Sie sind auf Seite 1von 38

Sartre: Imaginary Pursuit of Being Sartre: Imaginary Pursuit of Being

not address the larger question of the existential origins and meanings of affirmed the capacity of consciousness to reach outside itself and gain
imagining. knowledge of the world that was not simply an elaboration of the self.
The second book, L'imaginaire, published in 1940, restates the thesis One might suspect that Sartre fashions himself a realist, yet he consis-
of the earlier tract, namely, that images ought to be understood as forms tently qualifies the ascription, arguing instead that neither consciousness
of intentional consciousness, but also makes some forays into the existen- nor the world is primary, but that both "are given in one stroke: essentially
tial ground of imagining. Throughout this book, largely in the context of external to consciousness, the world is nevertheless essentially relative to
unsystematic asides, Sartre begins his speculations on the relationship consciousness" ("I" 4). The world does not unilaterally impress itself on
between desire and the imaginary. In this context, intentionality becomes consciousness, as if consciousness were a tabula rasa to be formed at will
an essential structure not merely of perception and imagination, but also by the contingencies of the world; nor does consciousness create the world
of feeling. Dismissing the claims of representational theories of knowl- as a particular representation. Consciousness reveals the world through
edge, Sartre claims that perception, imagination, and feeling are inten- determinate intentional relations; it presents the world through specific
tional forms of consciousness, i.e., that they refer to objects in the world modes without ever denying the essential externality of that world. Al-
and are not to be construed as impoverished perceptions or solipsistic though the world never makes itself known outside of an intentional act,
enterprises. Indeed, Husserl 's doctrine of intentionality signified for Sartre this noematic pole of experience-the object pole-is in itself irreducible;
the end to solipsistic idealism in the tradition of modern epistemology every intentional act, by virtue of being directed toward a noematic
("I," 4-5). correlate, affirms the independence and externality of consciousness and
Sartre's extension and reformulation of Husserl's view of intentionality its world. In Sartre's early essay on intentionality, he affirms the difference
entails a shift from an epistemological to an existential perspective. Inten- between consciousness and world as an external relation, but insists that
tionality for the Sartre of the 1930s signifies not merely the various ways this very externality is what binds the two indissolubly. The externality
in which we stand in knowing relations to things, but also an essential of this relation assures a non-solipsistic encounter with the world: "You
structure of the being of human life. The directionality of consciousness, see this tree, to be sure. But you see it just where it is : at the side of the
its comportment toward things outside itself, comes to signify the onto- road, in the midst of the dust, alone and writhing in the heat, eight miles
logical situation of human beings as a "spontaneity" and "upsurge." As from the Mediterranean coast. It could not enter into your consciousness
intentional beings, it is not merely our knowledge that is of the world, for it is not of the same nature as consciousness" ("I" 4) .
but our essential passion as well; our desire is to be enthralled with the Consciousness, then, does not apprehend the world in virtue of a
world, to be "of" the world. Intentionality comes to signify human access common identity with the world, except insofar as consciousness and
to the world, the end to theories that close off consciousness and subjec- world represent noetic and noematic poles which are structurally iso-
tivity from the world, forcing them to reside behind the dense screen of morphic. 2 This structural isomorphism, however, does not refute the
representation. ontological distinctness of both poles: one intends the world in the mode
Sartre discovered the possibility of a non-solipsistic view of conscious- of fearing, imagining, desiring, yet the world cannot intend consciousness
ness in Husserl's Ideas. 1 Against a background of psychologistic theories in the mode of fearing or desiring, and neither can consciousness success-
of perception and knowledge, Husserl appeared to Sartre as the first fully enclose itself in its object without first denying itself as conscious-
philosopher successfully to avoid the " illusion of immanence"-the ma- ness-the denying of which would, in effect, affirm itself as consciousness,
laise of "digestive philosophy"-which understood objects of perception the power to negate. Consciousness eludes the world even as the world-
as so many contents of consciousness, fabricated and entertained within and its own self-elision-remains its proper and necessary theme. Con-
the spatial confines of the mind ("I" 4) . In claiming that all consciousness sciousness, for the Sartre of "Intentionality" as well as The Transcendence
is consciousness of an object, Husserl's view of intentional consciousness of the Ego, is a translucent revelation of the world, an active presentation,
[102] [103]
Sartre: Imaginary Pursuit of Being
pher. As in the Phenomenology, the words that pursue difference become
an inadvertent means of overcoming difference. Words are thus subjected
to the project of desire and facilitate its satisfaction; they give presence to
negativity, constructing both the subject and its tentative satisfaction.
Two questions emerge about Sartre's literary project of existential
4
psychoanalysis. The first has to do with the limits of what can be articu-
lated, and the second, internally related to the first, with the accessibility
of the personal past. Sartre assumes that language brings forth the history
The Life and Death Struggles
of negation that constitutes an individual, but is it fair to assume that
infantile development, understood in terms of primary repression, is
of Desire: Hegel and
wholly accessible to consciousness and to words? What happens to words
when what cannot be spoken makes itself felt in speech? As we shall see,
Contemporary French Theory
the answer to this question poses a severe challenge to Sartre's entire
theory of the subject, its autonomy, and the nature of its linguistic power.
"It is the subject who introduces
division into the individual."
Lacan, Ecrits
The twentieth-century history of Hegelianism in France can be under-
stood in terms of two constitutive moments: (1) the specification of the
subject in terms of finitude, corporeal boundaries, and tempora lity and
(2) the "splitting" (Lacan)2. "displacement" (Derrida), and eventual death
(Foucault, Deleuze) of the sub·ect. 1 In the course of this history,
the Hegelian traveler in pursuit of a global place which he always already
occupies loses his sense of time and location, his directionality and, hence,
self-identity. lndeed, this subject is revealed as the trope it always was,
and one comes to see the hyperbolic aspirations of philosophy now clearly
inscribed in the very logos of desire. But Hegel is not so easily dismissed,
even by those who claim to be beyond him. The contemporary opposition
to Hegel rarely evidences signs of indifference. The difference from Hegel
is a vital and absorbing one, and the act of repudiation more often than
not requires the continued life of that which is to be repudiated, thus
[174] [175]

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen