Sie sind auf Seite 1von 17

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/227613153

John Stuart Mill's utilitarianism and the social ethics of sustainable


development

Article  in  European Journal of the History of Economic Thought · September 1997


DOI: 10.1080/10427719700000063 · Source: RePEc

CITATIONS READS

14 6,714

1 author:

Martin Paul O'Connor


Université de Paris Saclay - UPSay, FRANCE
320 PUBLICATIONS   3,169 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

The Virtual Eco-innovation FAIRGROUND (in ePLANETe) View project

Ecological Political Economy View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Martin Paul O'Connor on 26 December 2014.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 1

Abstract
John Stuart Mill's
Utilitarianism This paper considers the writings of John Stuart
and the Mill in political philosophy and political economy as
a prototype for ideals of a "sustainable
Social Ethics of development" grounded in a norm of justice and
social solidarity.
Sustainable Development
Mill's conception of a just "stationary state" of
society is examined alongside his attempts to
reconcile precepts of non-interference (individual
freedom) and private property, with the constraints
© MARTIN O'CONNOR and obligations of social, economic, and ecological
Professeur en Sciences Economiques coexistence.
It is shown that notwithstanding vacillations, Mill
CENTRE INTERNATIONAL REEDS, UNIVERSITE
ends up espousing an ethical norm of reciprocity
DE VERSAILLES ST QUENTIN-EN-YVELINES
and solidarity that is quite different from the
(UVSQ) RAMBOUILLET, FRANCE premise of self-interest axiomatised in most
economic models of competitive market
ADDRESS FOR CORRESPONDENCE : economies.

Martin.O-Connor@reeds.uvsq.fr These intuitions about a duty of care


complementary to the non-interference principle,
when systematised, are shown to find a new
contemporary application to questions of economic
justice and environmental sustainability.

Table of Contents NOTE: This document is a slightly abridged


version of the paper published under the
Table of Contents ..................................................... 1 same title, "J.S. MILL’S UTILITARIANISM AND THE
Abstract ..................................................................... 1 SOCIAL ETHICS OF SUSTAINABLE
1. John Stuart Mill and the paradigm of DEVELOPMENT", THE EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF
"sustainable development" ..................................... 2 THE HISTORY OF ECONOMIC THOUGHT, 4(3),
PP.478-506, 1997. It reflects thus the state of
2. Sustainable development and inter-temporal
solidarity .................................................................... 2 the literature at the time of writing (1995).
3. John Stuart Mill's ideal (stationary-state) No attempt has been made to update the
society........................................................................ 4 paper; however the List of References has
4. Liberty, individuality and solidarity (in a been amended to correct small errors and to
civilised society) ....................................................... 6 specify the published versions of papers
5. Individuality and reciprocity: the Hegelian and articles not yet in print when the paper
critique of utilitarianism ......................................... 10 was submitted in 1995.
6. From an ethic of solidarity to policies for A French version, whose argument is
sustainability ........................................................... 11
substantially the same, was published as
7. Acknowledgements ........................................... 12 O’CONNOR M., "LA RECIPROCITE INTROUVABLE :
8. References.......................................................... 13 L'UTILITARISME DE JOHN STUART MILL ET LA
9. Notes ................................................................... 15 RECHERCHE D'UNE ETHIQUE POUR LA
SOUTENABILITE" ECONOMIE APPLIQUEE 48 (2),
PP. 273-305, 1995.
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 2

reconcilable with norms of freedom and "self-interest" so


much valorised in the West.

1. John Stuart Mill and the paradigm Section 2 gives a brief recapitulation of the
emergence, since the 1960s, of the environmental crisis
of "sustainable development" as a problem of inter-temporal distributional justice or of
social and economic solidarity.
The writings of John Stuart Mill in political Section 3 outlines Mill's conception of a just
philosophy and political economy constitute a "stationary state" of society as he articulates it in his
sophisticated attempt to furnish a libertarian principle as Principles of Political Economy
the cornerstone of a just and progressive Section 4 examines his attempts to reconcile
social/economic order. For Mill this ideal society is, his favoured precepts of non-interference (individual
broadly speaking, an economic "stationary state", of a freedom) and private property, with the constraints and
society whose ethics and politics are informed by a obligations of social, economic, and ecological
mature appreciation and practice of utilitarian principles. coexistence. It is shown that he ends up, especially in
And these principles are, he further proposes, grounded his final essay on Utilitarianism (written in 1861),
in some fundamental laws or characteristics of human espousing an ethical norm of reciprocity and solidarity
nature. So, as was argued more than 20 years ago by that is fundamentally different from the premise of self-
Herman Daly (1973), Mill provides, in the synthesis of interest axiomatised in most economic models of
his writings, a sort of prototype of the ideals of a competitive market economies.
"sustainable development" grounded in a norm of justice
and solidarity embracing all of humanity. Section 5 discusses critically some of the
lacunae of Mill's theory of justice and solidarity,
Ethics and economics have never entirely particularly relating to his conception of reciprocity in a
gotten divorced from each other (see Sen 1987); and utilitarian society.
questions of ethics and the environment, and of
intergenerational fairness in particular, have been Section 6 concludes by showing how his
canvassed extensively over the past two decades (see intuitions about a duty of care complementary to the
Page 1977, 1991; Howarth 1994, 1997; Faucheux & non-interference principle, may be fleshed out in
O’Connor (eds) 1997; and Brown Weiss 1989 for application to contemporary questions of economic
indicative references). Yet newer is not necessarily justice and environmental sustainability.
better. Most of the founding contributors to political
economy, from Mandeville to Marx, were at pains to
elucidate ethical pre-requisites for the good (or bad)
functioning of the emerging liberal-capitalist economies. 2. Sustainable development
In this age of rapid obsolescence (and also post- and inter-temporal solidarity
modern nostalgia for all things lost) we can benefit from
reconsidering contemporary preoccupations in historical
1
perspective. The object of this paper is to show is that Human concern for degradation of the living
John Stuart Mill (and, as it happens, also Hegel before environment is not a new phenomenon, nor peculiar to
him) anticipated cogently some of the key contradictions Western industrial economies. However, the form taken
in the vision of a liberal society founded on self- by "environmental crisis" is distinctive in each society,
interested utilitarian principles. Mill's work is particularly for reasons of culture, technology and scale. The
pertinent to contemporary problems of the environment contemporary environmental crisis is, increasingly,
and public policy because he addressed at length the recognised as "global" in character and as distinctively
problem of how to reconcile ethical norms of individual associated with the dynamism of the West. Today's
freedom with requirements of social solidarity in a finite "problems of the environment" arise primarily in the
(planetary) living space. He provides a much more context of the expansion, on a world scale, of industrial
sophisticated "libertarianism" than one finds in, for production, mass-commodity-consumption, and various
example, the axiomatic normative formulations of forms of rapid transport and telecommunication. The
"market-led" social change, minimalist government, and 1960s saw a growing agitation across the affluent North
entrepreneurial-consumer sovereignty of the Austrian countries at the poisoning of urban and rural habitats
and Chicago Schools of economics. Moreover his occasioned by economic growth and consumerism.
discursive, yet clear, style of argumentation furnishes an This "habitat" and quality-of-life concern was overtaken
antidote to the mathematical axiomatisation that has in the 1970s by the oil-supply "energy crisis," and
become de rigeur in much of the "social choice theory" related preoccupations with natural resource depletion.
of today. People of the South countries, meanwhile, were
So, by reconsidering how Mill sought to salvage mounting wide-ranging protests at the depredation of
a just yet liberal society out of the rudeness and their natural resource base (including renewable
excesses of 19th century capitalism, we can get some sources such as fisheries and forests as well as mineral
insights into the problem of whether, and on what basis, wealth) -- a sort of "ecological unequal exchange" that
the collective social objectives of distributional justice has helped fuel economic growth in the North without
and of economic and ecological sustainability, might be distributing very fairly the so-called gains-from-trade.
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 3

The 1990s look to be the decade of "global ecology" achieving an "optimal [ = Pareto-efficient] use of scarce
issues, partly because of the planetary proportions of resources" (cf. the widely used text by Pearce & Turner
some of the ecological impacts (climate change, ozone 1990). However, while allocative efficiency may
layer depletion, accumulation of metal toxins, nuclear generally speaking be desirable, the primary issues are
waste disposal, etc.), and also because of the inter- distributional in character. What is the appropriate
nationalisation of the politics of the environment as distribution of "rights" to use of the environment --
epitomised by the UNCED Rio de Janeiro Conference in between rich and poor; between present and future;
2
1992 and the wrangles over the greening of the GATT. between tribal versus industrial users; for subsistence
versus exports; and so on? Such questions must,
The question of economic and ecological
strictly speaking, be addressed prior to efforts to
sustainability poses major challenges to the established
improve social efficiency of resource use, because
economic analysis traditions, and also to political
"correct" resource and environmental amenity valuation
institutions for the resolution of conflicts associated with
-- that is, assessment of the opportunity costs on-the-
management of the environment as a scarce and
margin -- will, according to established theory, depend
contested domain. In this respect, the contemporary
significantly on the assumptions made about "rights" or
environmental problems represent not only a major
"endowment" distribution (for example the rights of
economic crisis of raw materials and services supply,
indigenous social groups to maintain a viable natural
but also a new crisis of legitimacy for the market system
resource base outside of the monetary economy, and
and for liberal political philosophy.
the interests of future generations who are not
3
The challenges to economic analysis may be represented in today's marketplaces).
understood as relating to the requirement of
In the economics literature, the environmental
internalisation of a domain which had, until recently,
and economic sustainability objective is usually stated
axiomatically been excluded from the scope of
as an objective of ensuring that the needs or interests of
economic value theory. Recall, for example, what David
"future generations" are, in some sense of the words,
Ricardo wrote at the beginning of the 19th century, 4
fairly or adequately provided for. In this respect,
describing (Ricardo 1951, p.69) not only the
sustainability embodies a normative criterion of inter-
"indestructible" powers of the land but also the
generational equity of access to natural resources,
abundance of nature's free gifts. "The brewer, the
environmental amenity, and life-support services (cf.
distiller, the dyer," he said, "make incessant use of their
Page 1997, 1991; Daly 1989, 1992; Faucheux, Muir &
air and water for the production of their commodities;
O’Connor 1997; Howarth 1994, 1997; Norgaard &
but as the supply is boundless, they bear no price."
Howarth 1991; Howarth & Norgaard 1993; Marini &
Modern price theory has been constructed on the
Scaramozzini 1996; Pezzey 1997). There exist very
foundation of this axiomatic free-gift/free-disposal
real scientific difficulties in trying to give reliable
assumption (see Perrings 1987; O'Connor 1993a,
quantitative estimates of the sorts of "trade-offs"
1994b, 1996). But it is no longer remotely plausible to
involved in pursuing this goal, in view of ecosystem
treat the raw materials and "services" -- source, site,
complexities and uncertainties of many sorts. The
scenery, and sink -- furnished by nature as
challenges posed at the level of political process,
indestructible and/or non-scarce.
decisionmaking, and institutions for conflict resolution,
This requirement for "internalisation" may be are even greater.
considered in both political and economic dimensions.
In particular, the question arises of the extent to
The political dimension refers to the need for institutional
which collective social objectives of equity and
mechanisms for resolution of conflicts over access to
environmental sustainability -- which must be expressed
raw materials and environmental services generally (see
not just locally but also at the level of whole societies
for example Opschoor & van der Straaten 1993; van
and of the international community as a whole -- can be
der Straaten 1997; Dragun & O'Connor 1993; O’Connor
reconciled with norms of freedom and "self-interest"
1997). This requirement at the political level will be the
widely valorised in the West. This is an old question of
underlying theme of this paper. Economists, however,
individual rights and duties, virtue and vice, licence and
have typically approached the problem of
public order, that has preoccupied Western political
"internalisation" in terms of the idea of "correct prices"
philosophy for many centuries. The widespread appeal
for environmental goods and services reflecting the
of the modern "market economy" lies in the freedoms it
opportunity costs of their use. For example, exploitation
provides for individual choices, wealth accumulation,
of a natural resource today implies a reduction in what is
entrepreneurship, and innovation. But in the
or might be available for use tomorrow. Similarly,
sustainability context, this is also liberty to withhold or
destruction of a habitat or of life-support functions of an
withdraw from the legacy to the future without giving
ecosystem through pollution discharges, whether on a
anything back -- except perhaps piles of toxic wastes
global or on a local scale, impairs the capacity of that
(see Catton 1989; O'Connor 1993b, 1994b).
ecosystem to deliver services such as amenity, clean air
and water, and thriving plant and animal populations into The argument in this paper will be that
the future. Thus, the future generations' access to achieving sustainability would depend on resource
environmental sources of well-being is neither management choices made on behalf of future
"exogenously given" nor indestructible. Economists will generations, investments whose payoff is diffusely
often speak, in this sort of context, of the importance of distributed into the future. The delivery of such benefits
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 4

requires conscious policy action. It cannot be expected and injustices" of existing societies. The ideal would be
as an outcome of competitive markets, partly because that a division deemed equitable be made, and
the benefits are diffusely distributed (and hence hard to thereafter "individuals would be left to their own
quantify as well as hard to capture payment for), but exertions and to the ordinary chances, for making an
more particularly because under competitive pressures advantageous use of what was assigned to them"
there are strong commercial incentives to engage in (ibid.). Moreover, even if the legitimacy of a system of
"beggar the future" behaviour in order to reduce costs private property hinges on "that equitable principle, of
(and thus improve cash flow or profitability) or augment proportion between remuneration and exertion" (ibid.,
individual benefits in the present. The idea of market p.209), this is not an end in itself. Rather, proposes Mill
prices supporting an intertemporal efficient resource (ibid., p.210), it has merely an instrumental justification
allocation depends on the "internalisation" of all costs in relation to the desire for individual liberty:
and benefits by actors in the marketplace. This
presumes (inter alia) the existence of markets allowing
trades of all goods and use rights amongst all "After the means of subsistence are
consumers/owners. For the timescales, resources, and assured, the next in strength of the
effects of relevance to environmental sustainability, personal wants of human beings is
supposing we were to accord future generations some liberty; and (unlike the physical wants,
"property rights," real markets linking the future to the which as civilization advances become
now cannot exist. If we accept that future generations more moderate and more amenable to
do have an "interest" in present-day resource use even control) it increases instead of
though these interested parties do not bid in markets diminishing in intensity as the
today, then the onus is on us, the present generation, to intelligence and the moral faculties are
make purposeful provision for those to come. The more developed."
question we ask here, taking impetus from John Stuart
Mill, is how such an ethical commitment can be framed
and given practical expression within an avowedly From this, it follows that the proper goal of
"liberal" type of society. public policy and institutional design is the research of
"the greatest amount of human liberty and spontaneity"
(ibid.):

3. John Stuart Mill's ideal


(stationary-state) society "The perfection both of social
arrangements and of practical morality
would be, to secure to all persons
John Stuart Mill's writings can be understood as, complete independence and freedom
in part, an elaborate apology for "the private property of action, subject to no restriction but
system" and the freedoms of the individual, in reaction that of not doing injury to others: and
to some currents in 19th century socialism. In his guise the education which taught or the
as a social philosopher, he expounds a clear view of the social institutions which required them
underlying ethical precepts for governance and to exchange the control of their own
5
institutional arrangements in a just society. But his actions for any amount of comfort or
notion of legitimate freedoms is complex, and requires affluence, or to renounce liberty for the
careful interpretation. What will interest us first is how sake of equality, would deprive them of
Mill portrays the material (economic) basis for his one of the most elevated
"liberal" society, and why he falls upon the notion of a characteristics of human nature."
"stationary state" economy. Following from that, we will
look more closely at the ethical underpinnings of this
ideal. Similarly, in the introductory paragraphs of his
later essay On Liberty (1859, p.135), he asserts the
At the economic level, the institution of private principle:
property consists, says Mill (PPE, p.219), in "the
recognition, in each person, of a right to the exclusive
disposal of what he or she have produced by their own " .... that the sole end for which
exertions, or received either by gift or by fair agreement, mankind are warranted, individually or
without force or fraud, by those who produced it." On collectively, in interfering with the
this point Mill is close to his English precursor John liberty of action of any member of their
6
Locke, in proposing that: "The foundation of the whole number, is self-protection. That the
is in the right of producers to what they themselves have only purpose for which power can be
produced" (ibid.) On the other hand, in reality the rightfully exercised over any member of
prevailing social arrangements throughout the world are a civilized community, against his will,
arbitrary and unjust. So, Mill says (ibid., pp.201-202), "If is to prevent harm to others. His own
private property were adopted, we must presume that it good, either physical or moral, is not a
would be accompanied by none of the initial inequalities sufficient warrant. .... The only part of
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 5

the conduct of any one, for which he is alongside its productive powers. This rich view of the
amenable to society, is that which land must be kept in mind when we read, for example
concerns others. In the part which (PPE , pp.229-230):
merely concerns himself, his
independence is, of course, of right
absolute. Over himself, over his own "The essential principle of property
body and mind, the individual is being to assure to all persons what
7
sovereign." they have produced by their labour and
accumulated by their abstinence, this
principle cannot apply to what is not the
Achieving this ideal is not easy. First of all, the produce of labour, the raw material of
possibility of "non-interference" between independent the earth."
economic agents in Mill's private property-based liberal
society presumes the existence of a controllable and
exploitable external domain of nature. In this respect For this reason,
Mill is squarely in the Enlightenment tradition: the
continual development of new technologies and
scientific knowledge will ensure the progressive mastery "When the `sacredness of property' is
of nature, which will allow the possibility of Pareto- talked of, it should always be
improvements through time, namely that one man's remembered, that any such
obtaining of further improvements/property need not be sacredness does not belong in the
at the direct expense of another's interests. Building on same degree to landed property. No
this mastery premise, the non-interference precept man made the land. It is the original
expressly stipulates not an absolute "right" over private inheritance of the whole species.
property, but rather the freedoms of use and of When private property in land is not
expression subject to the obligation of avoidance of expedient, it is unjust. It is no hardship
significant injury occasioned to one individual in the to any one to be excluded from what
course of another's activity. Social progress is others have produced : they were not
8
conceived in these terms. bound to produce it for his use, and he
loses nothing by not sharing in what
In effect, Mill (as Locke before him: see
otherwise would not have existed at all.
Leclercq 1985), inveighs against delinquancy of both
But it is some hardship to be born into
nature and human nature, and exhorts the progressive
the world and to find all nature's gifts
institution, in and by society, of the moral good (justice)
previously engrossed, and no place left
grounded in an "improved" and subservient nature and a
for the newcomer...."
"perfected" human nature. But standing in the way of
this idea is the problem, clearly foreshadowed by
Thomas Hobbes (1651), of inter-personal and inter-
society conflicts in the face of material scarcity. These On the one hand, security in the rights to use of
are, in modern terminology, the difficulties of: (1) land, and compensation in the event of expropriation,
exhaustion and/or monopolisation of access to scarce should take account of the fact that "though land is not
natural capital (what Mill refers to as the "common the produce of industry, most of its valuable qualities are
heritage of all mankind") meaning likely inequities in so" (PPE, p.230). But on the other hand, "from the very
access to the finite "free gifts of nature"; (2) spillover nature of the case, whoever owns land, keeps others
effects from one appropriation, production, or out of the enjoyment of it" (PPE, p.235). What is the fair
consumption activity on another; and (3) the resolution of this antinomy? Mill doesn't give a full
distributional conflicts that come as part and parcel of answer. His own suggestion of making an equitable re-
these resource control and externality resolution issues. distribution of land -- as a "new start" for society -- would
imply either finding a substantial new domain of non-
Mill's attempted resolution of these difficulties is appropriated territory, or the repudiation of pre-existing
located at the ethical rather than technical level, and this property rights and privileges. More significantly, the
is what makes his thought on the matter still interesting question of justice in access resurfaces with the
today. In particular, he develops a vision of the human appearance of every newcomer and every new
individual as object of personal cultivation, proposing generation, inasmuch as they make new claims on the
that it is only through recourse to this dimension of society's wealth base.
"inner development" of the human individual that society
can ensure justice for all notwithstanding the constraints The scarcity and newcomer problems are
imposed by material scarcity. partially addressed by Mill through his theory of a
desirable population control and of the economic
At various points in the PPE , Mill looks at limits stationary state. It is this conception which has inspired
and qualifications to the proper domain of private many "sustainability" theorists, notably Herman Daly
property and its use. The most striking is in regard to (1973). Mill arrives upon his ideal of the "stationary
land, which for Mill is not just a factor of production but state" through an estimation of where, ultimately, the
also a natural presence having aesthetic significance "progress of social improvement" is destined to take
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 6

humankind. In Book IV of the PPE (pp.695-792) he lays improved, when minds ceased to be
out his attempt at a "Dynamics" or a "theory of motion" engrossed by the art of getting on...."
to complement the statical mode of analysis of the bulk
of his political economy. This is presented as an
enquiry into the "ultimate tendencies" of the various This vision of the economic stationary state
"progressive changes" visible in the society around him. constitutes the means by which Mill seeks to reconcile
The most evident amongst the tendencies identified by his view of social progress and individual liberty, with the
Mill is: (1) "a progress in wealth; and advancement of constraining factor of finite material basis for economic
what is called material prosperity"; and this in turn is a production activity. The key ingredient for achievement
product of two others: (2) "the perpetual, and so far as of this best of possible worlds will be the self-regulation
human foresight can extend, the unlimited, growth of exercised by the members of the society. Each
man's power over nature"; and (3) "a continual increase individual will abstain from excessive production of
in the security of person and property." The effect of population and also from competitive pursuit of material
the two latter is to bring about "a great increase of wealth -- practices which, in their accumulation, tend to
production and of accumulation" (PPE, pp.695-699). menace the security of everyone.
However, says Mill (ibid.), the translation of this
The avowed ideal, thus, is to allow the
accumulation into general prosperity is menaced by a
"individual" to prosper in the full expression of "human
countervailing tendency that is "as long continued, as
indefinite, and possibly even as rapid" as the first: liberty and spontaneity". Yet this freedom of the
(4) that for population to increase. individual is paradoxical, because it depends on having
the respect by all participants in society, of the same
Here Mill calls upon social good sense -- in basic ground rules. The benefits of the stationary state
particular the "cultivated intelligence" -- to save (human) cum liberal order will be realised only if the same self-
nature from its own worst nature. He admits on the one regulating behaviour is adopted by all (or, at least, the
hand that the "stationary state .... itself flies before us" great majority). There are, in other words, "spillover
under the impetus of improvements in the productive benefits" from self-regulating behaviour, and "increasing
arts and through "overflow of capital .... into the returns to scale" when such behaviour becomes
uncultivated and ill-cultivated regions of the earth," and sufficiently widespread. But conversely, adoption of
that there remains room in the world still "for a great self-regulating behaviour by a single individual depends
increase of population, supposing the arts of life to go on a sort of "higher" motivation to self-improvement
on improving, and capital to increase" (PPE, which may bring little or no material reward to that
pp.746-751). Yet, he insists (ibid.), saturation of the individual. Mill leaves himself here with a dilemma --
globe with people, even if well-fed, would be a world one that we can see echoed today in debates over
"from which solitude is extirpated" and "with nothing left national sovereignty, over the "right to cultural
to the spontaneous activity of nature." In other words, difference," over the relative merits of democratic/liberal
Mill cherishes what later generations of scholars and versus authoritarian versus ethnic autonomy
environmentalists will call wilderness and existence approaches to Third World societies' development, and
values. Population and production growth will, over the authority for pursuit of global environmental
increasingly, bring social and environmental costs; so sustainability goals. To what extent can the pursuit of a
what is desirable is a society that would "be content to supposed social progress (for example, environmental
be stationary, long before necessity compels them to it." sustainability defined by some criterion), be a warrant
For this state, he insists, is in another and more for cutting across individuals' and collectivities' own
important respect not stationary at all, but one notions of what is right and acceptable, in favour of a
compatible with the flowering of that most precious of privileged notion of the greater good of humanity
values, the liberty of the individual. The best state of (present and future)?
society is (ibid.):
Mill himself manages to resolve this
contradiction only partially, after a tortuous passage that
culminates in the formulation of his "Happiness Morality"
"that in which, while no one is poor, no
in the essay Utilitarianism. But although he leaves
one desires to be richer, nor has any
various questions unanswered, the issues he raises
reason to fear being thrust back by the
point clearly towards the nature of a solution that may
efforts of others to push themselves
be proposed.
forward."

And from there,


4. Liberty, individuality and solidarity
(in a civilised society)
"There would be as much scope as
ever for all kinds of mental culture, and
moral and social progress; as much Any appraisal of Mill's political philosophy and
room for improving the Art of Living, normative theory of the just society must offer a view on
and much more likelihood of its being the adequacy (or not) of his "non-interference principle"
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 7

as a precept of right action and governance. A first Book V, Chapter XI, on "the Grounds and Limits of the
concern is that the category over which this principle Laisser-Faire or Non-interference Principle". Here he
provides specific and positive guidance -- defining refers (PPE, p.943) to "a part of the life of every person
absolute liberty with regard to what Richard Wollheim who has come to years of discretion, within which the
(1973) terms purely self-regarding actions -- is relatively individuality of that person ought to reign uncontrolled
negligible. As summarised by Wollheim (1973, pp.3-4), either by any other individual or by the public
this is the argument that: "Every action that occurs collectively". This autonomous domain, he says (ibid.),
within a society and rises at all above the level of
triviality is bound to impinge upon other members of that
society," so that "the only actions that are ".... ought to include all that part which
unconditionally exempt from the jurisdiction of the state concerns only the life, whether inward
are of the order of brushing one's teeth". In this view, or outward, of the individual, and does
Mill's demarcation of actions that concern "the individual not affect the interests of others, or
only" hardly serves any purpose, and further precepts affects them only through the moral
would have to be advanced to protect the individual from influence of example."
possible encroachment by others or by the state. A
second concern, thus, is that even if significant content
can be given to the "self-regarding" category, Mill's non- We see the line being drawn, with the
interference principle furnishes no positive guidance as acceptance of "the moral influence of example" as a
to appropriate manners of resolving conflicts of interest legitimate impact made upon others. Similarly, as he
9
in the matter of "other-regarding actions". later asserts in the essay On Liberty (p.205), proper
conduct in society "consists, first, in not injuring the
The same difficulties are encountered today
interests of one another;" with the quid pro quo of,
with regard to current environmental externality and
sustainability debates -- that is, with the respective second, "each person's bearing his share (to be fixed on
problems (i) of spillover damages on the environmental some equitable principle) of the labours and sacrifices
incurred for defending the society or its members from
"commons" at local as well as global levels; and (ii) of
injury and molestation".
providing for the needs of future generations. In both
cases, in one way or another the welfare of others is And again, in the PPE (p.977), he proposes that
partially in "our" hands, meaning that resource use "anything which it is desirable should be done for the
choices involve, in the first instance, decisions about general interests of mankind or of future generations, or
(re)distribution that are not solvable in terms of a "non- for the present interests of those members of the
interference" precept. community who require external aid [the indigent, sick,
etc.], but which is not of a nature to remunerate
It seems that only reluctantly did Mill admit the
individuals or associations for undertaking it, is in itself a
need for some sort of generic precepts complementary
suitable thing to be undertaken by government". Yet the
to his non-interference principle. But there is no doubt
that he does admit it. His reluctance to enunciate legitimacy of fiscal measures needed for implementing
systematically these complementary precepts -- of, as this sort of policy, would have to arise through
consensus and "moral influence," since elsewhere in the
we will see, solidarity and care -- was perhaps partly
same work he insists, "the only cases in which
due to his awareness of the ease with which they could
government agency involves nothing of a compulsory
be perverted for paternalistic, sectarian, or totalitarian
nature, are the rare cases in which, without any artificial
motivations. Perhaps he was hesitating, feeling his way,
a sorrt of tatonnement. At any rate, his method of monopoly, it pays its own expenses" (PPE, p.944).
exposition is rather subtle, often to the point of being Finally, as we have already seen, a similar
Jesuitical and ambiguous. What we find throughout his vacillation is evident with respect to land, and more
writings is that a principle is enunciated in seeming particularly "the function of the law in defining property"
purity, but then qualified in a manner that wholly (PPE, p.797). This, says Mill, is by no means a simple
changes the principle's real meaning. thing to solve:
For example, Mill persistently complements his
non-interference principle by a normative theory of
moral progress in society. It moreover becomes clear in "It may be imagined, perhaps, that the
reading his work (and it was clear enough to Mill law has only to declare and protect the
himself) that this normative moral theory needs also to right of every one to what he has
be expressed as the level of specific public policy and himself produced, or acquired by the
governance mechanisms for resolving distributional voluntary consent, fairly obtained, of
conflicts as they emerged. So in effect, Mill gives a those who produced it. But is there
normative perspective in which one might conduct nothing recognized as property except
institutional analysis (norms of solidarity, respect, and what has been produced? Is there not
reciprocity, as we will see), even though he does not the earth itself, its forests and waters,
offer much himself in the way of practical institutional and all other natural riches, above and
design. below the surface? These are the
inheritance of the human race, and
First, let us recall what he has to say in the PPE there must be regulations for the
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 8

common enjoyment of it. What rights, are: To what extent does such an obligation of
and under what conditions, a person adaptation constitute an infringement of individuality?
shall be allowed to exercise over any To what extent is it necessary to have a collective
portion of this common inheritance (government) resolution to ensure "fair" provision or
cannot be left undecided. No function redistribution of economic opportunity across society as
of government is less optional than the circumstances change?
regulation of these things, or more
Sometimes in reading confirmed 20th century
completely involved in the idea of
libertarians, especially of Austrian subjectivist
civilized society."
persuasion, one gets the impression that a true blue
libertarian will choose death by starvation rather than to
renounce his [sic] absolute "freedom to choose". This is
Examples of contemporary environmental
an interestingly agonistic sentiment. However Mill's
externalities range from heavy metal contamination of
solution is rather different. In his last major works On
rivers and fish, up to the scale of climate change and
Liberty and Utilitarianism, we find a valiant attempt to
ozone layer destruction. Such «spillover effects» are
resolve the problem of reconciling the "free" individual
associated with all sectors of raw materials extraction,
within the social whole. Alongside re-assertions of the
industrial production, waste-disposal, or other
primacy of individual liberty, Mill adds exhortations as to
exploitative land-use. They evidently aggravate the
the merit of the moral influence of example, and further
distributional problems having to be resolved by function
intersperses assertions about the necessity of a
of government. Mill comments elsewhere (PPE, p.697)
collective political resolution of distribution questions
that, with the progress of civilised society, "Even the
based on a norm of social and economic solidarity. So,
vicissitudes of fortune which arise from inevitable natural
how may norms for harmonious collective resolution of
calamities, are more and more softened to those on
distributional conflicts be made to emerge from his non-
whom they fall, by the continual extension of the
interference/moral example virtues?
salutary practice of insurance". However, insurance can
function in this way only as long as the individual "risks" Let us start with an elucidation of what Mill
remain modest relative to society's wealth -- meaning hopes from the influence of moral example. He devotes
that there remains a solvent party against which the the whole of Chapter II of On Liberty (titled "Of the
individual claims can be brought. When the Liberty of Thought and Discussion", pp.141-183) to
viccissitudes are of the order of acid rain, radioactive defending the "non-injurious" character of such
material spillages, runaway genetic experiments, and influence. True liberty, he asserts, is enhanced not
global atmospheric perturbations, the principle of self- merely through the passive respect of another's material
insurance by any given social group runs up against property, preferences, and person (that is, non-
manifest limits. So, to repeat: How may the recognition interference and non-injury), but also through positive
of environmental scarcity and of intimate social and action of one individual on an other, the "disinterested
ecological interdependence be reconciled, in the exertion to promote the good of others". Free debate of
envisaged "stationary state," with the paramount value conflicting views constitutes a paramount opportunity of
of individual liberty and a notion of economic justice? "exchanging error for truth" (ibid., p.142), and is even
11
"No function of government is less optional than the the essential precondition of this.
regulation of these things, or more completely involved
But, it must still be asked, what constitutes this
in the idea of civilized society."
"good of others"? And how does this virtue of "good
A related problem of fairness arises in the example" furnish the basis for a just yet freedom-
context of damage or benefit to an individual's economic respecting society? In the attempt to make a reply, Mill
opportunities mediated through the price system. is finally led explicitly to formulate a conception of
Suppose that, as a result of other individuals' self- "liberty-in-solidarity" in society that is radically different --
improvement or changes in tastes, an individual and quite incompatible with -- the notion of "freedom of
experiences a drop-off in the commerce formerly individual choice" lionised by vulgar libertarian
obtained with those individuals, the benefits of which are philosophers and their "more market" flagbearers. It is
pecuniary. Mill would not allow that an injured individual to this precept of solidarity, which may be understood as
has any redress over another's changes in tastes, but a sort of duty of care, that we now turn.
he cannot deny that such reduction in opportunity may
10 In Utilitarianism (p.270) Mill states overtly that,
very often occur. The marketplace as the privileged
in the general rule, people can disregard the diffuse
nexus of voluntary transactions, indeed imposes a set of
spillover implications of their actions:
constraints and pressures on each individual, and in this
respect functions as what Warren Samuels (1992)
describes as a "system of mutual coercion". The forlorn
".... it is a misapprehension of the
individual has simply to seek new opportunities for
utilitarian mode of thought, to conceive
insertion into the web of transactions, through change in
it as implying that people should fix
vocation, through innovation, or an effort at improved
their minds upon so wide a generality
public relations. The risk of being left out thus exerts a
as the world, or society at large. The
real pressure to conformity with "what the market
great majority of good actions are
demands". The questions to be asked in this instance
intended not for the benefit of the
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 9

world, but for that of individuals, of ....; so that not only he may be unable
which the good of the world is made to conceive the possibility of happiness
up; and the thoughts of the most to himself, consistently with conduct
virtuous man need not on these opposed to the general good, but also
occasions travel beyond the particular that a direct impulse to the general
persons concerned, except so far as it good may be in every individual one of
is necessary to assure himself that in the habitual motives of action...."
benefiting them he is not violating the
rights, that is, the legitimate and
authorised expectations, of any one For a confirmed libertarian, this is a truly radical
else." notion. Social harmony is not a product of the
impersonal hand of the market, but of generous human
sentiment. Mill thus goes on to elaborate on his social
Here as so many times elsewhere, Mill ideal, and the basis for its progressive attainment, by
equivocates. On the one hand he seems to suggest appeal to a "natural basis of sentiment for utilitarian
that the problem of what we would now call "negative morality" (ibid., p.284):
externalities" is a relatively minor one. He almost seems
to make a presumption of the additive nature of the
"private" (individuals') benefits, which if too casually read "This firm foundation is that of the
could be taken as compatible with the norm of monetary social feelings of mankind; the desire to
"wealth-maximisation" via a decentralised market be in unity with our fellow-creatures,
mechanism. Of course, such a presumption of additivity which is already a powerful principle in
of individuals' actions and valuations becomes invalid human nature, and happily one of
whenever it is admitted that the "spillover impacts" of those which tend to become stronger,
individuals' actions -- that is, the simultaneous even without express inculcation, from
determination of relative prices, income distribution, and the influences of advancing
output mix in a general market equilibrium, as well as civilization."
"external" social and environmental costs and benefits --
are significant by comparison with the "private benefits"
12
as measured with status quo market prices. And in Whereas inequalities and prejudices and
fact, Mill is perfectly aware of these multiple dimensions conflicts of interest have meant, he says, the existence
of general interdependency, and of the ubiquity of of "large portions of mankind whose happiness it is still
situations where ethically sound action cannot be practicable to disregard" (ibid., p.286),
reduced simply to a matter of everyone assuring
themselves individually of "not violating the rights" of
any other party. A collective or institutional resolution of "In an improving state of the human
these issues is somewhere being presumed. In what mind, the influences are constantly on
sense? the increase, which tend to generate in
In the immediately prior passages of each individual a feeling of unity with all
Utilitarianism, Mill had enunciated in a telling way what the rest; which, if perfect, would make
he held to be the Utilitarian "standard of what is right in him never think of, or desire, any
conduct." This is, he insisted, the happiness of all beneficial condition for himself, in the
concerned. But as for the means and meaning of benefits of which they are not included.
obtaining this, there is no recourse to the quantitative [....] A person in whom the social
cost-benefit calculus of wealth-maximisation, rather an feeling is at all developed, cannot bring
appeal to human sentiments of solidarity (ibid., pp.268- himself to think of the rest of his fellow-
269): creatures as struggling rivals with him
for the means of happiness, whom he
must desire to see defeated in their
"utility would enjoin, first, that laws and object that he may succeed in his. The
deeply rooted conception which every
social arrangements should place the
individual even now has of himself as a
happiness, or (as speaking practically it
social being, tends to make him feel it
may be called) the interest, of every
one of his natural wants that there
individual, as nearly as possible in
harmony with the interest of the whole; should be harmony between his
and secondly, that education and feelings and aims and those of his
fellow-creatures."
opinion, which have so vast a power
over human character, should so use
that power as to establish in the mind
of every individual an indissoluble This "feeling of unity" together with its practical
association between his own consequences, is, says Mill, the "ultimate sanction of the
happiness and the good of the whole Happiness morality" -- that is, the empirical and logical
demonstration of its well-foundedness and coherence as
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 10

a principle of morality. theory of social ethics for sustainability. But this forces
us to ask, what substantively does Mill mean by this
In sum, Mill espouses not only a particular
reconciliation of the individual "with the interest of the
normative ideal of social harmonisation, but also an
whole"?
argument as to why and how it may progressively be
achieved. He postulates that the desire for such Apart from his allusions to a "feeling of unity,"
"harmony" is "naturally" inhering in the character of Mill himself manages only to give negative indications of
"social being" common to all human beings, and that what this might entail. For example, still in the essay on
this sentiment will come to the fore as a matter of social Utilitarianism, in expounding on the Greatest
progress. This is what allows him to assert the Happiness Principle (in Chapter II on "What
existence of the common good as the state where Utilitarianism Is," ibid., pp.262-263), he describes the
each person is obtaining "their own good" in a ideal society as providing for "an existence exempt as
harmonious society. far as possible from pain and as rich as possible in
16
enjoyments, both in point of quantity and quality...."
This presumption of a common "social feeling"
Relative to this end, he says, the prime difficulty lies in
has far-reaching consequences for the concept of
the contest with the "positive evils of life, the great
individuality and its social expression. Far from
sources of physical and mental suffering" -- such as
valorising an inviolate individuality as in modern-day
indigence, disease, and the premature loss of objects of
free-market ideology and as axiomatic in economic
affection. And, he enthuses (ibid., p.266), even if these
models of rational choice (where social order is
calamities cannot, at present, be much mitigated, the
achieved through the miraculous co-ordinating
progress of science holds out unlimited promise for
mechanism of the invisible hand), Mill places his hopes
conquest over disease and other noxious influences that
for social harmonisation on sentiments of solidarity and
cut short life, render it unendurable, or "which deprive us
reciprocity. He relies not on "self-interest" but rather on
of those in whom our happiness is wrapt up;" and thus:
the fact that individuals' tastes and preferences are
formed, not in glorious isolation but through a complex
13
process of reciprocal influence and socialisation.
"no one whose opinion deserves a
A tension arises here between ideals of moment's consideration can doubt that
solidarity and possibly irreducible differences between most of the great positive evils in the
ethical positions. This warrants separate discussion, but world are in themselves removable,
would strike off at a tangent. Suffice to say that we are and will, if human affairs continue to
offered by Mill a normative vision of a just society. In improve, be in the end reduced within
this utopia selfishness and dissension are transcended narrow limits."
through the replacement of substantive individuality (and
individual freedom) by a sort of "procedural" norm of
harmonisation. Individuality is subsumed within the The same vision flows through into the idea of
greater (and morally higher) requirement of a justice as it appears in his utilitarian morality. Justice is,
harmonisation of interests. No individual would, in this he concludes in Utilitarianism’s closing pages (Chapter
utopia, pursue any "object or contemplation" unless this IV, "On the Connection of Justice with Utility"),
be harmonised to the objects and contemplations of the simultaneously a rule of conduct and a sentiment which
14
entire social body. This subsumption of individuality- sanctions the rule. The idea of justice conveys the
in-solidarity is the kernal of Mill's notion of a just society. general sentiment that society ought to defend the
The just society is, says Mill, a society of free and individual in the possession of their rights, and against
secure equals, of individuals stripped of the injury. Thus (ibid., pp.315-316), to complement
"aristocracies of colour, race, and sex", of hereditary scientific and technological mastery,
privilege, and of distinctions as between slaves and
freemen, etc. (ibid., p.320). The equality is reconciled
with liberty through the sentiments of solidarity and "The moral rules which forbid mankind
15
reciprocity. to hurt one another (in which we must
never forget to include wrongful
interference with each other's
freedoms) are more vital to human
5. Individuality and reciprocity: the well-being than any maxims, however
Hegelian critique of utilitarianism important, which only point out the best
mode of managing some department of
human affairs. They also have the
Several obvious parallels might be drawn with peculiarity, that they are the main
premises and ideals of social justice found in element in determining the whole of the
contemporary sustainable development literature, for social feelings of mankind. It is their
example the imagining of a common future "meeting observance which alone preserves
the needs of future generations" as in the now- peace among human beings: if
celebrated Brundtland Report (WCED 1987). So, it obedience to them were not the rule,
might be proposed, Mill furnishes a sort of normative and disobedience the exception, every
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 11

one would see in every one else an commercial transaction, or a lover, or a fatal virus or a
17
enemy, against whom he must be process of uncontrolled global climate change. So
perpetually guarding himself...." Hegel's dialectical clarification actually constitutes a far-
reaching critique of "instrumental reason" and the self-
interested pursuit of the means of individual satisfaction
So, we have the idea of peaceful coexistence, a as a presumed basis for social harmony and good order.
society where each person has respect for others'
individuality (as ends-in-themselves) and each serves
The pursuit of "absolute" freedom and
the role as guarantor of security to others. But what is
spontaneity of the individual involves, Hegel makes
to stop this utopia from degenerating into a "Cold War"
clear, a neglect or attempted rejection of the reciprocal
of mutual deterrence (balance of power, balance of
obligations of coexistence. Belief in a possibility of
terror) and mutual hostage-taking?
unlimited substantive liberty is erroneous, and sooner or
G.F.W. Hegel, writing some decades before later will prove self-defeating. When an individual or
Mill, had already foreseen this paradox of the utilitarian social group sets itself up as the privileged "end" relative
metaphysics. In the Phenomenology of Spirit (first to which nature and other humans are treated as mere
published in German in 1807), Hegel insisted at length means, this tends to provoke the antithesis of
on the reciprocal dimension of "usefulness" in a body of substantive freedom -- in the form either of hostility or
codependent elements, of each element relative to all social conflict, or of a "natural" threat to progress and
18
others in the whole. This reciprocity finds its origin in security such as pollution or ecological catastrophe.
the dialectical opposition between being-in-itself and However, Hegel proposes, since man is a social (and
being-for-another, considered as two facets of the ecological) being, Reason permits that individuality need
absolute (Hegel 1977, pp.342-343): not "go beyond itself and destroy itself". What is
required is to accept one's own inevitable involvement --
for better and for worse -- in the welfare of others, as
“Both ways of viewing the positive and part and parcel of daily life. As Hegel eloquently puts it
negative relation of the finite to the in- (ibid., pp.342-343),
itself are, however, in fact equally
necessary, and everything is thus as
much something in itself as it is for an "Just as everything is useful to man, so
`other'; in other words, everything is man is useful too, and his vocation is to
useful. Everything is at the mercy of make himself a member of the group,
everything else, now lets itself be used of use for the common good and
by others and is for them, and now, so serviceable to all."
to speak, stands again on its hind legs,
is stand-offish towards the other, is for
itself, and uses the other in its turn." Here we may play on the double register of
vocation as fact of existence and as matter of ethics.
That is, what is a brute material fact of coexistence
So necessarily, as a matter of fact or of will, might also be affirmed as an ethic -- as a moral
19
individuality is radically "moderated" by the fact of obligation of reciprocation. One might even go so far
reciprocity. For each individual (ibid.), as to say (and this is not outside of the spirit of Mill's
sentiments in Utilitarianism) that, when resolved in a
social pact of reciprocity, the deepest pleasure in life
".... The extent to which he looks after comes with the sense of fulfilling this existential vocation
his own interests must also be matched of being in-the-service-of other life.
by the extent to which he serves
others, and so far as he serves others,
so far is he taking care of himself: one
hand washes the other. But wherever 6. From an ethic of solidarity to
he finds himself, there he is in his right policies for sustainability
place; he makes use of others and is
himself made use of."
Our final question is how this abstract ethic --
the idea of a vocation of reciprocal service -- might find
This sounds much like Mill's recipe of the ideal expression in real policy and institutional design for
utilitarian society. But Hegel is making no normative economic and environmental sustainability. Broadly
statements here, he is only giving a factual statement of speaking, the answer would be found in affirming
the implacably reciprocal character of the utility economic and social labours as generating wealth-in-
relationship. Willy-nilly one is (as useful object) in the common, as in the idea of a "public good" where
service of another, as much as (as subject-for-oneself) production or consumption by one person "spills over"
served by another. Depending on circumstances, this into benefits to others. This refers in particular to the
other that I find myself serving may be a partner in a wealth-in-common of the biophysical milieu as a habitat
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 12

(place of living) shared in common, and also to the idea specific ecological and amenity "protection"
of produced wealth and infrastructures as being, in decisions;
varying degrees, wealth shared in common. However,
time, labour, and economic resources expended in
this generic formulation is not, on its own, sufficient for
environmental repair and enhancement;
effective policy. In addition, there has to be a clear and
explicit recognition of the necessity of making choices infrastructures and durable public assets
as to the particular "interests" -- communal and investment;
ecological -- that are going to be sustained.
provision for extensive and ongoing community
Sustainability policy (and environmental policy more
involvement in decision making processes,
generally) is thus concerned with two dimensions of
sometimes known as "costs of democracy";
distribution: (1) What is, will be, or should be the
distribution of welfare -- that is, of wealth, of political and educational investments aimed at fostering ethics of
economic rights, of economic opportunity, and of access care and environmental interest;
to environmental benefits and amenities -- within each
generation now and into the future? And (2) How do we investments in research and technological
choose amongst the various particular economic and development intended to furnish understanding,
ecological outcomes that might be feasible within the information, and practical knowhow that may
framework of long-term sustainable activity? enhance simultaneously, the economic
opportunities and environmental security of
Provision for the "needs of future generations" generations to come.
can be assured only through choices of resource use
(investment and protection decisions) whose specific Such measures do not necessarily clash with individual
intent is to enhance the economic opportunities and liberty nor with the allocative efficiency criteria so highly
environmental security of those to come. Given that cherished in traditional neoclassical normative
sustainability -- both economic and ecological -- is not economics. Rather, they reflect goals of solidarity and
able to be assured by market forces alone (and indeed, of distributional justice. Infrastructure investments and
will often be compromised by unfettered pursuit of conservation decisions of this sort are not inconsistent
commercial opportunities), its basis has to be pursued with inter-temporal social efficiency. Rather, they can
as a matter of collective social choices and commitment. be construed as the expression of a choice to make
In effect, the requirement would be that commercial Pareto-efficient use of resources while providing for
investors and entrepreneurs should show "good" future generations' economic opportunity and
(responsible) attitudes towards their hosts -- that is, environmental security (see Howarth & Norgaard 1993;
towards the local human communities and the larger Norgaard & Howarth 1991; Mourmouras 1993; Muir
planetary community. People as investors, workers and 1995, 1996; Faucheux, Muir & O’Connor 1997). They
as citizens of their districts would be required, are resource management choices made on behalf of
collectively and individually give high priority to future generations, investments whose payoff is
maintaining the "communal conditions of life" -- habitat, distributed as a future "public good." Moreover, this
local infrastructures, community, culture, solidarities of process of "managing the trade-offs" between present
family and place, as well as workplace. In other words, and future should not be thought of a zero-sum game
the "freedoms" of the individual so much cherished by between self-interested players. On the contrary, the
Mill, are realisable only on condition of accepting as presumption has to be that environmental sustainability
complementary the corresponding duties of care. and equity of economic opportunity will consciously be
pursued as collective goals in a spirit of solidarity and
Looked at in this way, the wealth of the land and mutual good will. So, renewing old themes of John
sea, as a life-sustaining whole and source of wellbeing, Stuart Mill's, it needs to be emphasised that the
20
is first of all a wealth-in-common. Private use -- that acceptability of policy choices or proposals will depend
is, use for individual or exclusive (e.g. corporate) gain -- very much on how the process of decision making is
is subordinate to this common interest we all have. Use conducted, and on how people perceive the
for private gain is not an absolute right; it carries a respectfulness and fairness of both the process and the
corresponding burden of responsibility. The onus on outcomes of deciding the distribution of burdens,
those engaging in resource use activities geared to sacrifices, losses, and opportunities for gain or new
personal gain, is to make these activities also in the start.
service of the common good of the local communities.
This view of a duty of care actively pursued is important,
as it gives a positive expression to the achievement of
environmental objectives that have often been framed 7. Acknowledgements
negatively as constraints against exceeding some
"environmental bottom lines" or "stability threshold" or
21
"assimilative capacities" of natural systems. Such a The author thanks Richard Dawson for helpful
commitment may be given practical effect in a variety of comments on an earlier draft and also Tony Endres,
ways, partly through individual actions but more Eliot Muir at the University of Auckland. He expresses
particularly through communal and political choices, for his appreciation to the former C3E at the Université de
example: Paris I, the Institut fur Okologische Wirtschaftsforschung
gGmbH Berlin, and the European Commission’s Joint
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 13

Research Centre at Ispra Italy, for friendly support while HEGEL, G.F.W. (1807), Phenomenology of Spirit, English
the paper was being written. Finally, translation by A.V. Miller, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1977.
acknowledgements are due to Jean-François Noël (who HOBBES, Thomas (1651), Leviathan, Fontana Edition
made possible the French language version of the (1962), Edited and Abridged by John Plamenatz.
paper), to René Passet, Sylvie Faucheux and Philippe
HOWARTH, Richard (1994), "Sustainability under
Méral, and others of the Centre d’Economie et d’Ethique
Uncertainty: A Kantian Approach," paper to the International
pour l’Environnement et le Développement (C3ED). Symposium: Models of Sustainable Development , Paris,
Responsibility for the interpretations offered is the 16-18 March 1994, pre-printed pp.1005-1016 in Symposium
author’s alone. Papers Vol.II, C3E Université de Paris I.
HOWARTH, R. (1998), Sustainability, Uncertainty, and
Intergenerational Fairness’, pp.239–258 in S. Faucheux, M.
O'Connor and J. van der Straaten (eds 1997), Sustainable
8. References Development: Concepts, Rationalities, Strategies,
Dordrecht: Kluwer.

ARNOUX, Rosemary, Richard DAWSON, & Martin HOWARTH, Richard B. & Richard B. NORGAARD (1990).
O'CONNOR (1993), "The Logics of Death and Sacrifice in the "Intergenerational Resource Rights, Efficiency, and Social
Optimality", Land Economics, Vol.66, pp.1-11.
Resource Management Law Reforms of Aotearoa/New
Zealand," Journal of Economic Issues 27 (December 1993), HOWARTH, Richard B. & Richard B. NORGAARD (1992),
pp.1059-1096. "Environmental Valuation under Sustainable Development,"
American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings 80:
ASHLEY, Sir W.J. (1909), "Introduction" to John Stuart Mill's
Principles of Political Economy, Longmans, Green & Co., 473-477.
London, 1909 (reprinted 1976 by A.M. Kelly, New York). HOWARTH, Richard B. & NORGAARD, Richard B. (1993),
BROWN WEISS, E. (1989), In Fairness to Future "Intergenerational Transfers and the Social Discount Rate,"
Generations: International Law, Common Patrimony, and Environmental and Resource Economics 3: 337-358.
Intergenerational Equity, Dobbs Ferry, New York. ANDERSON, Victor & JACOBS, Michael (1991), The Green
CATTON, William R. Jr. (1989), "Cargoism and Technology Economy: Environment, Sustainable Development, and
and the Relationship of these concepts to important issues the Politics of the Future, Pluto Press, London.
such as Toxic Waste Disposal Siting," pp.99-117 in Dennis JACOBS, P. & D.A. MUNRO (Eds. 1987), Conservation
Peck (ed.), Psychosocial Effects of Hazardous Toxic with Equity: Strategies for Sustainable Development,
Waste Disposal on Communities, Charles C. Thomas, IUCN, Cambridge.
Springfield (Illinois, USA).
LATOUCHE, Serge (1991), La Planète des Naufragés, La
DALY, Herman E. (1973), "The Steady-State Economy: Découverte, Paris. (English translation: In the Wake of the
Toward a Political Economy of Biophysical Equilibrium and Affluent Society, Zed Books, London, 1993).
Moral Growth", pp.149-174 in: H.E. Daly (ed., 1973), Toward
a Steady-State Economy, W.H. Freeman, San Francisco. LECLERCQ, Gilles (1985), "A quoi sert l'état de nature?,"
pp.19-44 in: Gérard Klotz (ed.) Ordre, Nature, Propriété,
DALY 1992, «Allocation, distribution and scale: towards an Presses Universitaires de Lyon, Lyon.
economics that is efficient, just and sustainable,» Ecological
Economics 6, pp.185-193. LOCKE, John (1690), "An Essay Concerning the True
Original, Extent and End of Civil Government", reproduced
DENIS, Henri (1989), "Hegel et l'utilitarisme," Revue du pp.1-143 in: Sir Ernest Barker (ed. 1971), The Social
MAUSS No.3: 120-140. Contract: Essays by Locke, Hume, Rousseau, Oxford
DRAGUN, Andrew K. & Martin O'CONNOR (1993), "Property University Press paperback.
Rights, Public Choice and Pigovianism," Journal of Post- MACPHERSON, C.B. (1962), The Political Theory of
Keynesian Economics 16 No.1 (Fall 1993), pp.127-152. Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke, Clarendon
DUPUY, Jean-Pierre (1992), Le sacrifice et l’envie: le Press, Oxford.
libéralisme aux prises avec la justice sociale, Editions MÄLER, Karl-Göran (1985), "Welfare Economics and the
Calmann-Levy, Paris. Environment," pp.3-60 in Allen V. Kneese & James L.
FAUCHEUX, Sylvie & Martin O’CONNOR (eds 1998), Sweeney (Editors 1985), Handbook of Natural Resource and
Valuation for Sustainable Development: Methods and Energy Economics Volume I, North-Holland, Amsterdam/New
Policy Indicators, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham. York/Oxford.

FAUCHEUX, Sylvie, MUIR, Eliot & O’CONNOR, Martin MARINI, Giancarlo & Pasquale SCARAMOZZINI (1996),
(1997), «Neoclassical Natural Capital Theory and ‘Weak’ "Intergenerational Equity, Fiscal Policy and Environmental
Indicators for Sustainability,» Land Economics 73 (4), pp. Sustainability," pp.58-72 in S. Faucheux, D. Pearce & J.
Proops (eds. 1996), Models of Sustainable Development,
528-552.
Edward Elgar, Cheltenham.
GUHA, Ramachandra (1990), The Unquiet Woods:
Ecological Change and Peasant resistance in the MARTINEZ-ALIER, Juan (1991), "Ecology and the Poor: A
Himalaya, University of California Press, Berkeley. Neglected Dimension of Latin American History," Journal of
Latin American Studies 23 (No.3), 1991.
GUPTA, Anil K. (1991), "Household Survival through
Commons: Performance in an Uncertain World," Working MARTINEZ-ALIER, Juan & Martin O'Connor (1996),
Paper No.940, Indian Institute of Management, Ahmedabad ‘Distributional Issues in Ecological Economics’, in R.
380 015, India, June 1991. Costanza, O. Segura and J. Martinez-Alier (eds 1996),
Getting Down to Earth: Practical applications of
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 14

ecological economics, Washington D.C.: Island Press, Cheltenham.


pp.153-184.
O’CONNOR, Martin (1997), ‘Environmental Valuation from the
MERAL, Philippe (1997), « L’équité intergénérationnelle en Point of View of Sustainability,’ pp.149-180 in: A. Dragun & K.
économie de l’environnement : réflexion critique autour de Jacobbson (eds., 1997), Sustainability and Global
l’utilisation de la théorie de la justice de Rawls par l’analyse Environmental Policy, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham.
standard », Eeconomie Appliquée XLVIII No.2, pp.305–333.
O'CONNOR, Martin & Rosemary ARNOUX (1992),
MILL, John Stuart (1848, 7th edition 1871), Principles of "Ecologie, échange inéluctable, et éthique de l'engagement
Political Economy, with some of their applications to (Sur le don et le développement durable)," Revue du MAUSS
social philosophy, edited with an Introduction by Sir W.J. No.15-16, pp.288-309.
Ashley, Longmans, Green & Co., London, 1909 (reprinted
1976 by A.M. Kelly, New York). O'CONNOR, Martin & Eliot MUIR (1995), «Endowment
Effects in Competitive General Equilibrium: A Primer for
MILL, John Stuart (1859), On Liberty, reprinted pp.126-250 in Policy Analysts» Journal of Income Distribution 5, pp.145-
Utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill, edited with an Introduction 175.
by Mary Warnock, Collins/Fontana, 1962.
OPSCHOOR, Hans & Jan van der STRAATEN (1993),
MILL, John Stuart (1861), Utilitarianism, reprinted pp.251-321 "Sustainable Development: an institutional approach,"
in Utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill, edited with an Introduction Ecological Economics 7: 203-222.
by Mary Warnock, Collins/Fontana, 1962.
PAGE, Talbot (1977), Conservation and Economic
MOURMOURAS, Alex (1993), "Conservationist government Efficiency, John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore.
policies and intergenerational equity in an overlapping
generations model with renewable resources," Journal of PAGE, Talbot (1991), "Sustainability and the Problem of
Public Economics 51, 249-268. Valuation," pp.58-74 in Robert Costanza (Editor, 1991),
Ecological Economics: The Science and Management of
MUIR, Eliot (1995), The Question of Value: Price and Sustainability, Columbia University Press, New York/Oxford.
Output Distribution Sensitivities in General Equilibrium,
unpublished thesis for M.Sc. In Economics/Environmental PEARCE, David (1976), "The Limits of Cost-Benefit Analysis
Science, Department of Economics, University of Auckland, as a Guide to Environmental Policy," Kyklos 29: 97-112.
New Zealand. PEARCE, David (1988), "Optimal Prices for Sustainable
MUIR, Eliot (1996), "Intergenerational Wealth Distributional Development", pp.59-66 in: D. Collard, D. Pearce, & D. Ulph
Effects on Global Warming Cost-Benefit Analysis," Journal of (Editors), Economics, Growth and Sustainable
Economic Distribution, 6(2), pp.193–214. Environments: Essays in memory of Richard Lecomber,
Macmillan, London.
NORGAARD, Richard (1994), Development Betrayed,
Routledge, London. PEARCE, D. & K. TURNER (1990), Economics of Natural
Resources and the Environment, Harvester/Wheatsheaf,
NORGAARD, Richard B. & Richard B. HOWARTH (1991), Hemel Hempstead.
"Sustainability and Discounting the Future," pp.88-101 in
Robert Costanza (Editor, 1991), Ecological Economics: PERRINGS, Charles (1987). Economy and Environment: A
The Science and Management of Sustainability, Columbia Theoretical Essay on the Interdependence of Economic
University Press, New York/Oxford. and Enviromental Systems, CUP, Cambridge.

O'CONNOR, Martin (1993a), "Value System Contests and the PEZZEY, John (1997), “Sustainability Constraints versus
Appropriation of Ecological Capital," The Manchester Optimality versus Intertemporal Concern, and Axioms versus
School 61 No.4 (December 1993), pp.398-424. Data”, Land Economics 73(4), pp.448–466.

O'CONNOR, Martin (1993b), "Entropic Irreversibility and REDCLIFT, Michael (1987), Sustainable Development:
Uncontrolled Technological Change in Economy and Exploring the Contradictions, Methuen, New York.
Environment," Journal of Evolutionary Economics 3, RICARDO, David (1951), On the Principles of Political
pp.285-315. Economy and Taxation, edited by Piero Sraffa, Cambridge
O'CONNOR, Martin (1994a), "Valuing Fish in Aotearoa," University Press, Cambridge.
Environmental Values 4, 145-165. SACHS, Wolfgang (ed. 1992), The Development Dictionary:
O'CONNOR, Martin (1994b), «Entropy Liberty and A Guide to Knowledge as Power, Zed Books, London.
Catastrophe: On the Physics and Metaphysics of Waste SACHS, Wolfgang (ed. 1993), Global Ecology: A New
Disposal», pp.119–182 in Peter Burley & John Foster (eds., Arena of Political Conflict, Zed Books, London.
1994) Economics and Thermodynamics: New
Perspectives on Economic Analysis , Kluwer, Dordrect. SAMUELS, Warren J. (1992), Essays on the Economic
Role of Government: Vol.I Fundamentals; Vol.II
O'CONNOR, Martin (ed., 1994c), Is Capitalism Sustainable? Applications, Macmillan, London.
Political Economy and the Politics of Ecology, Guilford
Publications, New York. SAMUELS, Warren (1993), "On the Conclusivity of Certain
Lines of Reasoning in Economic Policy Analysis," Journal of
O'CONNOR, Martin (1995), "La Réciprocité Introuvable: Post Keynesian Economics 16: (No.2 Winter 1993-94),
L'utilitarisme de John Stuart Mill et la recherche d'une éthique pp.241–248.
pour la soutenabilité," Economie Appliquée, XLVIII No.2,
271-304. SAMUELS, Warren J. & Nicholas MERCURO (1986),
"Wealth Maximization and Judicial Decision-making: The
O'CONNOR, Martin (1996), "Cherishing the Future, Issues Further Clarified" (reply to Posner 1984),
Cherishing the Other: A ‘Post-Classical’ Theory of Value," International Review of Law and Economics 4, pp.133-137.
pp.321-344 in S. Faucheux, D. Pearce & J. Proops (eds.
1996), Models of Sustainable Development, Edward Elgar, SEN, A. (1987), On Ethics and Economics, Basil Blackwell,
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 15

Oxford.
SWANEY, J.A. (1990), "Common Property, Reciprocity and 5. The treatise on Principles of Political Economy and the essays
Community," Journal of Economic Issues 24, pp.451-62. On Liberty (1859) and Utilitarianism (1861) will serve as our main reference
texts. Works such as the System of Logic (2 volumes, 1843) are further
TOMAN, Michael, John PEZZEY & Jeffrey
indicators of the tenor of Mill's thought; and one can glean insights from
KRAUTKRAEMER (1995), "Economic Theory and
lesser tracts such as the essay on Bentham (1838). All page references to
`Sustainability'," in Daniel Bromley (ed., 1995), Handbook of
the Principles (cited for convenience henceforth as PPE) are to the 1909
Environmental Economics, Blackwell.
edition, edited and introduced by Sir W.J. Ashley (1909). This retakes with
VAN DER STRAATEN, Jan (1997), "Sustainable annotations the text of the 7th Edition (1871), the last published under Mill's
Development and Public Policy," forthcoming in S. Faucheux, own hand. Although successive editions from the 1st in 1848 show
M. O’Connor & J. van der Straaten (eds. 1997), Sustainable significant textual modifications, there is a constancy in the underlying drift
Development: Concepts, Rationalities, and Strategies, which entitles us to regard the work as contemporaneous with both his early
Kluwer, Dordrect. System of Logic and the later major works such as On Liberty and
Utilitarianism. Many commentators have focussed on problems of apparent
WCED (World Commission on Environment and Development inconsistency in different parts of Mill's writings. My purpose in this essay is
1987), Our Common Future (The Brundtland Report), to suggest an underlying coherence in the ethical preoccupations of Mill's
Oxford University Press, Oxford. argumentation, notwithstanding discrepancies at the level of detail.
WOLLHEIM, Richard (1973), "John Stuart Mill and the Limits 6. In particular, Locke's well-known Second Treatise (written about
of State Action", Social Research 40, pp.1-30. 1680, first published in 1690), titled "An Essay Concerning the True Original,
Extent and End of Civil Government." See also MacPherson (1962).
7. The same insistence on personality and cultivated intelligence,
and on liberty of expression, permeates the whole of the Principles of
9. Notes Political Economy -- for example, in Book V concerned with the proper
functions and influence of government, and notably Chapter XI, entitled "Of
the Grounds and Limits of the Laisser-Faire or Non-interference Principle".
1. It is now well known that Adam Smith, for example, founded his
optimism about the compatibility of market institutions with basic decency on 8. As he concludes his major treatise (PPE, p.979): "Even in the
a «theory of moral sentiments» which included a sophisticated notion of best state which society has yet reached, it is lamentable to think how great
people’s preoccupation about how they would appear in the eyes of others. a proportion of all the efforts and talents in the world are employed in merely
A comparison of how Smithian sympathy, self-love and vanity might -- or neutralizing one another. It is the proper end of government to reduce this
might not -- have pertinence to contemporary preoccupations for «solidarity» wretched waste to the smallest possible amount, by taking such measures
and sustainability, while not without interest, would require a separate as shall cause the energies now spent by mankind in injuring one another,
exegesis and discussion; for some indications see Dupuy (1992) and Méral or in protecting themselves against injury, to be turned to the legitimate
(1995). employment of the human faculties, that of compelling the powers of nature
to be more and more subservient to physical and moral good."
2. No single work gives a complete overview of this complex set of
issues in their historical, geographical, and theoretical dimensions. Some 9. The possibility that production of toothpaste (or other cosmetics)
useful critical perspectives include the books by Redclift (1987); Jacobs & may involve toxic by-products (cf. Catton 1989) is not precluded.
Munro (eds. 1987); M. Jacobs (1991); Norgaard (1994); Sachs (ed. 1992;
10. This is made plain, in another context, by the discussion in
ed. 1993); Faucheux & O’Connor (eds. 1998); and O'Connor (ed. 1994c).
Liberty (pp.207-208) of the "very severe penalties" in the forms of avoidance
The terms North and South are used here in their symbolic sense, roughly
of such commerce that may be imposed on an individual whose self-
equating with Rich (in per capital GDP terms) and Poor. The South and the
interested behaviours are found disagreeable by others in the society.
Third World may be regarded as approximately synonymous. On the
distinctive concerns expressed in the South -- notably the "ecology of the 11. For example (On Liberty, p.146): "There must be discussion, to
poor" and grass-roots resistance movements -- see for example Martinez- show how experience is to be interpreted. Wrong opinions and practices
Alier (1991) and Ramachandra Guha (1990). gradually yield to fact and argument; but facts and arguments, to produce
any effect, must be brought before it...."
3. For an extended discussion see Martinez-Alier & O’Connor
(1996). In a multi-good, multi-consumer, multi-input general equilibrium 12. For expanded discussions around this theme of externality and
there is simultaneous determination of the allocatively efficient output mix the institutionally decided "distribution of sacrifice" see especially Samuels
(and, hence, relative prices for inputs and outputs) with endowment (1992), Dragun & O'Connor (1993), Marrtinez-Alier & O’Connor (1996),
distribution (and, hence, income distribution). This is well established O’Connor (1997), and Arnoux, Dawson & O'Connor (1993).
theoretically (cf. Mäler 1985). However the significance for this result for the
non-separability of distributional and efficiency considerations in policy 13. We do not go into contemporary literatures axiomatising
evaluation -- most particularly when it is a matter of redistributions between postulates about dynamics of preference formation and possible altrustic
social groups having divergent consumption preferences -- has widely been behaviours. Note also that it has been asserted by some commentators on
overlooked. This point has been elucidated in rhetorical terms by Warren Mill's political philosophy writings, that the system and ideals that he
Samuels (1993; see also Samuels & Mercuro 1986), and has recently been describes are impracticable because they require too much of an admittedly
highlighted by several analysts with special reference to natural resource "imperfect" human nature. Some have suggested that Mill himself deemed
and environmental valuation through didactic use of general equilibrium a utilitarian morality to be applicable only inasmuch as human nature has
models (see notably Howarth & Norgaard 1990, 1992, 1993; O'Connor & reached a certain degree of sophistication or improvement; and that in the
Muir 1995; Muir 1995, 1996; Faucheux, Muir & O’Connor 1997). interim, "morality does not as yet apply" (Wollheim 1973, p.29). However we
here pursue, for the sake of argument, the implications of Mill's norm of
4. Thus, in the now-famous formulation in Our Common Future social solidarity. For, if the problem of reconciling freedoms of the individual
(WCED 1987, p.46), sustainable development is described as "a process of with social solidarity cannot be resolved under optimistic premises about
change in which exploitation of resources, the direction of investments, the moral commitment of individuals within society, it is unlikely to be solvable
orientation of technological development and institutional change are all in under economists' conventional assumptions of egotistical self-interest --
harmony and enhance both current and future potential to meet human which often end up in prisoners’ dilemmas. On the other hand, it is quite
needs and aspirations." possible to reject Mill's universalist postulate about "social feeling" tending to
harmony, on a variety of anthropological and philosophical grounds
M. O’CONNOR MILL'S UTILITARIANISM AND SUSTAINABLE DEVELOPMENT PAGE 16

supported by everyday observation. One might, for example, postulate non-


reconciliation of individuals amongst themselves and between social groups
as, a priori, irreducible -- and thus regard engagement in conflict, duel, war,
or other forms of antagonistic contest (with the associated griefs and
reversals) as both inevitable and honourable. This important point, which for
example is raised by Latouche (1991) in his critique of the universalist
postulates underlying contemporary Development ideology and practices, is
not further examined here.
14. The paradox is, that on the one hand the substantive content of
this collective interest is, ex ante, radically under-determined; yet on the
other hand the particular solution incarnated must come, ex post, to exercise
an over-riding weight over each individual in terms of their obligations of
respect. One can imagine that there may be, a priori, an indefinitely large
number of different regimes of "harmonised" social activity -- each one
being, we might say, a distinct eigenstate of the Millian operator of utilitarian
harmonisation. The diversity of human potential is contained in the range of
distinct possible eigenstates. But actual individuality in Mill's ideal type of
society, is constrained to modes of self-expression that are compatible with
one or other particular eigenstate.
15. Another question left unresolved here touches on the post-
modern problématique of «difference». Is the stripping of «aristocracies» a
matter of establishing «equivalence», namely all persons conforming to a
single model of humanity, such as homo oeconomicus or as defined by the
Declaration of Human Rights? Or is it a matter of disestablishing
power/privilege structures that depend on a hierarchisation of difference,
and thus promoting a richness of diverse humanities?
16. He even goes as far as to extend this to "the whole of sentient
creation," though without ever exploring what this might entail.
17. As Hegel observes (ibid.): "Different things are useful to one
another in different ways; but all things are mutually serviceable through
their own nature, viz. through being related to the Absolute in two ways, the
one positive, whereby they exist entirely on their own account, the other
negative, whereby they exist for others. The relation to absolute Being, or
religion, is therefore of all useful things the supremely useful; for it is pure
utility itself, it is this enduring being of all things, or their being-in-and-for-
themselves, and it is their downfall, or their being-for-another." I am grateful
to Henri Denis (1989) for introducing me to Hegel's thinking on this subject.
18. Formally, the postulate of absolute freedom finds its antithesis in
the fact that what is from one point of view regarded as in the service of
one's interests (one's objects and contemplations, as Mill would put it) is,
from the other point of view the source of one's downfall, rendered
subservient to another's projects and aspirations (see Hegel, ibid., pp.354-
363). For more detailed translation of this idea in application to economic
progress and ecological catastrophe, see also O'Connor (1994b).
19. This might be understood as a sort of Kantian categorical
imperative: one accepts as morally right only what one is willing to accord to
everyone else; in this case we accept to receive from and to be served by
others, in asmuch as we accept to act in the service of others. For
applications of this sort of idea with reference to ethical underpinnings of
sustainability norms, see for example Richard Howarth (1994, 1998);
O'Connor & Arnoux (1992); and Arnoux, Dawson & O'Connor (1993).
20. The idea of "common property" as wealth enjoyed in common
with rights of access shared by many members of a community with norms
of fairness, solidarity, and reciprocity, has emerged as an important theme in
recent work on institutional arrangements for environmental management.
See, for example, Gupta (1991); Quiggan (1988); Swaney (1990);
O'Connor (1994a); Méral (1995); and a flowering of studies reported at
successive conferences of the International Association for the Study of
Common Property.
21. Two well known exponents of such themes in the economics of
the environment literature are David Pearce (1976, 1988) and Herman Daly
(1973, 1992).

View publication stats

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen