Sie sind auf Seite 1von 12

A Critical Appraisal of Demand Artifacts in Consumer Research

Author(s): Terence A. Shimp, Eva M. Hyatt and David J. Snyder


Source: Journal of Consumer Research, Vol. 18, No. 3 (Dec., 1991), pp. 273-283
Published by: Oxford University Press
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2489339
Accessed: 15-03-2020 12:24 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

Oxford University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to Journal of Consumer Research

This content downloaded from 88.255.99.25 on Sun, 15 Mar 2020 12:24:48 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A Critical Appraisal of Demand Artifacts
in Consumer Research

TERENCE A. SHIMP
EVA M. HYATT
DAVID J. SNYDER*

Especially since the publication of Sawyer's instructive article on the topic, consumer
researchers have been concerned that demand artifacts significantlyvcompromise
the validity and generalizability of experimental findings. In this article we provide
an overview of the issues surrounding the demand-artifacts controversy, evaluate
the preconditions for demand artifacts, and offer a critique of suppositions about
the consequences and appropriate control of demand artifacts. Kellaris and Cox's
critique of Gorn's well-known classical conditioning experiments provides the back-
drop for much of the discussion.

A long with other social scientists (e.g., Orne 1962), 2. Although consumer researchers are justifiably
consumer researchers have been apprehensive that concerned that demand artifacts may compromise the
demand artifacts may compromise the validity and validity and generalizability of experimental results, we
generalizability of experimental results. Concern be- believe concern about demand artifacts is typically
came especially pronounced with the appearance of based on two equivocal premises: (1) that hypothesis
Sawyer's (1975) article at a time when the emerging guessing equates with demand artifacts and (2) that de-
discipline of consumer research was just beginning to mand artifacts necessarily represent a source of system-
deal with sophisticated reliability and validity issues. atic (vs. random) error.
Although Sawyer's treatise was an intelligent treatment 3. Given concerns about the real or presumed un-
of the subject in step with conventional wisdom in other desirable consequences of demand artifacts, consumer
disciplines, a reappraisal of demand artifacts in con- researchers often conduct postexperimental inquiries
sumer research is now needed. In this article we consider to assess hypothesis guessing and then delete guessers
tacit but widespread views among consumer researchers from subsequent statistical analyses. This approach, we
about the prevalence, consequences, and control of de- argue, is based on the dubious assumption that subjects
mand artifacts. Our argument is as follows. necessarily are demand biased because they appear to
1. Consumer researchers regard demand artifacts as have guessed the experimental hypothesis.
a commonplace if not inevitable characteristic of ex- This article is organized as follows. In the next section
perimental research. This view follows from the con- we clarify terminology and explore why the issue of
viction that (1) demand cues persist in experiments and demand artifacts is so troubling to researchers. We then
promote hypothesis guessing, (2) hypothesis guessing specify the necessary conditions for demand artifacts
alters subjects' natural (unbiased) response tendencies, and, in this context, introduce a well-known experiment
and (3) aggregate results are biased in a hypothesis-con- in consumer behavior as a concrete illustration for
firming (i.e., theory-supporting) direction. much of the remaining analysis. Finally, in separate
sections, we evaluate three major suppositions about
the consequences and control of demand artifacts.
*Terence A. Shimp is professor of marketing at the University of
South Carolina, Columbia, SC 29208. Eva M. Hyatt is assistant pro- THE NATURE OF DEMAND
fessor of marketing at Appalachian State University, Boone, NC
28608, and David J. Snyder is an assistant professor of marketing at
ARTIFACTS
Illinois State University, Normal, IL 61761. Our sincere appreciation
is extended to three reviewers for their challenging and valuable com-
It is important to make clear distinctions between
ments, to editors Rich Lutz and Kent Monroe for their helpful input, the related terms demand characteristics and demand
and to the following individuals for their reactions to various drafts artifacts. Demand characteristics refer here only to the
of the manuscript: Chris Allen, Bill Bearden, David Brinberg, Daniel cues present in an experiment that may convey an ex-
Feldman, Morris Holbrook, Donnie Lichtenstein, Tom Madden, Paul
perimental hypothesis to subjects. For example, an ex-
Miniard, Randy Rose, Alan Sawyer, and Joe Urbany.
perimenter's verbal instructions are a potential demand
273
?3 1991 by JOURNAL OF CONSUMER RESEARCH, Inc. * Vol. 18 * December 1991
All rights reserved. 0093-5301/92/1803-0002$2.00

This content downloaded from 88.255.99.25 on Sun, 15 Mar 2020 12:24:48 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
274 JOURNAL OF CONSUMER RESEARCH

cue. Demand artifacts, on the other hand, refer to the the effect of one theoretical construct on another, the
bias itself, the "error of inference regarding the cause preconditions necessary for demand artifacts limit the
of an observed effect" (Kruglanski 1975, p. 103). Here- likelihood that any given subject will be demand biased.
after, demand artifacts and demand bias are used in- Indeed, the original argument on which the accusation
terchangeably but separately from demand character- of widespread demand artifacts is based-that the role
istics and demand cues. expectations of experimenter and subject are well de-
fined, that student subjects have a strong desire to see
The Troublesome Nature of experiments they participate in make a scientific con-
tribution, and that they are motivated to figure out and
Demand Artifacts
validate the experimental hypothesis (Orne 1962)-is
Because behavioral laboratories are pristine and ster- itself founded on a set of questionable and unsupported
ile in comparison with natural environments, experi- premises (cf. Berkowitz and Donnerstein 1982, p. 250).
mental treatments typically are prominent. As such,
subjects can be expected to make causal judgments
NECESSARY CONDITIONS FOR
about the purpose of manipulations and their role in
an experiment. Indeed, in all capacities of life, people DEMAND ARTIFACTS
tend to ascribe causes to effects, or, more technically, Three conditions must exist for a subject to be de-
to make judgments of probable cause (Einhorn and mand biased.2 First, the subject must encode a demand
Hogarth 1986). It is precisely this tendency that makes cue that would alert him or her to the research hypoth-
demand artifacts so troubling to behavioral scientists. esis. Second, s/he must discern the correct research hy-
On the one hand, the experimenter (E) wishes to make pothesis or guess another hypothesis that is incidentally
a scientific causal claim along the lines, "Treatment correlated with the true research hypothesis.3 Third,
variable X has Z amount of effect on criterion variable s/he must act on the hypothesis by conforming to a cer-
Y." On the other hand, the subject (S) has reasons to tain role that leads to biased responses on dependent-
make his or her own causal judgment, albeit an informal variable measures. In equation form,
one involving subvocal queries along the lines: "Why
am I here? What am I supposed to be doing? What does Pr(Bi) = Pr(E1) X Pr(D1 I Ei) X Pr(AI IDi), (1)
this person want from me?" If S judges that E's apparent
hypothesis is supposed to cause how he or she is to be- where Pr(Bi) = probability that the ith subject will be
have, then S may act on the hypothesis, behaving dif- demand biased; Pr(Ei) = probability of encoding a de-
ferently than s/he otherwise might and thereby biasing
mand cue; Pr(D1/Ei) = conditional probability of dis-
cerning the true experimental hypothesis or a correlated
the data on which E relies to make his or her causal
claim.
hypothesis; and Pr(A1l/Di) = conditional probability of
acting on the hypothesis.
The credibility of E's preferred explanation, or causal
This multiplicative function stresses that all three
conclusion, therefore hinges on discounting the alter-
conditions must apply for a subject to be demand
native explanation that subjects discerned the experi-
biased. Moreover, it shows that the overall probability
mental hypothesis (i.e., judged it to be the intended
of demand bias is constrained by the probability of the
cause of their behavior) and complied with it. Unfor-
least likely event-as we shall see, a very important
tunately, from E's perspective, this threat is not easy to
consideration indeed.
dismiss if an experimental treatment really does affect
S's causal judgment because it stands out and represents
a difference-in-a-background factor (Einhorn and Ho-
2The first two preconditions are related to steps two (receptivity)
garth 1986). E's judgment about a treatment variable's and three (motivation) in a model of the psychological process un-
cause is thereby reduced by the gross strength of an derlying demand artifacts (Rosnow and Aiken 1973; Rosnow and
alternative demand-artifacts explanation.' That is, the
Davis 1977).
3Although an incorrectly conjectured hypothesis might be inde-
stronger the gross strength of a demand-artifacts expla-
pendent of the content of the actual research hypothesis, this incorrect
nation, the weaker is the net strength of E's preferred
hypothesis may be problematic, nonetheless, if the direction of the
"X causes Y" explanation. Given doubts about the net response suggested by the incorrect hypothesis is correlated with that
strength of X-causes- Y claims, critics often challenge suggested by the research hypothesis itself. For example, in a classical
experiments on grounds that putative cause-effect conditioning experiment, the correct research hypothesis (i.e., the
hypothesis predicted by theory) is that the repeated pairing of con-
claims are indefensible.
ditioned and unconditioned stimuli will promote positive attitude
While such challenges are necessary to ensure that formation toward the neutral conditioned stimulus by virtue of the
researchers are not facile in drawing conclusions about contingency relation established. However, subjects in a classical
conditioning experiment may conjecture, incorrectly, that they are
to evaluate an attitude object favorably simply because of its repeated
'A potential cause, or cue to causality, has both gross and net occurrence (i.e., the incorrect hypothesis corresponds to the scientific
strengths. Gross strength is its strength in the absence of other cues notion of a mere exposure effect). Hence, although these hypotheses
to causality, whereas its net strength is reduced by the gross strength are independent of one another in content, both predict response
of other cues (Einhorn and Hogarth 1986). behavior in the same direction.

This content downloaded from 88.255.99.25 on Sun, 15 Mar 2020 12:24:48 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CRITICAL APPRAISAL OF DEMAND ARTIFACTS 275

We elaborate on these conditions in the following mental hypothesis. Undoubtedly, subjects do formulate
sections. To facilitate the discussion, we use as a ref- and act on some hypothesis about an experiment's pur-
erence point an experiment by Gorn (1982) that has pose, but the conjectured hypothesis is highly idiosyn-
been subjected to charges of demand artifacts on two cratic and, typically, incorrect (Carlopio et al. 1983).
occasions in JCR (Allen and Madden 1985; Kellaris However, as in the case of encoding, the probability
and Cox 1989).4 In brief, in a first experiment Gorn that subjects will discern the hypothesis is a function
presented subjects with a slide of a light blue or beige of the particular environment. Simplistic experiments
writing pen (the conditioned stimulus [CS]) while si- and transparent instructions or procedures increase the
multaneously playing background music (the uncon- odds that subjects will guess the hypothesis correctly.
ditioned stimulus [US]). Music from the movie Grease In classical conditioning experiments involving multiple
served as a positive US, and classical Indian music pro- trials, for example, subjects are most likely to guess the
vided a negative US. After exposure to the pen and mu- experimental hypothesis when no filler material is in-
sic combination, subjects selected either a light blue or terspersed between trials to confuse hypothesis guessing
beige pen as a gift for having participated in the exper- (see Stuart, Shimp, and Engle 1987).
iment; this choice measured the conditioned effect. In Gorn's classical conditioning work and in related
Congruent with conditioning expectations, 79 percent experiments in consumer research involving a single-
of the subjects picked the pen color associated with the trial condition, evidence suggests that subjects rarely
positive music, whereas only 30 percent picked the pen discern the experimental hypothesis. In their thorough
color associated with the negative music. attempt to ascertain the amount of hypothesis guessing
There are several reasons for suspecting that Gorn's Allen and Madden (1985) found "little indication that
results are vulnerable to demand artifacts (cf. Allen and participants recognized the hypothesized relationship
Madden 1985; Kellaris and Cox 1989). First, subjects between the affective valence of the humorous material
were run in two groups, and the first group may have and their pen choices" (p. 309). Kellaris and Cox (1989)
discussed the study between classes with the second determined that the percentage of subjects who correctly
group. Second, because the study was rather straight- discerned the experimental hypothesis (i.e., that music
forward (no confederates, no complicated procedure, would affect the choice of pen color) ranged from a low
etc.), subjects may have suspected that the music was of 0.3 percent in experiment I to a high of 13.6 percent
intended to influence their choice. Third, subjects' in experiment 3. These low values support the claim of
choice of pen color may have been biased because of Carlopio et al. (1983) that the ventured hypothesis is
the obtrusiveness of the choice task. Finally, as college typically incorrect.
students in a classroom, subjects might have been ap-
prehensive or inclined to play the good-subject role,
Condition 3: Acting on the Hypothesis
affirming the experimenter's hypothesis. We note before
continuing that these claims are plausible but not nec- Demand bias cannot materialize unless subjects act
essarily correct. on the surmised experimental hypothesis. Four types
of role enactment have been identified, the first two of
Condition 1: Encoding a Demand Cue which are in a hypothesis-confirming direction: good
The initiating condition for demand bias is that a subjects attempt to confirm the hypothesis so as to ad-
subject must encode a demand cue that provides him vance knowledge or to pursue other noble goals; ap-
or her with a basis for discerning the experimental hy- prehensive subjects do the same to avoid appearing wit-
pothesis. In general, demand-cue encoding is the most less or to create a positive impression; negative subjects
probable of the three conditions. Subjects are likely to attempt to disconfirm the hypothesis; and faithful sub-
detect demand cues in sterile laboratory environments. jects act on their own inclinations rather than alter be-
In Gorn's ( 1982) experiments, it is virtually certain that havior in response to a surmised hypothesis (Sawyer
most subjects would have encoded the simultaneous 1975).
display of the pen and rendition of the music. Gorn's Although much has been written about the various
cover story may have heightened this awareness because subject roles (see, e.g., Berkowitz and Donnerstein
he told subjects that the study dealt with the role of 1982), there is limited evidence that these roles are
music in advertising. widely enacted. Orne's (1962) claim that subjects act
out the good-subject role by behaving in a way that
Condition 2: Discerning the Hypothesis supports the experimenter's hypothesis is basically un-
supported (Kruglanski 1975; Silverman 1977; Weber
Having encoded a demand cue, or cue to causality,
and Cook 1972). Apprehensive role playing clearly is
a subject must use this perception to guess the experi-
the most frequently enacted of the four roles (Weber
and Cook 1972), but, even so, the evidence is mixed
4Subsequent discussion will focus only on Kellaris and Cox's (1989)
challenge to Gorn because Allen and Madden's (1985) creative re-
regarding this role's prevalence (e.g., see Burkart 1975;
search employed humor as the unconditioned stimulus (US) and, Christensen 1982; Henchy and Glass 1968; Innes and
therefore, lacks direct comparability with Gorn's use of music as US. Young 1975; Minor 1970; Rosenberg 1969; Silverman

This content downloaded from 88.255.99.25 on Sun, 15 Mar 2020 12:24:48 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
276 JOURNAL OF CONSUMER RESEARCH

1977; Turner and Simons 1974; Weber and Cook 1972). Kellaris and Cox conducted two experiments (experi-
Documentation concerning negative role playing is in- ments 1 and 3) and a nonexperiment (experiment 2).6
consistent and statistically suspect (Greenberg and Fol- Although their two experiments, especially experiment
ger 1988); this role is of limited interest anyway because 3, replicated the procedures in Gorn's first experiment
claims of demand artifacts are typically predicated on with only minor modifications, neither replication sup-
the assumption that subjects act in a theory-supporting ported Gorn's finding that music conditioned pen-color
direction, that is, either as good or apprehensive sub- preference. However, subjects in the nonexperiment
jects. who were asked to imagine themselves listening to "a
Again returning to Gorn's (1982) experiment, one very pleasant, likable piece of upbeat music taken from
cannot plausibly argue that his business-student subjects a popular film" were significantly more likely to select
selected pen colors to advance science or that they felt the advertised pen color than were subjects who imag-
compelled to make a good impression on the experi- ined themselves listening to "a rather unpleasant piece
menter. Likewise, one would have difficulty arguing that of Indian classical music that most people would dis-
Allen and Madden's (1985) and Kellaris and Cox's like." Does the fact that Kellaris and Cox could not
(1989) nonsupportive results were due to subjects acting replicate Gorn's findings in their experiments but could
in a contrary, disconfirming manner. do so in a nonexperiment suggest the possibility that
Gorn's results may have been due to demand artifacts
COMMON SUPPOSITIONS ABOUT and not to conditioning?
This certainly is what these authors have insinuated
DEMAND ARTIFACTS
and apparently what others have gleaned from their ar-
Having identified the fundamental issues involved in ticle (e.g., see n. 4 in Bruner 1990). In the following we
the demand-artifacts controversy, we now appraise challenge Kellaris and Cox's demand-artifacts inter-
three suppositions that extend, if only tacitly, from the pretation of Gorn's results and argue more generally
view that demand artifacts are prevalent in experimental against the tendency to accept too readily demand-ar-
consumer research: (1) that failure to replicate prior tifact explanations for nonreplicated results.
experimental findings may indicate demand artifacts First, although Kellaris and Cox were conscientious
are responsible for the initial findings; (2) that putative and clever in their effort to replicate Gorn's study, their
theory-supporting evidence actually may represent little music selections serving as US were not identical to
more than false-positive readings due to the presence Gorn's. Although we cannot identify any obviously
of demand artifacts; and (3) that demand artifacts can crucial differences, basic research has established that
be controlled by conducting postexperimental inquiries slight changes in CS-US combinations can alter the
and deleting hypothesis guessers. likelihood, rate, and magnitude of conditioning (e.g.,
Domjan and Burkhard 1986; Swartz 1989).
Second, the fact that Kellaris and Cox's nonexperi-
Supposition 1: Failure to Replicate Indicates
ment supports Gorn's findings is not in itself convincing
Demand Artifacts
evidence that Gorn's results were due to demand arti-
When an experiment is replicated, chances are that facts. It is well-known that nonexperiments produce a
the exact or even similar findings will not be obtained special mental set that is unique to role-playing subjects
(cf. Epstein 1980). This can be explained by at least five (Kruglanski 1975). That Kellaris and Cox's nonexper-
factors, including improper replication (e.g., nonequiv- iment obtained results congenial with Gorn's original
alent manipulations), nonrobust theory, the presence findings may simply establish that the nonexperiment
of demand artifacts in the original or replicated data, worked as it should and that subjects readily surmised
sampling effects, and laboratory effects.5 These multiple that the experimenter expected them to select (not se-
possibilities notwithstanding, consumer researchers lect) the pen color associated with the appealing (un-
tend to attribute failed replications to demand artifacts appealing) music. Another possibility is that the subjects
or theory frailties while overlooking quirky sampling in the nonexperiment merely predicted their own be-
and laboratory effects. havior without any attempt at guessing what the ex-
Kellaris and Cox's (1989) challenge to Gorn (1982) perimenter expected. In either case, Kellaris and Cox's
is a typical demand-artifacts explanation for nonequiv-
alent results between original and replicated experi-
6In a nonexperiment subjects listen to a description of an experi-
ments. In an attempt to replicate Gorn's findings (or, mental treatment and then are asked how they would respond to the
alternatively, to examine the robustness of his results), treatment. Nonexperiments implicitly encourage subjects to surmise
the experimental hypothesis and act on it. The purpose is to ascertain
whether an actual experiment might be susceptible to demand arti-
5Laboratory effects involve differences across experiments in such facts. If a nonexperiment fails to replicate a true experiment, demand
context-specific factors as physical and temporal conditions, exper- artifacts can be ruled out as a cause for the true experiment's results;
imenters, and procedures. It is hard to control or even assess the yet, if a nonexperiment replicates a true experiment, this does not
magnitude of laboratory effects (cf. Epstein 1980; see also Rosenthal necessarily mean that the experiment includes a demand artifact. For
and Rubin 1980). another application of nonexperiments, see Lim and Summers (1984).

This content downloaded from 88.255.99.25 on Sun, 15 Mar 2020 12:24:48 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CRITICAL APPRAISAL OF DEMAND ARTIFACTS 277

nonexperimental results are not probative regarding the TABLE 1

matter of whether Gorn's findings are demand biased. DATA AND ESTIMATES BASED ON KELLARIS
A final challenge can be mounted on the basis of the AND COX'S EXPERIMENT 2
logic Kellaris and Cox employ when speculating that
Gorn's findings reflect demand artifacts rather than Pen choice (B)

conditioned behavior. They argue that the absence of


Choice of Choice of
significance in their two actual experiments indicates
advertised nonadvertised
that pen-color preference was not conditioned by music Music appeal (A) pen (B1i) pen (B2) Total
and that the significant relationship in their nonexper-
iment between the music description and pen-color A. Actual data:a

choice had to be due to demand artifacts. They therefore Liked (Al) 45 25 70


Disliked (A2) 24 42 66
go on to suggest that Gorn's significant results were
themselves probably due to demand artifacts. We argue, Total 69 67 136
on the other hand, that, if their replications are not
B. Estimated data:b
demand biased, then Gorn's results probably are not
Liked (Al) 45 25 70
demand biased either since, as already noted, Kellaris Disliked (A2) 24 42 66
and Cox's experiments are close approximations of
Gorn's. Total 69 67 136
Consider first Kellaris and Cox's experiment 1, in
aData are from Ke
which a postexperimental inquiry found that only one bData are based on Kellaris and Cox's measure of 29 percent hypothesis
of 299 subjects guessed the experimental hypothesis. guessers and the assumption that 100 percent of guessers enacted a hypothesis-
The fact that fewer than one-half of 1 percent of the confirming role; X2 = 10.63, p <.05.

subjects discerned the research hypothesis is proof pos-


itive that demand artifacts could not have influenced
findings obtained in this initial experiment. However, acted on the hypothesis as good or apprehensive sub-
a more appropriate comparison is experiment 3, which jects. Taken together, this yields a probability of .29
more closely matched Gorn's experiment. In this ex- that subjects would have been demand biased (i.e.,
periment, in which Gorn's own cover story was used, Pr(Bi) = 1 X .29 X 1). If this probability is applied to
Kellaris and Cox determined that 13.6 percent of the all 136 subjects who participated in experiment 2, up
subjects (12 of 88) guessed the hypothesis. This, of to 39 could have been demand biased (i.e., .29 X 136).
course, simply establishes that about one of seven sub- On the basis of the row marginals in the actual data
jects may have been demand biased. Even for these (i.e., 70 subjects exposed to the "liked" and 66 to the
subjects bias ultimately depends on their enacting hy- "disliked" music; part A), it can be deduced that 20 of
pothesis-supporting behavior in the role of good or ap- the 39 demand-biased subjects would have been exposed
prehensive subjects. By making assumptions about the to the liked and 19 to the disliked music. Additionally
probability of each of the three demand-biasing events assuming that the remaining 50 liked and 47 disliked
(i.e., Ei, D1/Ei, A1/Di; see Eq. 1), it is possible to re- nondemand-biased subjects made pen choices at ran-
construct Kellaris and Cox's data in experiment 3 and dom (since they were not demand biased and could not
ascertain what their results would have been if all hy- have been conditioned by the nonexperiment), we ob-
pothesis guessers had acted on the hypothesis and be- tain the frequency counts in part B by adding the 20
come demand biased. and 19 demand-biased subjects to the numbers of non-
biased subjects in the good-subject-congruent cells (i.e.,
Building Demand Bias into Kellaris and Cox's Data. Al B 1 and A2B2). That is, good and apprehensive sub-
In justifying assumptions about these probabilities, it jects exposed to the liked (disliked) music should have
is useful first to examine data from their nonexperiment chosen the advertised (nonadvertised) pen color. Given
(experiment 2). Part A of Table 1 presents actual data these assumptions, the data in part B perfectly replicate
from Kellaris and Cox's nonexperiment. Part B, which the actual data in part A.
for reasons explained below is identical to part A, es- Our logic thus provides an appropriate estimate of
timates what the data would have looked like if all hy- the maximum number of subjects who could have been
pothesis guessers had been demand biased. The recon- demand biased in experiment 3. Part A of Table 2 re-
structed data (part B) are based on two assumptions produces Kellaris and Cox's results, while part B esti-
and one fact: (1) the probability is 1 that subjects would mates what the results would have looked like under
have encoded a demand cue in this intentionally trans- the assumption that 100 percent of hypothesis guessers
parent nonexperiment; (2) the probability is .29 that were indeed demand biased. The data in part B are
subjects discerned the hypothesis-a fact based on Kel- based on the same two assumptions made above; how-
laris and Cox's own data indicating that 29 percent of ever, the probability of discerning the hypothesis (i.e.,
their nonexperimental subjects guessed the hypothesis; Pr(Dl/Ei)) now is set at the lower level of .136, which
and (3) the probability is 1 that subjects would have is the percent of hypothesis guessers in the relevant

This content downloaded from 88.255.99.25 on Sun, 15 Mar 2020 12:24:48 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
278 JOURNAL OF CONSUMER RESEARCH

TABLE 2 TABLE 3

DATA AND ESTIMATES BASED ON KELLARIS DATA AND ESTIMATES BASED ON GORN'S EXPERIMENT 1
AND COX'S EXPERIMENT 3

Pen choice (B)


Pen choice (B)
Choice of Choice of
Choice of Choice of advertised nonadvertised
advertised nonadvertised Music appeal (A) pen (B1) pen (B2) Total
Music appeal (A) pen (B1) pen (B2) Total
A. Actual data:a
A. Actual data:a Liked (Al) 74 20 94
Liked (Al) 22 19 41 Disliked (A2) 30 71 101
Disliked (A2) 23 24 47
Total 104 91 195
Total 45 43 88
B. Estimated data:b
B. Estimated data:b Liked (Al) 61 33 94
Liked (Al) 25 16 41 Disliked (A2) 44 57 101
Disliked (A2) 20 27 47
Total 105 90 195
Total 45 43 88
aData are from Gor
aData are from bData are based on Kellaris and Cox's measure of
Kellaris 13.6 percent hypothesis
and Cox
NS. guessers and the assumption that 100 percent of guessers enacted a hypothesis-
bData are based on Kellaris and Cox's measure of 13.6 percent hypothesis confirming role; x2 = 8.90, p < .01.
guessers and the assumption that 100 percent of guessers enacted a hypothesis-
confirming role; x2 = 2.97, p < .1.

evidence anything other than demand artifacts. More


Gorn-procedure condition of Kellaris and Cox's ex- will be said about this shortly.
periment 2. If the probability of the other two demand- Removing Demand Bias from Gorn's Data. Re-
biasing events (i.e., Pr(Ei) and Pr(Al/Di)) is assumed to versing the above process, we can investigate what
be 1, then Pr(Bi) is .136. Gorn's (1982) results would have looked like if the pu-
With this estimate, a maximum of 12 subjects (.136
tatively demand-biased subjects in his frequency table
X 88) could have been demand biased, with six subjects
were removed from the demand-congruent cells. The
exposed to the liked music version and six to the disliked
data from his first experiment are displayed in part A
music version. Under the additional assumption that
of Table 3. Because Gorn did not report the specific
some subjects may have been influenced by the exper-
incidence of hypothesis guessing, we assume that per-
imental treatments, the 76 remaining nondemand-
cent to be the same as in Kellaris and Cox's experiment
biased subjects are allocated to the four cells exactly in
3 in which Gorn's cover story was used, namely, 13.6
proportion to what Kellaris and Cox's actual data (part
percent.
A) reveal. For example, of the 35 unbiased subjects who
With this assumption, part B of Table 3 shows that
were exposed to liked music, 54 percent, or 19 subjects,
potentially 27 subjects would have been demand biased
should have chosen the advertised pen. Adding the six (i.e.,.136 X 195). Proportionately, 13 would have been
demand-biased subjects to cell Al B 1 (the demand-con- exposed to the liked music and 14 to the disliked music.
gruent cell) results in an estimate of 25 subjects who
Removing these demand-biased subjects from the de-
would have selected the advertised pen after listening mand-congruent cells (Al B 1 and A2B2) yields a fre-
to appealing music. Similarly, adding the six demand-
quency distribution that remains statistically significant
biased subjects in the disliked music condition who, (x2 = 8.90, p < .0 1). In other words, even allowing the
acting as good or apprehensive subjects, would have
possibility that 27 of Gorn's subjects chose pen colors
selected the nonadvertised pen results in an estimate of
acting as good or apprehensive subjects, the results are
27 subjects in cell A2B2.
nevertheless statistically significant, because sufficient
On the basis of these- assumptions, part B shows a numbers of nondemand-biased subjects responded in
marginally significant relationship between music ap- a conditioning-congruent fashion. Thus, Gorn's original
peal and pen choice (X2 = 2.97; p < .1). This demand- conclusion that his data evidence classical conditioning
biased result indicates, by implication, that Kellaris and is sustained.
Cox's actual data from experiment 3 also would have
yielded a statistically significant relationship had those Section Summary. These reconstructed results
data been demand biased to the magnitude indicated show that statistically significant relations are obtained
by the proportion of hypothesis guessers. Thus, the fact after building demand artifacts into the data from Kel-
that the actual data (Table 2, part A) show no significant laris and Cox's experiment 3. Thus, their original data
relationship indicates that Kellaris and Cox's results would themselves have been statistically significant had

This content downloaded from 88.255.99.25 on Sun, 15 Mar 2020 12:24:48 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CRITICAL APPRAISAL OF DEMAND ARTIFACTS 279

their experiments contained demand-biased subjects to iments, as well as much other consumer research. Ep-
the extent suggested by their postexperimental evidence stein (1980, p. 793) cogently expresses the problem as
of hypothesis guessing. Furthermore, on removing po- follows: "Behavior observed on a single occasion,
tentially demand-biased subjects from Gorn's data whether in the laboratory or elsewhere, is apt to be so
through the reverse process, we show that his results situationally unique as to be incapable of establishing
still warrant a nonartifactual, classical conditioning ex- reliable generalizations that hold over even the most
planation. minor variations in the situation. To the extent that
The fact that Kellaris and Cox's results are not sta- this is true, it follows that the laboratory study as nor-
tistically significant indicates (1) that pen choice in their mally conducted is often unreplicable." This assertion
experiments was not influenced by music appeal and, has received support from related work in consumer
hence, failed to evidence conditioning and (2) that de- research (Lastovicka and Joachimsthaler 1988). The
mand artifacts did not bias their results. Hence, because implication is clear: single measures of complex behav-
Kellaris and Cox's replications reveal no evidence of iors are as unreliable as single-item measures of attitudes
demand artifacts, it is only logical to conclude that and other psychological constructs.
Gorn's findings, too, are probably more attributable to
successful classical conditioning than to demand arti-
Supposition 2: Demand Artifacts Create
facts.7 It is beyond the scope of this article to explain
why conditioning occurred in Gorn's experiments but
False-Positive Readings
not in Kellaris and Cox's. As noted earlier, basic dif- Measurement errors, both random and systematic,
ferences in the choice of US may account for the fact are pervasive in behavioral research (cf. Cote and
that near-equivalent experiments sometimes do not Buckley 1987, 1988). Although both forms of error af-
yield comparable results. Also, the possibility remains fect conclusions regarding the true relation between
that Gorn's results are artifactual even though, as we theoretical constructs, systematic errors are more prob-
have shown, Kellaris and Cox's research does not sus- lematic in that they attenuate or inflate estimates of
tain this conclusion. relationships, whereas random errors only attenuate
More generally, this article shows that it is easier to observed relations (Cote and Buckley 1988). Thus,
assert than to justify a demand-artifacts-based indict- whether demand bias represents random or systematic
ment of a nonreplicated experiment. Furthermore, us- error holds important implications for how journal re-
ing demand artifacts to explain nonreplicated results viewers and other critics apply claims of demand arti-
may amount to supplanting a more probable sampling- facts in judging theory tests.8
or laboratory-effects explanation with a less probable It has been conventional to see demand cues as sys-
demand-artifacts explanation. The issue of sampling ef- tematically inflating observed scores on dependent
fects requires no commentary here, but some brief re- variables in a theory-supporting direction.9 However,
marks about laboratory effects are in order. In partic- the notion that demand characteristics produce sys-
ular, no matter how similar two experiments may tematic bias necessarily implies that subjects guess the
appear, the fact always remains that differences between same, or a similar, hypothesis and enact the same hy-
experimenters, laboratory conditions, time of day, time pothesis-supporting role(s), thus ultimately affecting
of semester, time of year, and so on can dramatically aggregate behavior in a uniform direction (Kruglanski
affect experimental outcomes. In addition, experimental 1975). For subjects to discern the same hypothesis and
findings are inherently unstable when results are based act the same way is, as previously noted, improbable;
on single items of data, as is the case with the pen-color indeed, the direction of bias is inconsistent even in
choice measure in Gorn and Kellaris and Cox's exper- studies in which subjects are given the true hypothesis
(Kruglanski 1975). Yet experimental data are likely to
be compromised by systematic demand effects when
7Because Gorn employed what, on the surface, appears to be a
cues are present that both (1) arouse concern about how
more obtrusive measure of pen selection than did Kellaris and Cox
in their replication, it could be claimed that his experiment is more one is to be appraised and (2) provide hints about ap-
susceptible to demand bias than our position has acknowledged. propriate responses for obtaining favorable evaluations
However, we would argue that the pen-selection procedure in Gorn's from experimenters (Fromkin and Streufert 1976).
experiment may have been less, not more, obtrusive than Kellaris Arousal cues are present when subjects sense that
and Cox's procedure. Whereas Gorn's subjects left their seats en masse
(thereby providing a sense of obscurity) and selected a preferred pen
their personalities, intelligence, or judgment is being
color from one of two boxes located on opposite sides of the room, appraised, as is the case when subjects are run individ-
Kellaris and Cox's subjects individually selected a preferred pen color
from their seats as a box containing both pen colors was passed around
the room. It therefore is possible that Kellaris and Cox's subjects 8We note that the term demand bias suggests by definition that the
were more likely than Gorn's to think that their choice was being error is systematic; however, this usage is a matter of tradition and
observed and recorded. As such, Kellaris and Cox's observation pro- is not necessarily appropriate.
cedure actually may have been more reactive, more likely to prompt 9The theory-supporting qualification is made here on the premise
evaluation apprehension, and hence more biasing than Gorn's (cf. that consumer researchers are more concerned with preventing false-
Kazdin 1982). positive than false-negative results.

This content downloaded from 88.255.99.25 on Sun, 15 Mar 2020 12:24:48 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
280 JOURNAL OF CONSUMER RESEARCH

ually or given the impression that their individual per- imental inquiries (PEIs) and delete subjects who appear
formance is important. Appropriate-response cues are to have surmised the experimental hypothesis. It seems
most common when frequent or continuous feedback to be widely accepted that postexperimental measure-
is given based on subject performance (cf. Gergen 1965) ment of hypothesis guessing controls the problem of
or when the experimenter makes the purpose of the demand artifacts. However, as noted above, this as-
experiment transparent. sumes that hypothesis guessing can be measured validly
In cases in which both arousal and appropriate-re- and that hypothesis guessing necessarily leads to hy-
sponse cues are present, some subjects can be expected pothesis-confirming role playing. Both assumptions are
to respond in a uniform fashion, thereby producing a questionable in that the measurement of hypothesis
systematic response bias between treatment groups if guessing is tricky and potentially invalid (see Gorn, Ja-
cues are correlated with treatment conditions. However, cobs, and Mana 1987), and role playing, if undertaken
when only an arousal cue is present, subjects must gen- at all, need not materialize in a hypothesis-confirming
erate their own notions of an appropriate response. direction.
Since subsets of subjects would formulate different no- Thus, our position is that the PEI, rather than elim-
tions of an appropriate response and since errors across inate bias, may in fact introduce another form of bias
subsets would generally offset one another, the resulting that is systematically related to the dependent variable.
overall response error would be random rather than Specifically, hypothesis-guessing subjects may system-
systematic. atically differ from nonguessers in being more alert, in-
It is most appropriate, then, to invoke demand ar- telligent, and sophisticated, in having a higher need for
tifacts to account for theory-supporting results in cases cognition, and so on. Therefore, in a between-subjects
in which it is likely that a treatment group's scores erred design, subjects in the treatment group who remain after
systematically because all or, more reasonably, some of hypothesis guessers have been removed may be fun-
the subjects enacted a hypothesis-confirming role. But damentally different (less alert, etc.) than subjects in
this, unfortunately, is not easy to demonstrate. The im- the control group against whom they are compared,
plicit assumption that hypothesis guessing necessarily since, by definition, only subjects in experimental
results in demand artifacts is problematic, for all hy- groups have an opportunity to guess the experimental
pothesis guessers do not enact the same role. It may be hypothesis and be deleted. Stated alternatively, the pool
that theory-supporting experiments should not be the of treatment-group subjects on whose responses statis-
only, or even primary, target of consumer researchers' tical analyses are performed (i.e., the nonguessers) may
apprehension about demand artifacts. Rather, in view not be representative of the population to which the
of the well-known bias against the null hypothesis (At- experimenter generalizes findings. Consequently, re-
kinson, Furlong, and Wampold 1982; Greenwald 1975), moving hypothesis guessers may lead to systematic dif-
concerns about demand artifacts might more properly ferences between comparison groups along the lines of
be directed at file drawers of unsubmitted studies in the selection-bias threat to internal validity noted by
which the theory was not supported because demand- Cook and Campbell (1979, p. 5 3). In addition to threat-
based random errors attenuated observed relations be- ening internal validity, removing hypothesis guessers
tween theoretical constructs. may also adversely affect an experiment's external va-
Lest we be misinterpreted as suggesting that theory- lidity and in turn compromise its construct validity (cf.
supporting results can never be ascribed to demand ar- Lynch 1982).
tifacts, let us note that, while it is unlikely that large Because it can never be known with certainty whether
numbers of subjects are demand biased in competently the subset of data without hypothesis guessers is more
conducted experiments, the possibility remains that a or less biased than the full data set, albeit in different
small proportion of demand-biased subjects may sway ways, it is probably most prudent to analyze experi-
experimental findings in a theory-supporting direction. mental data both with and without hypothesis guessers.
Unfortunately, this recognition brings no solution with In the event that statistical conclusions are incongruous,
it, for no simple solution is possible. The canonical pro- it would then be appropriate for consumer researchers
cedure for eliminating demand bias in consumer re- to note the differences. Readers could draw their own
search has been postexperimental measurement and conclusions regarding the possible reasons for and im-
removal of hypothesis guessers, but this approach is port of the inconsistencies.
predicated on the dubious assumptions that hypothesis
guessing can be measured validly and that hypothesis
DISCUSSION
guessers necessarily enact hypothesis-confirming roles.
The publication process invariably involves some
Supposition 3: Deleting Hypothesis Guessers friction between authors and the editors and reviewers
who are the gatekeepers responsible for assuring that
Controls the Problem
authors' theory-supporting results do not have alter-
The most common method in consumer research for native explanations. This interaction is healthy insofar
dealing with demand artifacts is to perform postexper- as it leads to published articles that are more circum-

This content downloaded from 88.255.99.25 on Sun, 15 Mar 2020 12:24:48 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CRITICAL APPRAISAL OF DEMAND ARTIFACTS 281

spect than they otherwise might be. However, demand The wording of questions and the context in which
artifacts are often accentuated as a source of error to questions appear can affect the responses to question-
the exclusion of the myriad other errors that are just as naires and interviews (Bradburn 1982). Respondents
likely, or perhaps more likely, to jeopardize the validity may sense what the researcher is getting at and alter
and generalizability of experimental results. For ex- their responses to accommodate what they think the
ample, idiosyncratic subject states (e.g., mood) and ex- researcher expects. In-depth interviews in the interpre-
perimental contextual conditions, or laboratory effects tivist tradition are particularly susceptible to demand-
(e.g., time of day, day of week, laboratory atmospherics), type artifacts. The same individual often interviews
undoubtedly affect how subjects respond to experimen- numerous participants, and though in strict naturalistic-
tal stimuli; however, these factors are typically assumed inquiry terms the researcher has no a priori agenda or
away. hypotheses (Lincoln and Guba 1985), it is only human
Another potentially unhealthy offshoot of the em- to have expectations about the research outcome or to
phasis on demand artifacts is that otherwise meritorious form expectations during the course of the, research.
studies are challenged on grounds that they are fatally Strong rapport often develops between a researcher and
flawed by demand artifacts. Gatekeepers sometimes as- informant during an in-depth interview, rapport that
sert that manuscripts are unacceptable because of de- may encourage the informant to be especially concerned
mand artifacts, without articulating exactly how such with the impression s/he conveys to the researcher.
artifacts might have occurred, and it is easier for critics When informants say what they think the researcher
to raise the specter of demand bias than it is for re- wants to hear, the bias threatens an ethnographic study's
searchers to counter such claims. For example, an integrity every bit as much as demand artifacts jeop-
anonymous reviewer of a different paper commented ardize the validity and generalizability of experimental
that "those of us who believe in practicing safe science results in the laboratory (see Wallendorf and Belk 1989).
would contend that it is prudent to place the onus on The observation method also is susceptible to de-
the experimenter to show that [results are not demand mand-type bias, particularly when observations are ob-
biased]." Although on the surface this comment is ir- trusive (Kazdin 1982). Obtrusive observation evokes
refutable (who does not want to practice safe science?), reactivity since people sometimes alter their behavior
it imposes an impossible task on experimenters. How when aware that they are being observed. Just as in the
is one to prove that his or her results are not demand case of experimental demand artifacts, obtrusive ob-
biased? Certainly, as we have argued, conducting PEIs servation can influence apprehensive subjects to alter
and deleting hypothesis guessers does not solve the their behavior so as to be viewed in a more socially
problem, because the measurement of hypothesis desirable light (Kazdin 1982).
guessing has questionable validity and the act of hy- The point here is to emphasize that something par-
pothesis guessing, even if measured validly, is not allel to demand artifacts is a fact of research life re-
equivalent to being demand biased. Moreover, deleting gardless of which data-collection method is used. In
hypothesis guessers may itself create a form of system- keeping with our earlier probable-cause (Einhorn and
atic bias that is more insidious than the presumed bias Hogarth 1986) account of demand artifacts in the lab-
thought to be associated with demand artifacts. Al- oratory, we do not mean to suggest now that the po-
though consumer researchers believe they are doing the tential for demand artifacts is equivalent within and
right thing when they conduct PEIs and remove hy- outside the laboratory; the point, instead, is that many
pothesis guessers, this behavior may merely serve to of the issues are similar. Perhaps it is time for researchers
give the impression of safe science and thereby assuage to accept the fact that experiments are not all that dif-
peer criticism. 1 ferent from other data-collection methods; indeed, de-
mand-cue encoding, hypothesis conjecturing, and role
Demand Artifacts beyond the Laboratory enacting are universal phenomena.
The concept of demand artifacts has its roots in the
domain of laboratory experimentation, and it is here Some Final Caveats
where consumer researchers' primary concerns remain.
In pointing out that demand-type biasing crosses all
It is important to recognize, however, that biasing akin
modes of data collection we do not mean to imply that
to demand artifacts is possible in any form of data col-
researchers need not be concerned with demand arti-
lection that both arouses respondents' concerns for how
facts in experimental consumer research. Rather, the
they are being evaluated and provides cues to appro-
priate response behavior.
purpose of this article has been to confront tacit beliefs
among consumer researchers regarding the supposed
consequences and appropriate control of demand ar-
"0This is not to suggest that PEIs have no role in consumer research.tifacts. At the same time it is important to caution
Indeed, the PEI is invaluable at the pretesting and pilot testing stages
of the research process (Lim and Summers 1984), and in the final
against any tendency to use our arguments in unin-
experiment it can offer reassuring results by establishing that subjects tended ways. Specifically, it would be incorrect to find
did not guess the experimental hypothesis. here a claim that demand artifacts are unimportant. On

This content downloaded from 88.255.99.25 on Sun, 15 Mar 2020 12:24:48 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
282 JOURNAL OF CONSUMER RESEARCH

the contrary, any aspect of experimentation that in- 70 Construct Validation Studies," Journal of Marketing
creases measurement error, random or systematic, is a Research, 24 (August), 315-318.
matter of concern. Experimenters must attempt to and M. Ronald Buckley (1988), "Measurement Error

minimize the likelihood that subjects will discern and and Theory Testing in Consumer Research: An Illustra-
tion of the Importance of Construct Validation," Journal
act on transparent hypotheses. Various procedures for
of Consumer Research, 14 (March), 579-582.
accomplishing this have been discussed and need not
Domjan, Michael and Barbara Burkhard (1986), The Prin-
be repeated here (e.g., Rosenthal and Rosnow 1984, pp.
ciples of Learning and Behavior, Monterey, CA: Brooks/
106-107; Sawyer 1975).
Cole.
On the other hand, consumer researchers could ap-
Einhorn, Hillel J. and Robin M. Hogarth (1986), "Judging
propriately use our arguments to fend off unjustified Probable Cause," Psychological Bulletin, 99 (1), 3-19.
accusations when critics (1) challenge an experiment Epstein, Seymour (1980), "The Stability of Behavior. II. Im-
on grounds that it is demand biased without articulating plications for Psychological Research," American Psy-
how it is biased, (2) discount theory-supporting results chologist, 35 (September), 790-806.
as actually due to demand artifacts, or (3) claim that Fromkin, Howard L. and Siegfried Streufert (1976), "Labo-
an experiment is fatally flawed science just because a ratory Experimentation," in Handbook of Industrial and
PEI has not been performed and hypothesis guessers Organizational Psychology, ed. Marvin D. Dunnette,
removed. Although it would be imprudent for consumer Chicago: Rand McNally, 415-465.
researchers to summarily dismiss demand artifacts and Gergen, Kenneth J. (1965), "The Effects of Interaction Goals

assume that they never threaten the validity of exper- and Personalistic Feedback on the Presentation of Self,"
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1 (5), 413-
imental findings, accusations of demand artifacts must
424.
be made judiciously to ensure that the presumption of
Gorn, Gerald J. (1982), "The Effects of Music in Advertising
demand bias does not overrule reason.
on Choice Behavior: A Classical Conditioning Ap-
proach," Journal of Marketing, 46 (Winter), 94-10 1.
[Received March 1990. Revised April 1991.] , W. J. Jacobs, and Michael J. Mana (1987), "Obser-
vations on Awareness and Conditioning," in Advances
in Consumer Research, Vol. 14, ed. Melanie Wallendorf
REFERENCES
and Paul F. Anderson, Provo, UT: Association for Con-
Allen, Chris T. and Thomas J. Madden (1985), "A Closer sumer Research, 415-416.
Look at Classical Conditioning," Journal of Consumer Greenberg, Jerald and Robert Folger (1988), Controversial
Research, 12 (December), 301-315. Issues in Social Research Methods, New York: Springer.
Atkinson, Donald R., Michael J. Furlong, and Bruce E. Greenwald, Anthony G. (1975), "Consequences of Prejudice
Wampold (1982), "Statistical Significance, Reviewer against the Null Hypothesis," Psychological Bulletin, 82
Evaluations, and the Scientific Process: Is There a (Sta- (January), 1-20.
tistically) Significant Relationship?" Journal of Coun- Henchy, Thomas and David C. Glass (1968), "Evaluation
seling Psychology, 29 (March), 189-194. Apprehension and Social Facilitation of Dominant and
Berkowitz, Leonard and Edward Donnerstein (1982), "Ex- Subordinate Responses," Journal of Personality and So-
ternal Validity Is More Than Skin Deep: Some Answers cial Psychology, 10 (December), 446-454.
to Criticisms of Laboratory Experiments," American
Innes, John M. and Roger F. Young (1975), "The Effect of
Psychologist, 37 (March), 245-257.
Presence of an Audience, Evaluation Apprehension, and
Bradburn, N. M. (1982), "Question Wording Effects in Sur-
Objective Self-Awareness on Learning," Journal of Ex-
veys," in Question Framing and Response Consistency,
perimental Social Psychology, 11 (January), 35-42.
ed. Robin M. Hogarth, San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 65-
Kazdin, Alan E. (1982), "Observer Effects: Reactivity of Di-
76.
rect Observation," in Using Observers to Study Behavior,
Bruner, Gordon C. (1990), "Music, Mood, and Marketing,"
ed. Donald P. Hartmann, San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 5-
Journal of Marketing, 54 (October), 94-104.
19.
Burkart, Barry R. (1975), "Apprehension about Evaluation,
Kellaris, James J. and Anthony D. Cox (1989), "The Effects
Paralanguage Cues, and the Experimental-Bias Effect,"
Psychological Reports, 39 (August), 15-23. of Background Music in Advertising: A Reassessment,"
Carlopio, James, John G. Adair, R. C. L. Lindsay, and Barry Journal of Consumer Research, 16 (June), 113-118.
Spinner (1983), "Avoiding Artifact in the Search for Bias: Kruglanski, Arie W. (1975), "The Human Subject in the Psy-
The Importance of Assessing Subjects' Perceptions of the chology Experiment: Fact and Artifact," in Advances in
Experiment," Journal of Personality and Social Psy- Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 8, ed. L. Berkowitz,
chology, 44 (April), 693-701. Orlando, FL: Academic Press, 101-147.
Christensen, Larry (1982), "Examination of Subject Roles: Lastovicka, John L. and Erich A. Joachimsthaler (1988),
A Critique of Carlston and Cohen," Personality and So- "Improving the Detection of Personality-Behavior Re-
cial Psychology Bulletin, 8 (September), 579-583. lationships in Consumer Research," Journal of Consumer
Cook, Thomas D. and Donald T. Campbell (1979), Quasi- Research, 14 (March), 583-587.
Experimentation: Design and Analysis Issues for Field Lim, Jeen-Su and John 0. Summers (1984), "A Non-exper-
Settings, Boston: Houghton Mifflin. imental Investigation of Demand Artifacts in a Personal
Cote, Joseph A. and M. Ronald Buckley (1987), "Estimating Selling Experiment," Journal of Marketing Research, 21
Trait, Method, and Error Variance: Generalizing across (August), 251-258.

This content downloaded from 88.255.99.25 on Sun, 15 Mar 2020 12:24:48 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
CRITICAL APPRAISAL OF DEMAND ARTIFACTS 283

Lincoln, Yvonna S. and Egon G. Guba (1985), Naturalistic and Daniel J. Davis (1977), "Demand Characteristics
Inquiry, Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. and the Psychological Experiment," Et cetera, 34 (Sep-
Lynch, John G., Jr. (1982), "On the External Validity of Ex- tember), 301-313.
periments in Consumer Research," Journal of Consumer Sawyer, Alan G. (1975), "Demand Artifacts in Laboratory
Research, 9 (December), 225-239. Experiments in Consumer Research," Journal of Con-
Minor, Marshall W. (1970), "Experimenter-Expectancy Effect sumer Research, 1 (March), 20-30.
as a Function of Evaluation Apprehension," Journal of Silverman, I. (1977), The Human Subject in the Psychological
Personality and Social Psychology, 15 (August), 326- Laboratory, New York: Pergamon.
332. Stuart, Elnora W., Terence A. Shimp, and Randall W. Engle
Orne, Martin T. (1962), "On the Social Psychology of the (1987), "Classical Conditioning of Consumer Attitudes:
Psychological Experiment: With Particular Reference to Four Experiments in an Advertising Context," Journal
Demand Characteristics and Their Implications," Amer- of Consumer Research, 14 (December), 334-349.
ican Psychologist, 17 (November), 776-783. Swartz, Barry (1989), Psychology of Learning and Behavior,
Rosenberg, M. J. (1969), "The Conditions and Consequences New York: Norton.
of Evaluation Apprehension," in Artifact in Behavioral Turner, Charles W. and Lynn Stanley Simons (1974), "'Effects of
Research, ed. R. Rosenthal and R. L. Rosnow, New York: Subject Sophistication and Evaluation Apprehension on Ag-
Academic Press, 280-350. gressive Responses to Weapons," Journal of Personality and
Rosenthal, Robert and Ralph L. Rosnow (1984), Essentials Social Psychology, 30 (September), 341-348.
ofBehavioral Research: Methods and Data Analysis, New Wallendorf, Melanie and Russell W. Belk (1989), "Assessing
York: McGraw-Hill. Trustworthiness in Naturalistic Consumer Research," in In-
and Donald B. Rubin (1980), "Comparing Within- terpretive Consumer Research, ed. Elizabeth C. Hirschman,
and Between-Subjects Studies," Sociological Methods Provo, UT: Association for Consumer Research, 69-84.
and Research, 9 (August), 127-136. Weber, Stephen J. and Thomas D. Cook (1972), "Subject Effects
Rosnow, Ralph L. and Leona S. Aiken (1973), "Mediation in Laboratory Research: An Examination of Subject Roles,
of Artifacts in Behavioral Research," Journal of Exper- Demand Characteristics, and Valid Inference," Psycholog-
imental Social Psychology, 9 (May), 181-201. ical Bulletin, 77 (April), 273-295.

This content downloaded from 88.255.99.25 on Sun, 15 Mar 2020 12:24:48 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen