitability against which the human soul
of his invaluable insights regarding general
is to be tested, purified, and forged towards
conceptions of ideology and “collective un-
human inner salvation, in this world and in
conscious” as the fundamental problem of
the thereafter. As Marx focused on the
our age. The “social origins of knowledge”
broader sociality and lost sight of the inner
thesis built into Mannheim’s perspective,
sociality of human organism, Gurdjieff los-
which was rooted in Marx’s theory of mate-
es sight of the broader sociality and the role
rial determination of consciousness, can
it plays in the origination and perpetuation
only thrive in a conceptual and theoretical
of human inner fragmentations and alien-
environment where knowledge is divorced
ations. The self and the world are thereby
and separated from social existence. If we
themselves separated from one another in
say social existence determines our con-
their respective western and eastern doc-
sciousness, as stated the thesis of Man-
trines, each failing to notice and thereby to
nheim’s sociology of knowledge, this
rectify one or another side of the totality of

109
would turn tautological if we consider our ing personally self-reflective and thus self-
knowledge, our ideas, our culture, to be a transformative. His borrowed “detached
part and parcel of that social existence. The intellectuals” theorization was to be sure a
dualism of society and knowledge, there- self-defeating argument within a paradigm
fore, in contrast to a part/whole dialectical of “social origins of knowledge;” but I have
conception of them, allows a primacy to be argued that it did not have to be self-defeat-
attached with one rather than another as- ing in a more dialectical environment in
pect of the dichotomy. Hence, we have a so- which knowledge is as much the origin of
ciological perspective whereby we always self and social reality as it is its product.
seek to find the “social origins,” not recog- Theories of social stratification, if pursued
nizing that our own ideas, views, and cul- for their own sake, run the risk of becoming
tural artifacts may as well be the origins of self-fulfilling prophecies when applied to
old or new and alternative social arrange- everyday social problems and solution
ments. Although Berger and Luckmann’s strategies. Sociologists as intellectuals, in
notion of “social construction of reality” their teaching and research, no matter how
has become a commonsense sociological dedicated, may become embroiled so much
perspective nowadays, even then we shrug in interpreting, albeit critically, the strati-
from creative sociological theorizing and fied class, gender, race, and ethnic nature of
practice of alternative and utopistic social capitalist society, that they inadvertently
arrangements, big or small, under the pre- become a perpetuator of them and the be-
text of engagement in “scientific” study of lief that there is something to be gained by
facts and figures about the reality of our so- pursuing upward mobilities in either of its
cial stratifications. bourgeois or proletarian varieties. It will
Despite the above shortcomings, how- perhaps take some effort in the sociologies
ever, Mannheim made a great contribution not just of knowledge but of self-knowledge,
to the sociological theory of ideology, by in- on the part of the academics themselves,
troducing his what he called “general con- faculty or student, to realize that stratifica-
ception of ideology,” i.e., the notion that in tions of our inner and broader social lives
our socio-political discourses we become are two sides of the same coin tossed
increasingly aware that not only our adver- around by the Wall Street and Microsoft
saries, but even ourselves are unconscious- managers of the postmodern information
ly biased and thereby ideological. society.
Mannheim advanced the notion that the Social stratification is not simply about
problem of collective unconscious is the the amount of possessions or savings in
greatest challenge and obstacle in the path bank accounts. It is not a state of things, but
of scientific social knowledge and transfor- a relational process taking place without
mation. Thereby, by encouraging sociolo- and within. It is about the nature and qual-
gists and social scientists alike to turn their ity of our experiences as human beings. So-
gaze as well inward, he introduced a signif- cial and self stratifications cannot exist
icant self-reflexive element into utopistic apart from one another. To break the chain
theorizing and practice. Nevertheless, be- of our macro social structural slaveries, we
cause of his all-universal materialist theo- cannot jump over our own knees, so to
retical environment inherited from Marx, speak, but need to understand and practi-
his generally “objectivist” social scientific cally change the micro structural slaveries
framework, and also his eschewing of the shaping our everyday inner lives and psy-
individual as a unit of analysis (given his ches, here and now.
sociological training and bias) Mannheim
in effect disarmed the intellectual from be-

110
IV structural crisis of the modern world-sys-
tem of collective imperialism.
The contested theoretical identities of Pointing out that world-history has ex-
Marx, Gurdjieff, and Mannheim in search perienced not one, but two major renais-
of the good life, eastern or western, are not sances—during 600-400 BC and A.D. 1300-
isolated efforts in world-historical context. 1500—each of which followed a long and
On the contrary, as fragmented voices find- devastating process of nomadic invasions
ing their way into our contemporary imag- of the south marking respectively the fall of
inations they encapsulate the three broad ancient civilizations and the rise of modern
world-historical movements of western economic imperialism, I have argued that
utopianism, eastern mysticism, and the ac- the settled-nomadic dialectic in fact lies at
ademia. Using a nonreductive dialectical the root not only of the north-south, but
conception of world-history in contrast to also of the east-west, nomenclature in
the conceptions espoused respectively by world-historical discourse. The by and
Marx, Gurdjieff, and Mannheim, I have large failing eastern and western renais-
tried to construct an alternative view of sances signified conscious and intentional
world-history as a grand human architec- human efforts at integrating the fragment-
tural project of building inner and global ed philosophical, religious, and scientific
human harmony. World-history is viewed dimensions of human creativity which
as a long-term and large-scale process of emerged after the fall of ancient civiliza-
splitting of the intra- and inter/extraper- tions and reinforced by classical, medieval,
sonal realms of human life into a habituat- and modern empires. This fragmentation
ed eastern vs. western civilizational has essentially involved and perpetuated a
dualism whose transcendence has been, dualistic spatiotemporal distanciation of
and will necessarily be, dependent upon the intra- and inter/extrapersonal dimen-
conscious and intentional creative human sion of social knowledge and transforma-
effort. World-history is conceptualized as a tion, manifested in the lop-sided
process of nomadization, ruralization, ur- emergence of oppositional utopian, mysti-
banization, and subsequent rise and disin- cal, and academic traditions in humanist
tegration (partly as a result of the first utopistics. The structural crisis of the mod-
major, Indo-European, nomadic invasions ern world-system involves both the self-de-
of the south) of ancient civilizations, fol- structive tendency of collective
lowed by a long era of imperial reintegra- imperialism and the potentially self-trans-
tions of the world through increasingly forming power vested in human creative
synchronous periods of classical political powers to invent new humanist renais-
domination, medieval cultural conversion, sances on a global scale capable of critically
and ultimately modern economic exploita- reintegrating the lopsided utopian, mysti-
tion for which the second major (central cal, and academic fragments of humanist
Asian and north European) nomadic inva- utopistics in search of alternative self and
sions paved the way. The modern world- broader social systemicities in the midst of
system is a result not only of the ascen- the existing order, here and now. In the
dance of an economic form of imperial inte- world-historical dialectics of eastern mysti-
gration of the world, but of the invention of cal and western utopian traditions, aca-
a new phenomenon in world-history which demia has played a determining role—for
may best be characterized as “collective im- better or worse. The failed renaissances of
perialism.” Postmodernity and globaliza- the past also signify failed academic efforts
tion today are expressions of the deepening at defragmenting the philosophical, reli-
gious, and scientific disciplinarities. A frag-

111
mented and “disciplined” academia, still in ments beginning from the personal here
the grips of matter/mind, self/society, and and now. Only through dialectical tran-
theory/practice dualisms will continue to scendence of philosophically perpetuated
fail in fulfilling its mission of reintegrating religious vs. scientific teleologies of world-
the essentially creative powers of human- historical change in favor of a conscious
kind in favor of the good life. and intentional humanist teleology arising
One may view Marx’s western utopia- from the creative powers of human beings
nism, Gurdjieff’s eastern mysticism, and themselves can substantively rational and
Mannheim’s academic sociology of knowl- real advances be made towards building in-
edge as mutually alienated and lop-sided ner and global harmony. “Human architec-
philosophical, religious, and scientific frag- ture” is the art of imaginative design and
ments of humanist utopistics in modern construction of alternative spatiotemporal
times. The projection of human creative dialecticities between the personal self-
powers onto “objective laws (or origins) of identities here and now and long-term,
motion of nature or history,” “supernatu- large-scale, world-historical change.
ral” agencies, or select elites of remarkable In my dissertation I have tried to dem-
intellectuals or party cadres, represents the onstrate that all philosophical, theoretical,
degree to which the very world-historical and practical dualisms—which emanate
agencies for human de-alienation have from dichotomizations of reality into mat-
themselves grown alienated from one an- ter and mind, and result in alienating self
other. The failing conscious and intentional and social knowledges and praxes—can be
shocks of the two major eastern and west- effectively transcended through their re-ar-
ern humanist renaissances of the 4th-6th ticulation as diverse manifestations of part-
centuries BC and of 13th-15th AD in bring- whole dialectics. Developing and applying
ing about a lasting dialectical synthesis of an architectural approach to sociology, I ad-
the three polarized and failing fragments of vocate the abandoning of “house storeys”
utopistic endeavor, I argue, has given rise and similar metaphors still subconsciously
in the modern period to the “antisystemic” fragmenting psychosociological and histor-
mode of seeking social change which by its ical analyses. The habituated common
very nature of spatiotemporally distanciat- sense definition of society as “multiple”
ing the actual means from the promised ethno-national and/or civilizational sys-
ends of social change has also proven to be tems of relations among “individuals”—
an exercise in failure. based on ahistorical presumptions of hu-
The way out of this world-historical man “individuality”—is rejected in favor of
impasse, I argue, is inventing new human- its definition as a singular world-historical
ist renaissances involving far-reaching and ensemble of intra-, inter-, and extraperson-
integrative alternative-”civilizational” dia- al self relations. It is argued that human life
logues across utopian, mystical, and aca- can be harmonious only when it is a world-
demic fragments of humanist utopistics. system of self-determining individualities.
The answer lies in conscious and intention- Towards this end, the sociology of self-
al reclaiming and reconstitution of human- knowledge is proposed as an alternative re-
ist utopistics—informed by a view of search and pedagogical landscape for
human society as a singular spatiotemporal building de-alienated and self-determining
ensemble of diverse intra-, inter-, and ex- human realities.
trapersonal self relations, and exercised by The proposed sociology of self-knowl-
example in the midst of life in the context of edge and human architecture—twin fields
creative, self-de-alienating, self-harmoniz- of inquiry involving research on and prac-
ing, and globally self-expanding move- tice of spatiotemporal dialectics between

112
here-and-now personal self-identities and proach to various classical or
world-historical social structures—are ex- contemporary social theories, and being
ercises in applied sociology beginning in open to comparative cultural diversity in
the social spacetimes of our classrooms. our theorizing efforts, I argue, would pro-
They are meant to introduce students to ap- vide a much more fruitful theoretical envi-
plied sociology not simply in theory, but in ronment for the advancement of utopistics.
the practice of their globally self-reflective To dehabituate from the alienating self and
research as part of their curricular assign- social structures preventing us from
ments. I use audiovisual media and partic- achieving social justice, we need to find
ularly feature films to evoke not just the ways to dehabituate ourselves from dualis-
intellectual, but also the emotional and sen- tic theoretical practices. We do not stand
sual selves of students in their learning ex- apart from the contested theoretical identi-
perience. I have found a reverse micro to ties of the good life we have inherited from
macro, present to past, ordering of socio- the past in world-history context; to recog-
logical theories to be an invaluable strategy nize this and to move beyond contestation
in exposing students to rather abstract the- in favor of open and detached dialogues
oretical discussions. Seeing no dualism be- would be a prerequisite for bringing about
tween teaching and research, I approach effective change in favor of the good life,
teaching itself as a most important exercise without and within.
in applied sociological research. For me,
practicing what C. Wright Mills called the V
sociological imagination is not simply a
motto but is an actual practical guide to be
One crowd in religion ponder their way,
pursued by students first in the laboratory
One crowd in science supposedly stay,
of their global self-research assignments
I fear one morning town crier shouts,
throughout the semester. Examples of stu-
“The way’s neither! O gone astray!”
dents’ works chronicled in the journal Hu-
man Architecture: Journal of the Sociology of —Omar Khayyam
Self-Knowledge attest to the plausible value
of such a pedagogical strategy in teaching If anything, Khayyam’s quatrain above
applied sociology across diverse course of- speaks to the heart of our contested identi-
ferings. ties in a world-history context. Our contest-
I have argued, more exhaustively in the ed identities habitually framed in
dissertation and more briefly in the forego- philosophy, religion, and science, have of-
ing, that the root cause of practical failures ten sidelined art and artistic endeavors
in ending our self and social stratifications from assuming hegemonic standpoints in
is to be sought in the habituated structures the formulation of our theories of and strat-
of our theoretical frameworks, world-his- egies for change. Why not stop at this point
torically inherited in terms of various dual- of interpreting our selves and world in pre-
isms of mind/matter, self/society, theory/ determined frameworks and start creating
practice, and east/west. Recognizing the new ones in the here and nows of our inner
significance of challenges posed by the sub- and interpersonal lives? Really, what
conscious as a mediating region between makes us not see Omar Khayyam (or Rumi,
mind and matter, redefining society and so- similarly), for instance, as social psycholo-
ciology in terms of interaction of selves gists, sociologists, historians, and applied
rather than of presumed “individuals,” social theorists? Why can’t our sociologies
adopting both micro/macro and integra- and historiographies be poetic, and ex-
tive (not just selective or even eclectic) ap- pressed in diverse art forms? Why do we

113
not see Rumi, who is more globally popular bituations in favor of the good spiritual life
than ever today, as an applied sociologist, is of course one of the layers of the poem di-
social psychiatrist, and inner and world rected at the intellectual center of our or-
historian, in his own right? Why should so- ganism, to what comprises our waking
ciology and historiography not be at the consciousness. The reed metaphor, on the
same time utopistic in substance, and artis- other hand, and all the subtle and complex
tic in form? tropological symbolisms associated with
The Song of the Reed which opens Ru- the metaphor is directed at our emotional
mi’s book of spiritual couplets is another center, speaking to it in terms of the lan-
voice crying humankind’s alienated and guage of visualizations, which is the prima-
contested identities in search of loving rein- ry language of communication with our
tegration and fulfillment in world-history subconscious mind. Finally, the couplet
context. This song with which I would like form and rhythm of reed’s song as ex-
to conclude my presentation is actually a pressed in the poem is a crucial third layer
three-fold song, woven delicately with one of the poem, directed at our sensibilities of
another as in a Persian carpet destined for a hearing, sight, and movements, aspects of
mystical flight towards the good spiritual the physical center of our organism. The
life. The meaning, the feeling, and the sen- three-fold nature of the poem in the origi-
sations are the three equally significant and nal is, in short, of paradigmatic relevance to
vital elements of the poem, aimed at evok- the very thesis of the poem, which is the
ing, awakening, blending, and “cooking” need of human beings to free themselves
our souls towards the experiencing of inner from habituations and addictions of the
and global unity that can only be a precon- earth in favor of the good spiritual life. It is
dition for experiencing the cosmic self- the fragmented and independent function-
knowledge sought after in the mystical tra- ing of the three centers in the human organ-
dition. The three-foldness of the Song of the ism, and the alienated multiple selfhoods
Reed is of the essence for the eastern civili- resulting from it, that makes possible the
zational utopistics of which it is a part. To perpetuation of habituated and addictive
bridge it with the thoughts, feelings and behaviors in the human organism. Rumi’s
sensibilities of a western audience engaged seeking a “torn-torn, longing” heart is
in western utopistics of varied kinds—i.e., meant to evoke our emotional sensibilities
searching in their own western ways for the to join the whirling dance of his spiritual
good life around the globe and outside journey. His references to the distinction
themselves—requires not one, not two, but between soul and body, the limits of our ear
a triple translation of its context, content, and tongue and eye sensibilities, are meant
and form elements. to evoke our physical selfhoods to tune in
Western free-verse translations of Ru- to his reed’s song. His evoking our curiosi-
mi’s Song of the Reed miss the whole point ties about his secret is meant to evoke our
of his applied social psychology and psy- higher intellectual selves to embark on the
chiatry when they omit its tropological journey of cosmic self-knowledge and
rhyme from its truncated and overrationa- change.
lised substantive meaning. The song is di- Rumi’s Song of the Reed is not simply
rected not just to one, but to all the three preaching to us, but through the actual un-
physical, intellectual, and emotional cen- folding of his poem’s threefold architecture
ters of the human organisms comprising is participating in helping us transform our
his audience. The meaning of the poem in identities towards freedom from enslave-
terms of the alienation of humankind and ments to worldly objects. He is speaking
the need for efforts to give up worldly ha- not only to our conscious but to our uncon-

114
scious and subconscious minds, i.e., to the Reed comes of use when lovers departIt’s wail-
three-fold minds of our intellectual, physi- ing scales tear love’s veilings apart
cal, and emotional selves simultaneously, Like reed both poison and cure, who saw?Like
seeking to tear apart the veils and buffers reed comrade and devote, who saw?
Reed tells of the bleeding heart’s talesTells of
that separate the three centers from one an-
what mad lovers’ love entails
other and all of them from lessons of world-
With the truth, only seeker’s intimateAs the
history, preventing us from realizing the ut- tongue knows only ear’s estimate
ter sleepiness, imprisonment, mechanical- Days, nights, lost count in my sorrowPast
ness, and enslavement of our ordinary lives merged in my sorrow with tomorrow
as alienated selves. The “secret” alluded to If the day is gone, say: “So what! go, go!But
in the poem, i.e., the separation of body and remain, O you pure, O my sorrow”
soul, the inner alienation of human physi- This water‘s dispensable—not for the fishHun-
cal, intellectual, and emotional selves, is the gry finds days long without a dish
fundamental and paradigmatic essence of Cooked soul‘s unknowable if you’re rawThen
the poem, a secret that is paradoxically be- there is no use to tire the jaw
Break the chain, . .. be free, ... O boy!How long
ing given to us on the humble platter of
will you remain that gold’s toy?!
spiritual food by Rumi without our eyes
Say you have oceans, but how can you pourAll
and ears being able to “get the clue,” so to oceans in a single day’s jar, more & more?!
speak. The voice of Rumi is another con- The greedy’s eye-jar will never fill upNo pearl,
testing identity in world-history context if oyster’s mouth doesn’t give up
whose aim is to do away with contestations Whoever tore his robe in love’s affairTore free of
altogether in favor of the good life through greed, flaw, and false care
the unitary experiencing of human and cos- Joy upon you! O sorrowful sweet love!O the
mic love. healer! healer of ills! love! love!
Imagine a ceremony in the presence of O healer of the vain, of our shameO Galen in
Rumi, where one hears the soothing cries of name, Platonic in fame!
Earth’s whirling in heaven’s for love, loveHills’
reeds in the background. Rumi suddenly
whirling round the earth’s for love, love
interrupts them and sings his own reed’s
Love’s the soul in hill! It’s love in the hillThat
song: brought hill down and Moses the chill!
If coupled my lips with friends’ on and onI’ll
Listen to how this reed is wailingAbout separa- tell tales, like reed, long, long
tions it’s complaining: Uncoupled, though, these lips will cease wails
“From reedbed since parted was IMen, women, Lose tongue, though remain untold tales
have cried my cry When the rose is dead, garden long goneNo
“Only a heart, torn-torn, longingCan hear my canary can recite her song long
tales of belonging The lover is veiled, beloved’s the allVeil must
“Whosoever lost his essenceFor reuniting seeks tear to hear beloved’s call
lessons If you do stay away from love, hear, hear!Like a
“In the midst of all I criedFor the sad and happy wingless bird you’ll die, fear, fear!
both sighed How can I stay awake and see the roadIf lover’s
“But they heard only what they knewSought light shine not on my abode?
not after the secrets I blew Love always seeks ways to spread the light
“My secret’s not far from this, my cryBut, eye Why, then, does your mirror reflect a night?
or ear catch not the light if don’t try Your mirror takes no tales, if need to know,
“Body and soul each other do not veilBut there ‘Cause your rust keeps away all lights’ glow.
is no one to hear his soul’s tale”
What arises from the reed is fireWhoever lost it,
is lost entire
What set the reed on fire is love, loveWhat rages SUGGESTED BIBLIOGRAPHY
in reed is nothing but love, love

115
Adorno, Theodor W. 1967. “The Sociology of tated Bibliography, with an introductory
Knowledge and Its Consciousness.” In essay by Michel De Salzmann. New York:
Prisms, London: Spearman. Garland Press.
Adorno, Theodor W. 1973. Negative Dialectics. Driscoll, J. Walter. 1999. Gurdjieff: a Reading
New York: Seabury Press. Guide, Los Altos, California: Gurdjieff
Bailey, Leon. 1994. Critical Theory and the Sociol- Electronic Publishing. (purchasable at
ogy of Knowledge: A Comparative Study in http://www.gurdjieff.org/G.htm)
the Theory of Ideology. New York: Peter
Lang. Engels, Frederick. [1888] 1970. “Ludwig Feuer-
bach and the End of Classical German
Baker, George and Walter Driscoll. 1992. “Gurd- Philosophy.” Pp. 335-376 in Karl Marx and
jieff in America: An Overview.” In Amer- Frederick Engels: Selected Works. Moscow:
ica's Alternative Religions. SUNY Press, Progress Publishers.
Albany.
Engels, F. 1976. Dialectics of Nature. Moscow:
Berger, Peter and Thomas Luckmann. [1966] Progress Publishers.
1967. The Social Construction of Reality: A
Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. Gar- Finch, Henry Leroy. 1996. “Gurdjieff and the
den City, NY: Doubleday & Company, Modern World.” Pp. 8-29 in Gurdjieff:
Inc. Essays and Reflections on the Man and his
Teaching, edited by Jacob Needleman and
Bourdieu, Pierre, and Loic J. Wacquant. 1992. George Baker. New York: Continuum.
An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology. Chi-
cago: The University of Chicago Press. Foucault, Michel. 1972. The Archeology of Knowl-
edge and the Discourse on Language. NY:
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1998. Practical Reason: On the Pantheon Books.
Theory of Action. Stanford: Stanford Univ
Press. Foucault, Michel. 1995. Discipline and Punish.
Translated by Alan Sheridan. NY: Vin-
Bourne, Russell, series editor. 1966. Great Ages of tage/Random House.
Man: A History of the World's Cultures.
New York: Time Incorporated. Foucault, Michel. 1973. Madness and Civilization:
A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason.
Brook, Peter. (director). 1978. Feature Film: Translated by R. Howard. NY: Vintage/
“Meetings with Remarkable Men.” New Random House.
York: Remar Productions, Inc.
Fromm, Erich. [1956] 2000. The Art of Loving.
Buford, Thomas O. 1995. In Search of a Calling: NY: HarperCollins.
The College's Role in Shaping Identity.
Macon, Georgia: Mercer University Fromm, Erich. [1976] 1996. To Have or To Be.
Press. NY: Continuum.
Cohen, G. A. 1978. Marx's Theory of History: A Garaudy, Roger. [1964] 1967. Karl
Defense. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton Marx: The Evolution of His Thought. New
University Press. York: International Publishers.
Collins, Randall. 1998. The Sociology of Philoso- Gulbenkian Commission. 1996. Open the Social
phies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Sciences: Report of the Gulbenkian Commis-
Change. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The sion on the Restructuring of the Social Sci-
Belknap Press of Harvard University ences. Stanford: Stanford University
Press. Press.
Coser, Lewis. 1968. “Knowledge, Sociology of.” Gurdjieff, G. I. [1933] 1973. Herald of Coming
Pp. 428-435 in The International Encyclope- Good: First Appeal to Contemporary
dia of the Social Sciences. New York: The Humanity. New York: Samuel Weiser Inc.
Macmillan Company and The Free Press. Gurdjieff, G. I. 1950. All and Everything: Beelze-
Curtis, James E. and John Petras, eds. 1970. The bub's Tales to His Grandson. First Edition.
Sociology of Knowledge: A Reader. New New York: Harcourt, Brace and Com-
York and Washington: Praeger Publish- pany.
ers. Gurdjieff, G. I. 1973. Views from the Real World:
Deikman, Arthur J. 1982. The Observing Self: Early Talks of G.I. Gurdjieff. New York:
Mysticism and Psychotherapy. Boston: Bea- Arkana/Penguin Books.
con Press. Gurdjieff, G. I. [1963] 1985. Meetings with
Deikman, Arthur J. 1990. The Wrong Way Home: Remarkable Men. New York and London:
Uncovering the Patterns of Cult Behavior in Viking Arkana.
American Society. Boston: Beacon Press. Gurdjieff, G. I. [1981] 1991. Life is Real Only
Driscoll, J. Walter and the Gurdjieff Foundation Then, When “I AM.” New York and Lon-
of California. 1985. Gurdjieff: An Anno- don: Viking Arkana/Triangel Editions,
Inc.

116
Gurdjieff, G. I. 1992. All and Everything: Beelze- Publishing Co., Inc. & The Free Press.
bub's Tales to His Grandson. Second Edi- Kettler, David and Volker Meja. 1993. “Intro-
tion. New York and London: Viking duction.” In From Karl Mannheim, edited
Arkana/Triangle Editions, Inc. by Wolff. Kurt H. New Brunswick: Trans-
Habermas, Jurgen. 1973. Theory and Practice. action Publishers.
Boston: Beacon Press. Kettler, David and Volker Meja. 1995. Karl Man-
Harvey, David. 1990. The Condition of Postmoder- nheim and the Crisis of Liberalism: The
nity. MA: Basil Blackwell. Secret of These New Times. New Brunswick
Harvey, David. 1996. Justice, Nature & the Geog- and London: Transaction Publishers.
raphy of Difference. Oxford: Blackwell Kettler, David, Volker Meja and Nico Stehr.
Publishers Ltd. 1984. Karl Mannheim. New York: Tavis-
Harvey, David. 2000. Spaces of Hope. Berkeley: tock Publications.
University of California Press. Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific
Harvey, David. 2001. Spaces of Capital. London: Revolutions. Chicago: The University of
Routledge. Chicago Press.
Haschak, Paul G. 1994. Utopian/Dystopian Litera- Kumar, Krishan. 1991. Utopianism. Minneapolis:
ture: A Bibliography of Literary Criticism. Univeristy of Minnesota Press.
Metuchen, N.J., & London: The Scare- Lefebvre, Henri. 1991. The Production of Space.
crow Press, Inc. Translated by Donald Nicholson Smith.
Hegel, G. W. F. 1975. Hegel's Logic. Translated by Oxford: Blackwell.
William Wallace with foreword by J. N. Lenin. V. I. [1913] 1968. “The Three Sources and
Findlay. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Three Component Parts of Marxism.” Pp.
Hegel, G. W. F. 1969. Hegel's Science of Logic. 62-67 in Marx, Engels, Marxism. Moscow:
Translated by A. V. Miller. London: Progress.
Humanity Books. Lenin, V. I. 1977. Philosophical Note-
Hoffman, John. 1976. Marxism and the Theory of books. In Collected Works, vol. 38. Moscow:
Praxis. New York: International Publish- Progress Publishers.
ers. Lenin, V. I. 1977. Selected Works. Mos-
Hopkins, Terence K., Immanuel Wallerstein, cow: Progress Publishers.
and Associates. 1982. World-Systems Anal- Levin, Jerome David. 1992. Theories of the Self.
ysis: Theory and Methodology. Beverly Washington: Hemisphere Publishing
Hills: Sage Publication, Inc. Corporation.
Horkheimer, Max. 1947. Eclipse of Reason. NY: Lukacs, Georg. [1923] 1971. History and Class
Seabury Press. Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialec-
Horkheimer, Max. 1974. Critical Theory: Selected tics. Translated by Rodney Livingstone.
Essays. NY: Seabury Press. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Horkheimer, Max. 1990. “A New Concept of McCarthy, E. Doyle. 1996. Knowledge As Culture:
Ideology?” Pp. 140-157 in The Sociology of The New Sociology of Knowledge. New
Knowledge Dispute, edited by Volker Meja York: Routledge.
and Nico Stehr. London and New York: McLellan, David. 1977. Karl Marx: His Life and
Routhledge. Thought. New York: Harper Colophon
Horkheimer, Max and Theodor W. Adorno. Books.
1972. Dialectic of Enlightenment. NY: McLellan, David. 1979. Marxism after Marx: An
Seabury Press. Introduction. New York: Harper & Row
Horton, Robin and Ruth Finnegan, eds. 1973. Publishers.
Modes of Thought: Essays on Thinking in McMurtry, John. 1978. The Structure of Marx's
Western and Non-Western Societies. Lon-
don: Faber & Faber. World-View. Princeton: Princeton Univer-
sity Press.
Kateb, George. [1963] 1972. Utopia and Its Ene-
mies. Schocken Books. Mannheim, Karl. 1990. “Competition as a Cul-
tural Phenomenon.” In The Sociology of
Kateb, George. 1968. “Utopias and Utopia- Knowledge Dispute, edited by Volker Meja
nism.” Pp. 267-70 in The International and Nico Stehr. London and New York:
Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences, edited Routhledge.
by David L. Sills, vol. 16. New York: The
Macmillan Company and The Free Press. Mannheim, Karl. 1936. Ideology and Utopia.
Translated by Louis Wirth and Edward
Kateb, George. [1967] 1972. “Utopias and Utopi- Shils. New York: Harcourt Brace and
anism.” Pp. 212-215 in The Encyclopedia of Company, Harvest Books.
Philosophy, vol. 8. New York: Macmillan

117
Mannheim, Karl. [1940] 1981. Man and Society in Marx, Karl and Frederick Engels. 1975-. Col-
an Age of Reconstruction. London: Rout- lected Works. New York: International
ledge Kegan & Paul. Publishers.
Manuel, F. E. and F. P. Manuel. 1979. Utopian Marx, K., Frederick Engels, and V. I.
Thought in the Western World. New Jersey: Lenin. 1978a. On Dialectical Materialism.
Humanities. Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marcuse, Herbert. 1990. “Sociological Method Marx, K., Frederick Engels, and V. I. Lenin.
and the Problem of Truth.” Pp. 129- 139 1978b. On Communist Society. Moscow:
in The Sociology of Knowledge Dispute, Progress Publishers. Third revised edi-
edited by Volker Meja and Nico Stehr. tion.
London and New York: Routhledge. Mead, George Herbert. 1934. Mind, Self and Soci-
Marcuse, Herbert. 1954. Reason and Revolution: ety. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chi-
Hegel and the Rise of Social Theory. NY: Bea- cago Press.
con Press. Mead, George Herbert. 1938. The Philosophy of
Marcuse, Herbert. 1955. Eros and Civilization: A the Act. Chicago: University of Chicago
Philosophical Inquiry into Freud. Boston: Press.
Beacon Press. Mead, George Herbert. [1959] 1981. The Philoso-
Marcuse, Herbert. 1958. One-Dimensional Man. phy of the Present. Chicago: University of
Boston: Beacon Press. Chicago Press.
Marcuse, Herbert. 1958. Soviet Marxism: A Criti- Meja, Volker and Nico Stehr, eds. 1990. The Soci-
cal Analysis. NY: Vintage Books. ology of Knowledge Dispute. London and
Markovic, Mihailo. 1974. From Affluence to New York: Routhledge.
Praxis. Boston: Beacon Press. Meja, Volker and David Kettler. 1993. “Intro-
Marx, Karl. 1967a. Capital. Vol. 1. New York: duction.” In From Karl Mannheim, by Kurt
International Publishers. Ninth 1979 H. Wolff, New Brunswick: Transaction
printing. Publishers.
Marx, Karl. [1859] 1970. A Contribution Merton, Robert K. [1949] 1957. Social Theory and
to the Critique of the Political Economy. Social Structure. Glencoe, Ill.: The Free
Edited with and Introduction by Maurice Press.
Dobb. New York: International Publish- Mills, C. Wright. 1940. “Methodological Conse-
ers. quences of the Sociology of Knowledge.”
Marx, Karl. [1859] 1970. “Preface.” Pp. American Journal of Sociology 46:316-330.
19-23 in A Contribution to the Critique of Mills, C. Wright. 1953. Character and Social Struc-
the Political Economy. Edited with and ture: The Psychology of Social Institutions.
Introduction by Maurice Dobb. New New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
York: International Publishers. Mills, C. Wright. 1959. The Sociological Imagina-
Marx, Karl. 1970. “Letter to F. Mehring,” dated tion. New York: Oxford University Press.
July 1893, 1858, pp. 495-497 in Karl Marx Moore, James. 1991. Gurdjieff: The Anatomy of a
and Frederick Engels. Selected Works, vol. Myth. Rockport, Massachausetts: Elment.
3. Moscow: Progress Publishers.
More, Sir Thomas [1516] 1965. Utopia. New
Marx, Karl. 1973. Grundrisse: Founda- York: Penguin Books.
tions of the Critique of Political Economy.
New York: Vintage Books. Mukherjee, Ramkrishna. 1978. What Will It Be?:
Explorations in Inductive Sociology.
Marx, Karl. 1975. “Letter to Engels,” dated Jan- Durham, North Carolina: Carolina Aca-
uary 14, 1858, pp. 93 in Karl Marx and demic Press.
Frederick Engels. Selected Correspondence.
Moscow: Progress Publishers. Third Mumford, Lewis. 1941. The Story of Utopias.
revised edition. New York: Peter Smith.
Marx, Karl and Frederick Engels. Vol. 1:1969, Needleman, Jacob. 1993. “G. I. Gurdjieff and
Vol. 2:1969, Vol. 3:1970. Selected Works. His School.” Pp. 359-379 in Modern Eso-
Moscow: Progress Publishers. teric Spirituality (part of the series World
Spirituality: An Encyclopedic History of the
Marx Karl and Frederick Engels. 1975. Selected Religious Quest) edited by Antoine Faivre
Correspondence. Moscow: Progress Pub- and Jacob Needleman. London: SCM
lishers. Third revised edition. Press Ltd.
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. 1978. The Needleman, Jacob. 1996. “Introduction.” Pp. ix-
Marx-Engels Reader, edited by Robert C. xii in Gurdjieff: Essays and Reflections on
Tucker. 2nd edition. New York: W. W. the Man and his Teaching, edited by Jacob
Norton & Company. Needleman and George Baker. New

118
York: Continuum. Honderich. Oxford: Oxford University
Negley, Glen. [1977] 1978. Utopian Literature: A Press.
Bibliography with a Supplementary Listing Snodgrass, Mary Ellen. 1995. Encyclopedia of
of Works Influential in Utopian Thought. Utopian Literature. Santa Barbara, Califor-
University Press of Kansas. nia: ABC-CLIO.
Nicoll, Maurice. 1985. Psychological Commentar- Soja, Edward. 1993. “History: Geography:
ies on the Teaching of Gurdjieff & Ouspensky. Modernity.” Pp. 135-150 in The Cultural
Volume One. Boston & London: Shamb- Studies: A Reader, edited by Simon Dur-
hala. ing. New York and London: Routledge.
Ouspensky, P.D. 1949. In Search of the Miracu- Speeth, Kathleen Riordan. 1989. The Gurdjieff
lous: Fragments of an Unknown Teaching. Work. NY: Jeremy P. Tarcher/Perigee.
New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich Stark, Werner. 1958. The Sociology of Knowledge:
Publishers. An Essay in Aid of A Deeper Understanding
Pilcher, Jane. 1994. “Mannheim's Sociology of of the History of Ideas. Glencoe, Ill.: The
Generations: An Undervalued Legacy.” Free Press.
British Journal of Sociology 3:481-495. Stark, Werner. [1967] 1972. “Sociology of
Popper, Karl, R. 1963. The Open Society and Its Knowledge.” Pp. 475-478 in The Encyclo-
Enemies. 2 vols. New York: Harper Torch- pedia of Philosophy, vol. 7. New York: Mac-
books. millan Publishing Co., Inc. & The Free
Popper, Karl, R. 1970. “The Sociology of Knowl- Press.
edge.” Pp. 282-306 in The Sociology of Tamdgidi, Mohammad H., ed. 1997. ‘I’ in the
Knowledge: A Reader, edited by James E. World-System: Stories From An Odd Sociol-
Curtis and John Petras. New York and ogy Class, (Selected Student Writings, Soc.
Washington: Praeger Publishers. 280Z: Sociology of Knowledge: Mysticism,
(Reprinted from The Open Society and Its Utopia, Science). Limited Edition. Bing-
Enemies. 2 vol. NJ: Princeton University hamton: Crumbling Façades Press.
Press. 1963). Tamdgidi, Mohammd H. 1999. “Ideology and
Remmling, Gunter W. 1975. The Sociology of Karl Utopia in Mannheim: Towards the Soci-
Mannheim: With a Bibliographical Guide to ology of Self Knowledge,” Presented at
the Sociology of Knowledge, Ideological anal- the History of Sociology Refereed
ysis, and Social Planning. London: Rout- Roundtable Session of the American
ledge & Kegan Paul. Sociological Association, 94th Annual
Rosdolsky, Roman.1977. The Making of Meeting, August 6-10 1999, Chicago.
Marx's ‘Capital.’London: Pluto Press. Reprinted in Human Architecture:
Journal of the Sociology of Self-Knowl-
Rumi (Molana Jalaleddin). Masnavi-e Ma’navi edge, Fall, 2002, 120-139.
(Spiritual Couplets).
TTamdgidi, Mohammad-Hossein. 2002. “Mysti-
Scheler, Max. 1978. Problems of a Sociology of cism and Utopia: Towards the Sociology
Knowledge. Translated by Manfred S. of Self-Knowledge and Human Archite-
Frings, edited and with an introduction cure (A Study in Marx, Gurdjieff, and
by Kenneth W. Stikkers. London: Rout- Mannheim).” Ph.D. Dissertation, Bing-
ledge & Kegan Paul. hamton University (SUNY).
Shannon, Thomas Richard. 1989. An Introduc- Tamdgidi, Mohammad H. 2001. “Open the
tion to the World-System Perspective. Boul- Antisystemic Movements: The Book, the
der, San Francisco, & London: Westview Concept, and the Reality” Review, XXIV,
Press. 2:301-338.
Shun, Kwong-loi. 1995. “Chinese Philosophy.” Taylor. C.C.W. 1995. “Socrates.” Pp. 836-837 in
Pp. 130-132 in The Oxford Companion to The Oxford Companion to Philosophy,
Philosophy, edited by Ted Honderich. edited by Ted Honderich. Oxford: Oxford
Oxford: Oxford University Press. University Press.
Shils, Edward. 1968. “Mannheim, Karl.” Pp. Thayer, H.S. [1967] 1972. “Pragmatism.” Pp.
557-562 in The International Encyclopedia of 430-436 in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
the Social Sciences, edited by David L. vol. 6. New York: Macmillan Publishing
Sills, vol. 16. New York: The Macmillan Co., Inc. & The Free Press.
Company and The Free Press.
Tillich, Paul. 1990. “On Ideology and Utopia.”
Shils, Edward. 1995. “Karl Mannheim.” The Pp. 107-112 in The Sociology of Knowledge
American Scholar 64, 2, Spring: 221-235. Dispute, edited by Volker Meja and Nico
Singer, Peter. 1995. “Hegel, George Wilhelm Stehr. London and New York: Routh-
Friedrich.” Pp. 339-343. in The Oxford ledge.
Companion to Philosophy, edited by Ted

119
Tucker, Robert, C., ed. 1978. The Marx-Engels Weber, Max. [1930] 1958. The Protestant Ethic and
Reader. 2nd edition. New York: W. W. the Spirit of Capitalism. Translated by Tal-
Norton & Company. cott Parsons, New York: Charles Scrib-
Turner, Bryan S. 1995. “Karl Mannheim's Ideol- ner's Sons.
ogy and Utopia.” Political Studies White, Hayden, V. [1967] 1972. “Feuerbach,
XLIII:718-727. Ludwig Andreas.” Pp. 190-2 in The Ency-
Turner, Bryan S. 1998. “Preface to the clopedia of Philosophy, vol. 3. New York:
new edition.” In Ideology and Utopia. Lon- Macmillan Publishing Co., Inc. & The
don: Routhledge. Free Press.
Vazques, Adolf S. 1977. The Philosophy of Praxis. Williams, Raymond. 1958. Culture and Society:
Prometheus Books. 1780-1950. Harmonsworth: Penguin.
Vigadski, Vitalis. 1974. The Story of a Williams, Robin M., Jr. 1966. “Some further
Great Discovery: How Karl Marx Wrote Comments on Chronic Controversies.”
“Capital.” Abacus Press. American Journal of Sociology LXXI,
May:717-21.
Wallerstein, Immanuel. l974. The Modern World-
System, I: Capitalist Agriculture and the Wilson Organ, Troy. 1975. Western Approaches to
Origins of the European World-Economy in Eastern Philosophy. Athens, Ohio: Ohio
the Sixteenth Century. New York & Lon- University Press.
don: Academic Press. Wolff, Kurt H. 1983. “A Preliminary Inquiry
Wallerstein, Immanuel. l979. The Capitalist into the Sociology of Knowledge from
World-Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge the Standpoint of the Study of Man.” In
Univ. Press. Beyond the Sociology of Knowledge: An
Introduction and a Development. New York:
Wallerstein, Immanuel. l989. “Culture as the University Press of America.
Ideological Battleground of the Modern
World-System,” Journal of Social Studies, Wolff. Kurt H. [1971] 1993. From Karl Mannheim.
XXI, l:5-22. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.
Wallerstein, Immanuel. 1990. “Braudel on Capi- Young, T. R. 1972. New Sources of Self. New York:
talism, or Everything Upside Down.” In Pergamon Press Inc.
Modern Age - Modern Hitorian. Edited by Young, T. R. 1990. The Drama of Social Life: Essays
Ferenc Glatz, Budapest. in Post-Modern Social Psychology. New
Wallerstein, Immanuel. 1991a. Unthinking Social Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.
Science: The Limits of Nineteenth Century Young-Eisendrath, Polly and James A. Hall.
Paradigms. Cambridge: Polity Press. 1987. The Book of the Self. New York and
Wallerstein, Immanuel. 1991b. Geopolitics and London: New York University Press.
Geoculture: Essays on the Changing World- Zurcher, Louis A., Jr. 1977. The Mutable Self: A
System. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Self-Concept for Social Change. Beverly
Press. Hills: Sage Publications.
Wallerstein, Immanuel. 1996. Historical Capital-
ism with Capitalist Civilization. London
and New York: Verso.
Wallerstein, Immanuel. 1998a. Utopistics: Or,
Historical Choices of the Twenty-First Cen-
tury. New York: The New Press.
Wallerstein, Immanuel, ed. 1998b. Mentoring,
Methods, and Movements: Colloquium in
Honor of Terence K. Hopkins by His Former
Students. Binghamton: Fernand Braudel
Center (co-publisher: Ahead Desktop
Publishing House).
Wallerstein, Immanuel. 1999. The End of the
World As We Know It: Social Science for the
Twenty-First Century. Minneapolis: Uni-
versity of Minnesota Press.
Wallerstein, Immanuel. 2000. “Where Should
Sociologists Be Heading?” Contemporary
Sociology 29, 2:306-308.
Weber, Alfred. 1927. Ideen zur Staats- und Kultur-
soziologie. Karlsruhe.

120

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen