Sie sind auf Seite 1von 128

FORMS OF TIME

Spring 2008

Brian Massumi
with Jason Nguyen and Mark Davis
Brian Boigon
with Izabel Gass

MANIFOLD
To the Reader
9 Izabel Gass
Brian Massumi
17 with Jason Nguyen and Mark Davis
Bergsonism Gilles Deleuze
31 reviewed by Nicholas Risteen
Kant’s Critical Philosophy Gilles Deleuze
39 reviewed by Izabel Gass
Ambiguous Etiologies
59 Robert Crawford and Federico Cavazos
Brian Boigon
69 with Izabel Gass
Architectures of Time Sanford Kwinter
77 reviewed by David Dahlbom
Duration and Simultaneity Henri Bergson
89 reviewed by Matthew Conti

Islands and Worlds Reinhold Martin


95 reviewed by Jamie Chan
Writing on Architecture Yale University
99 reviewed by Stephen Nielson
talk20 Philadelphia University of Pennsylvania
109 reviewed by Jason Nguyen
FOA Alejandro Zaera-Polo
115 reviewed by Francis Bitonti
Shrinkwrapping Vague Things Neil Denari
121 reviewed by Molly Wright Steenson
Mass Mysteria David Erdman
125 reviewed by Izabel Gass
Founding Editor-in-Chief
Izabel Gass

Associate Editors
Sanford Kwinter
Nana Last
Tait Kaplan
Joseph Lim
Nicholas Risteen
Etien Santiago

MANIFOLD PUBLISHING GROUP


info@manifoldmagazine.com
www.manifoldmagazine.com

First published in 2008

All work copyright the original author.


©2008 Manifold Publishing Group

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a


retrieval system, or transmitted in any form by any means without prior written
permission from the publisher.

This issue is brought to you through the generosity of the 2006-2007 Dr. Bill
Wilson Student Initiatives Grant.

Manifold is sponsored by Lars Lerup, William Ward Watkin Professor and Dean
at Rice School of Architecture.

Cover design by Ann Chou

Printed and bound in the USA by the Manifold Publishing Group


MANIFOLD
To the Reader
Izabel Gass

“The traditional concept is that things are in time, whereas the new concept is that
time is in the things”- Karlheinz Stockhausen

Manifold Magazine was founded in May 2007 to provide a platform


for a reinvigoration of philosophical thought within the discipline of archi-
tecture. We made a promise to the reader in Manifold 1: the second issue
of the journal would be released only when a meaningful philosophical
discussion had been generated within its pages. We hope and suspect that
time has come.

The theme of Manifold 2 is “Forms of Time,” (a play on the title of


Sanford Kwinter’s 2001 book Architectures of Time). The editorial direction
was twofold. Our first aim was to generate a discussion of time as a mor-
phological order through which form is articulated. This meant returning to
scientific developments of the late 19th and early 20th centuries to explain
the scientific grounds for a Modern chronotope in which space, time, and
matter are not maintained as distinct variables but rather are collapsed
within what Einstein called “the field condition,” or a perfectly immanent
material world in which space-time-matter are all one continuous thing
(“Immanence” from the Latin immanere, to inhere within). In its philo-
sophical use, the term “immanence” indicates a world that is founded in
nothing transcendent—no timeless “substratum” (Aristotle) against which


change occurs. There is a parity between the Einsteinian field and ontologi-
cal immanence in that what “inheres within” the immanent world—essence,
difference, “god” — does not ground it or ontologically precede it; similarly,
for Einstein, space and time no longer exist as “carriers” for events (a word
he uses throughout his writings to describe Newtonian mechanics) but
instead constitute a single time-event, an indistinguishable force. As the
quote of composer Karlheinz Stockhausen above suggests, the immanent
world differentiates itself. Despite Gilles Deleuze’s recent oblivion within
contemporary architectural discourse, he remains the central philosopher
of an immanent ontology; it was in this light that we sought a thorough
reading of Deleuze’s lesser known texts.

Second to this primary discussion, the editors aimed that a critical


undercurrent run below the surface of Manifold 2, an undercurrent meant
to quietly suggest that many contemporary practices which claim owner-
ship of “topological” morphology and immanentist philosophy have done
little to dismantle the notion of the architectural object as fundamentally
static and individuated from its environment. Hence, the decision to allow
the title of Manifold 2 to echo the propos of Kwinter’s six-year-old book:
The problem of Immanence has still yet to be addressed.

The first set of our book reviews covers two of Gilles Deleuze’s
early works, Bergsonism (1966) and Kant’s Critical Philosophy (1963). It
is my hope that these texts provide a more foundational introduction to
the origins of Deleuzian “immanence” than can be found in the mere pil-
laging of Deleuzian jargon still common in architecture today. With these
reviews, we hoped to illuminate a personal statement of Deleuze’s from a
1988 interview:

10
Setting out a plane of immanence, tracing out a field of imma-
nence, is something all the authors I’ve worked on have done
(even Kant — by denouncing any transcendent application of
the synthesis of the imagination, although he sticks to possible
experience rather than real experimentation). Abstractions
explain nothing, they themselves have to be explained: there
are no such things as universals, there’s nothing transcendent,
no Unity, subject (or object), Reason; there are only processes,
sometimes unifying, subjectifying, rationalizing, but just pro-
cesses all the same. 

Also, Jason Nguyen and Mark Davis interviewed Brian Massumi on


the intellectual origins of the Deleuzian virtual as well as of the Foucauld-
ian diagram, assessing the potential for creating a “temporal architecture”
along these lines.

It seemed only fair that Henri Bergson, as the great 20th century
philosopher of time, deserved a place of his own in this issue along with
Deleuze’s reading of his work. Matthew Conti studied Bergson’s interpreta-
tion of the scientific paradigm shift from classical mechanics to Einsteinian
relativity in Bergson’s brave (though sometimes muddled) book, Duration
and Simultaneity (1922). The book requires some amount of historical con-
textualization; Robin Durie does a particularly brilliant job in his English
translation. I will try to do half as well:

Classical or “Newtonian” mechanics rested on a notion of time as


“absolute.” Absolute time can be understood as a universal framework for
the measurement of movement, outside of or distinct from movement
i. See Negotiations, trans. Martin Joughin; Columbia University Press, 1995

11
itself; or, as Einstein succinctly phrases it:

According to classical mechanics, time is absolute, ie, it is


independent of the position and the condition of motion of the
system of coordinates.ii

In the classical model, time has no creative agency because time


does not regulate movement, but merely measures it. Crucial here is that
the concept of “simultaneity,” the notion that two events can occur “at
the same time,” relies on the relation of distinct events to a standardized
temporal scale.

The linch-pin is jerked from the theory of “Absolute Time” in the


1880’s, when Albert Michelson and Edward Morley discover that the speed
of light remains constant regardless of the speed of its point of observation
— an observer moving at 65 mph does not perceive light moving faster than
an observer standing still. Einstein eventually uses this finding to reveal the
fallacy of the “Theorem of the Addition of Velocities,” the notion that the
sum total of the relative velocities of an observer and her object of observa-
tion provide the velocity of the system in “Absolute Time”:

Let us assume that the simple law of the constancy of the veloc-
ity of light c (in vacuum) is justifiably believed [...] If a ray of
light be sent along [an] embankment [...] the tip of the ray will
be transmitted with the velocity c relative to the embankment.
Now let us suppose that our railway carriage is [...] travelling
along the railway lines with the velocity v, and that its direction

ii. Einstein, Relativity: The Special and General Theory, p. 62

12
is the same as that of the ray of light, but its velocity of course
much less. Let us inquire about the velocity of propagation of
the ray of light relative to the carriage [...] The velocity W of
the man relative to the embankment is here replaced by the
velocity of light relative to the embankment. w is the required
velocity of light with respect to the carriage, and we have

w=c–v

The velocity of propagation of a ray of light relative to the car-


riage thus comes out smaller than c. iii

Thus, the total velocity of the system of the speed of light rela-
tive to the speed of its observer is irreducible to Absolute Time, inasmuch
as the speed of light is constant — time is not, in the Newtonian sense,
“independent of the condition of motion” of light; rather, light maintains
its own condition of motion, or its own time.

In his Duration and Simultaneity, Henri Bergson uses Einsteinian


relativity to legitimate a science of “Duration” — consciousness understood
as a temporal flow internal to the human subject. Matthew Conti’s review
of this text attempts to pinpoint exactly where the philosopher loses the
scientist — and where the scientist loses the philosopher — unfolding
Bergson’s enigmatic reading of Einstein.

The design project featured in this issue, Robert Crawford and


Federico Cavazos’ “Ambiguous Etiologies”, modulates turbulence and
catalyzes material and climatological interactions to produce architectural
iii. Einstein, pp. 21-22

13
forms from drifts of snow in Wyoming’s barren landscape. The project
could be said to operate under the assumption that time and matter exist in
a single, continuous, self-integrated manifold, (Einsteinian “field”) not the
“dichotomized” (Massumi) world of Newtonian time and space. Einstein
again:

In Newtonian mechanics, space and time [...] play the part of


carrier or frame for things that happen in physics, in reference
to which events are described by the space co-ordinates and the
time. In principle, matter is thought of as consisting of “mate-
rial points,” the motions of which constitute physical happen-
ing [...] If matter were to disappear, space and time alone would
remain behind (as a kind of stage for physical happening).

By contrast:

The concept of field [replaced] the idea of a particle (mate-


rial point) [...] Temperature is here a simple example of the
concept of field. This is a quantity (or a complex of quantities)
which is a function of the co-ordinates and the time. Another
example is the motion of a liquid. At every point there exists
at any time a velocity, which is quantitatively described by its
three ‘components’ with respect to the axes of a co-ordinate
system (vector). The components of the velocity at a point (field
components), here also, are functions of the co-ordinates (x, y,
z) and the time (t) [...] Even in classical physics the event is
localized by four numbers, three spatial co-ordinates and a time
co-ordinate; the totality of physical “events” is thus thought of
as being embedded in a four-dimensional continuous manifold.

14
But the basis of classical mechanics this four-dimensional con-
tinuum breaks up objectively into the one-dimensional time
and into three-dimensional spatial sections, only the latter of
which contain simultaneous events. iv

While Cavazos and Crawford’s design work attempts a material


interpretation of the field condition, David Dahlbom ventured a review
of Sanford Kwinter’s 2001 Architectures of Time, homing in on Kwinter’s
understanding of the “subjective bloc,” or a theory of the subject within
an immanent ontology. Dahlbom particularly raises the question of how
free will and socio-political agency, as they have been typically constituted
in Humanist discourse, are to be rethought in this framework — a hugely
important subject that Kwinter has never managed to fully address.

Lastly, my own interview with Brian Boigon turns to a discussion of


the mundane world of Perez Hilton, instant messaging and computer gam-
ing. Boigon offers a disjunctive and rambling manifesto on the capacity of
contemporary technology to define a “dynamic architecture” that extends
beyond the disciplinary literalism of architecture as built form.

At the conclusion of his interview, Boigon demands: “if you want to


make your architecture into a building, enter through Marcel Duchamp’s
Door 11.” Door 11, of course, was Marcel Duchamp’s puzzling doorframe
construction in which one door shared two frames, such that, to close the
door in one frame was to open it in another. I particularly liked Boigon’s
reference here, mostly because it is our aim that each issue of Manifold
provoke more than explain, which is to say, we hope to never close the
door on any idea, but merely move our readers and contributors from one
iv. Einstein, pp. 165-166

15
room of questions to another. In Deleuze’s words, “abstractions explain
nothing.” This is to say, without fail, the elaboration of any thought always
yields a complexity that reconfigures the whole of an idea. On that note,
we thank you for reading and, as always, challenge you with an invitation to
join our endeavor.

Sincerely,

Izabel Gass
Editor-in-Chief

16
Brian Massumi
with Jason Nguyen and Mark Davis

Nguyen, Davis: Historically, a Western understanding of the material


world has relied on a desire to understand things for what they “are.” But
the work of Deleuze and Guattari proposes an ontology rooted in “becom-
ing.” Paradoxically, this way of thinking debases the singular moment of
instantiation, elevating instead the abstract collection of circumstances that
intersect to produce it. What is the role of the “Virtual” in this ontology,
and how does it differ from the Platonic “Ideal”?

Massumi: An effort of thought is required to prevent the Deleuzian “vir-


tual” from slipping into the Platonic ideal. The concept automatically shifts
in this direction the instant it is separated from “the singular moment of
instantiation,” or in deleuzian terms, the “actual.” It is the virtual which
is debased by being separated in thought from actuality — not the actual
which is debased by its association with the virtual. The two are inseparable.
They must be thought strictly together. From a deleuzian point of view they
have no philosophical meaning apart from their dynamic embrace of each
other. The movement of becoming is not on one side or the other: it is the
result of their coming together. “Dynamic” and “movement” are the key
words. There would be neither dynamism nor movement were the virtual
and actual in separate realms. There is one world, and it is they.

The virtual separated from the actual would be utterly “sterile” be-
cause it would have nothing through which to express itself. Unexpressed,

17
it would not give itself to thought. The actual apart from the virtual would
be absolute stasis, because a thing in change is like a doppler effect through
the present of a just-past moving into the future. The past and future are
precisely what are inactual, so they fall to the virtual. The moment you
think change, you have actually appealed to the virtual. Think the actual
without the virtual, and you have fixity.

Deleuze needs a concept of the virtual because of his project of


thinking the actual. The starting point of that project is the heraclitean
observation that the only constant is change. Conversely, Deleuze needs
the actual to hold the reality of the virtual. Deleuze considers his thought,
including the thought of the virtual, to be a variety of empiricism. He
accepts the dictum that everything that can be considered real must in
some way be experienced, with “experienced” minimally defined as having
effects or taking effect. The actual is nothing other than the taking-effect of
the virtual. A supernal virtual could never get past the post of this effective
philosophy.

This is just a first approximation. The virtual is a slippery concept.


It is by nature elusive. I call it “recessive.” It does not expend itself in its
effect. It withdraws back into itself, constituting in the same stroke the
just-past of that effect, and the to-come of the next. It is always in the gaps
between chronological moments, in a nonlinear, recursive time of its own:
just past – yet to come; future-past. When the virtual withdraws back into
itself in the gaps in the actual, it has no “place” to go. It goes only into its
own return. You can only think it across its iterations, and the mark of each
iteration is an actual change. However: every change can be expressed as a
change in an order of juxtaposition of actual elements. In other words, the
virtual, by nature elusive in a time-like way, takes effect as a spacing. It does

18
not take effect without its effects taking place.

This is where the paradox of Deleuze’s thinking lies: not in an alter-


native between the actual and the virtual, but in how they come together.
The way in which they come together creates a space-time tension that is
difficult to model conceptually because our habits of thought tend both to
dichotomize space and time (treating them as independent variables) and
to erase their difference (for example, by construing time as a “line”). It
is difficult to talk about the virtual without falling into one of these traps,
or most often both at the same time. For example, the suspicion that the
virtual is a Platonic ideal has already spatialized it as a realm apart, a higher
plane or other world.

Deleuze has two base strategies to deal with this slipperiness of the
virtual in its relation with the actual. First, he multiplies models for it. A
given model may tend toward spatializing the virtual. He will immediately
undermine it with a temporalizing counter-model. If you put the two to-
gether, you get a space-time tension, or even a paradox. You are making
progress. None of the models are meant to be adequate descriptions of the
virtual. They are conceptual tools meant to assist in following the move-
ment of the virtual into and out of the actual. This movement will be dif-
ferent in each case. And in each case, a particular set of models will have to
be mobilized. The virtual is most adequately expressed in the interference
patterns between them. The thought of the virtual is all about process, and
must itself be a process. It can never come in one go.

For example, Deleuze often speaks of the virtual as being composed


of sets of “pure singularities.” These are point-like, and taken together form
“constellations.” Taken that way, the virtual begins to resemble a fixed

19
space-like structure. So Deleuze will go on to say that the singularities
“extend” toward one another. This undoes the fixity by adding a vector
aspect carrying a time connotation. The constellation is starting to feel like
a projective geometry (in which points and lines are interchanged, and the
plotting of space requires a time of transformation). Then just as you’re
getting used to that he’ll say that each singularity “includes” all the oth-
ers, in the dynamic form of its extensions toward them. The singularity is
now sounding like a curve: an integration of singularities. We’re now in a
calculus model, each singularity an integrable differential. If you try to put
the models together, you get points stretching out into lines, lines curv-
ing, curves folding back into mutual inclusion -- the whole bending into a
topological model. Point, set, structure, vector, curve, differential, integral,
topological transformation —all these are the virtual. And that is only a
few of the mathematical models you might appeal to (there are others:
Riemann space, Markov chains, fractals, and on and on). There are also
physical models (the singularity as quantum of event). Biological models
(rhizome, phylum). Geological models (strata, plateaus). Military models
(war-machine, “fleet in being”). The models never end. Their multitude is
only limited in the working out of a particular conceptual problem. Each
problem approached will take its own selection of them. The materials and
formations in question will simply not be able to bear the embarrassment
of conceptual riches. The models will shake down, under pressure, into
a restricted set. The movements into and out of the reduced plurality of
models that are left will mimic the actual pattern under study. The problem
will have been processed in thought. Thought will have mimicked its actual
object in and as its own process – making that process analogical.

The thinking of the virtual is always analogical, in an irreducibly


complex way. Simondon has an ugly name for this kind of analogical think-

20
ing of and with complexity. He call it “allagmatics.” Here it means you can
never model the virtual once and for all. And that you can never simply
apply the models of it that you produce. You have to put them to work.
You have to work through them, and work them through, differently in
each case, under problematic pressure. You have to enact them. It’s a real
process.

Mistrust anyone who privileges any one model of the virtual. They
are standing back from the process. It is a common tactic of critics of De-
leuze to take one of his proliferation of models for the model, and then
on that basis critique the concept of the virtual as inadequate. This is like
amputing someone’s thumb and then criticizing them for not living up to
the definition of the human by failing to display opposable digits. You can’t
grasp the virtual without a full conceptual hand. You can’t actually grasp it
at all. It’s more like prestidigitation. You make the moves that conjure it up
performatively as a thought-effect.

Nguyen, Davis: As Deleuzian-Guattarian preoccupations seep in to ar-


chitecture, practices are emerging which pose philosophical questions for
the process of form-making, yet still have not confronted the largely static
nature of the built environment. Is it possible to re-conceive the discipline
of architecture entirely as an art of temporal, rather than spatial, organiza-
tion? What are the implications of such an agenda?

Massumi: Approached processually, there is no contradiction between form


and formation, stasis and transformation, or even time and space. The most
useful way of approaching these “oppositions” is to treat them as phase
transitions. We do not say that ice “contradicts” water. Water becomes ice,
and ice water. They are processual extensions of each other. Each contains

21
the other as its own potential. They are in a state of “mutual inclusion” in
the same line of variation. They belong to the same “phylum.” Their starkly
different formal qualities, it is true, commit them to different destinies.
Water enters prioritarily into regimes of flow, ice into regimes of rigid ac-
cumulation. However, the formal differences do not belie their belonging
to the same phylum. Quite the contrary, they express it – differentially. The
transitions from one phase state to another give the process to which both
forms belong the opportunity to express itself more fully. The potentials
each phase state contains appear differentially, in a distribution bringing
to expression at the same time what the process immanently includes, and
its engagement with external conditions belonging to other processes. The
ice-form expresses at the same time a potential of the material phylum to
which it belongs, and an environing set of weather conditions. The expres-
sion of the potential of the water process is conditioned by another, more
encompassing process. The second process takes the first up into itself. It
sets the conditions under which a specific form belonging to the first process
will present itself in it. This is what Deleuze and Guattari call “capture.”

Capture is always “double capture,” because as I noted the process


taken up has something to say about what happens, and co-determines the
more encompassing process determining what form it takes. Today’s weather
conditions wouldn’t be what they are were water not part of the phylum it
is. Weather conditions may determine which of water’s potentials will ap-
pear, but the weather is dependent on water’s offering up those potentials
for it to be what it will have been on any given day. It’s the difference
between rain and snow. The point is: even “static” or frozen forms belong
to processual continuums populated by phase transitions between related
forms which express the same process in starkly different formal qualities.
Which form presents itself with what precise qualities, when, where and

22
how, is determined in dynamic encounter with another process that is more
encompassing than the first but with which the first is nevertheless in a
relation of co-determination.

The design process, what your question calls “formation,” is archi-


tecture’s liquid phase. The “static” form that emerges from that phase is
the built structure. The weather is the urban environment (including all its
constituent dimensions or strata: zoning, circulatory patterns, commercial
pressures, cultural preferences, trends in taste) providing the conditions for
that building. Urbanism and architecture are in a relation of double capture.
To be thought fully, neither can be thought apart. They are co-determining.
The determination doesn’t end at the erection of the building. The urban
process that takes it up may continue to bring new architectural potentials
contained in the building to expression. How a building takes effect, what
architectural-urban effects it has, varies according to what passes through
it, how it is inhabited, and what goes on around. A building may be repur-
posed, qualitatively changing what difference its formal qualities make in
the life of the city – the architectural equivalent of snow or rain, a city
chill or urban warming trend. An entire architectural genre might modulate
which potentials actually appear, even without explicit formal reconfigura-
tion, in response to economic or cultural changes redefining the prevailing
“weather” conditions of the urban environment. The building next door
might be demolished and replaced, changing the local urban fabric in a
way that modulates the remaining building’s lived qualities and perhaps,
as a consequence of that, its program. The street in front might evolve into
a pedestrian mall, changing patterns of circulation, those changes in their
turn entraining others. The building may deteriorate, contributing through
its very breakdown to the conditions for urban renewal. The possibilities
are infinite. If you look at the larger picture of the double capture of the

23
built form and the urban environment, over the long term the fixity of the
“static” form reliquefies. All that is concrete melts into city.

The “static” form is only a provisional stop in the architectural


process. It is better conceived of as a threshold in a process that contin-
ues past it, and sweeps it up in a co-determined movement of continuing
transformation. The architectural process is ongoing for two reasons: 1) fol-
lowing to the principle of mutual inclusion, each form (or phase) virtually
“contains,” in processual potential, all others belonging to the architectural
continuum; 2) through the encounter with the encompassing, conditioning
process of the city, different sets of these architectural potentials are serially
expressed, with or without actual formal modification (sometimes relation-
ally, much the way one color modulates another by its proximity).

The question, then, is: how can the design process pre-adapt itself
to the continuation of process, which is in any case inevitable? How can
it build into its built result as-yet unexpressed architectural potentials,
enriching or intensifying the way it lends itself to re-uptake and recursive
reforming by other processes (double capture). How can it multiply its own
co-determining contributions to the double captures it engages? As Lars
Spuybroek argues, answering these questions requires shifting the vocabu-
lary from, for example, “ambiguities” of code or meaning, to ontogenetic
“vagueness.” Ontogenetic vagueness is not a lack of definition. It is a surplus
of it: a mutual inclusion in the same actual form of potentially divergent
takings-effect belonging to different phases of the same process. Greg
Lynn also speaks of this surplus-determination when he calls the produced
architectural form the dynamic “form of a multiplicity.” This question of
the surplus-determining continuation of the architectural process is the
problem my own work on architecture has focused on.

24
Surplus-determination has to do only marginally with what is most
commonly taken to be the “content” of architecture: the typologies of
constituted form-defining styles which can be infused with new meaning
through a recoding or cross-coding of their component formal units. It is
less concerned with architecture’s formal disciplinary understanding of
itself than with its living through the encounter with its outside. There is a
particularly important “outside” of architecture that the built environment
actually contains: the body. It cannot be forgotten that the living-through
of the architectural process is always, and always variably, embodied.

There is a third “double capture” in close embrace with the two


already discussed. The material phylum of the human body, with its im-
manent process of experience-formation and all the potential that process
holds, enters into complex relations of co-determining continuation and
recursive reforming with the built structure. The built form is to body as
the built environment is to the building. The qualities of the built environ-
ment are the weather conditions for embodied experience.

A logic of perceptual emergence, of experiential ontogenesis, must


be added to the larger picture. What experiential phase transitions does a
passing or inhabiting body engage in double capture with the built form?
How do these continuous transformations feed back into urbanism? Or
back into architecture, at its interface with urbanism? What unexpressed
potentials are capacitated, at what thresholds, and to what effect? How can
architectural form surplus-determine perception and qualities of experi-
ence? Arakawa and Gins answer that question by adapting the concept of
“affordances” from J.J. Gibson’s “ecological” approach to perception theory.
The unit of architecture, from this processual perspective, is not a formal
unit of style. It is the “landing site”: the way in which an architectural

25
element beckons the body to actualize one of its experiential potentials.
Or many at once. When there are several, without one necessarily being
privileged over another, the architectural element has become surplus-de-
termining: the unitary form of an experiential multiplicity whose conditions
of emergence are an architectural encounter with the phylum of the body,
that encounter itself enfolded in the urban encounter with architecture:
triple articulation.

It cannot be emphasized enough that this foregrounding of percep-


tion and experience is not a call for a phenomenology of architecture. Phe-
nomenology returns experience to a form of interiority (the transcendental
ego) or a closed loop (the “flesh” of the world as preflective of subjective
expression). Experience is but an echo. In the ecological approach I am
advocating experience is an emergence. It returns the body to a processual
field of exteriority (encounter). The same goes for architecture itself. The
model at all levels is what I have called “relational autonomy”: the emer-
gent expression of a process’ singular potentials in a dynamic of encounter
with its processual outside. Applied to architecture, this undermines the
explanatory power of any approach that begins by separating the inside of
the discipline from its outside, as if architecture itself were effectively a
form of interiority defined by historical periods, a repertory of styles, or a set
of characteristics procedures. All of these change. All are under continual
variation. Architecture as a “discipline” is what passes through these ongo-
ing phase-shifts. It is in the gaps between chronological moments. It is in
the surplus-determination of elements of style in virtue of which they carry
an in-built, or immanent, potential for modulation. It is in the invention
of new procedures which retool its interface with other processes. Architec-
ture is the indiscipline flowing through its own complexly co-determined
iterations. It is not an edifice itself. It is not a structure. It has no definitive

26
content. It is a living process. As Deleuze and Guattari were fond of saying,
escape is the life-blood of process. A creative discipline is defined by how
it escapes its past content and internal constraints. It renews itself through
the rigorous indiscipline of its effective couplings with processes other than
its own.

Nguyen, Davis: The predominant architectural (mis-)use of Deleuzian-


Guattarian philosophy in architecture has been on form-making, often
confusing digital tools for “abstract machines” for dynamic form generation.
But isn’t architecture itself a socio-political abstract machine, as Foucault
showed time and again (Bentham’s Panopticon, the poor houses, the hospi-
tals, the public registers, etc.)? If so, what consequences might this present
for a “critical” architectural practice?

Massumi: By the logic I have been advancing, digital tools can indeed be
considered “abstract machines” for dynamic form generation. And architec-
ture itself, in the “big picture,” would be a socio-political abstract machine.
These are not mutually exclusive propositions.

The definition of an abstract machine would be: the generative


principle by which a continuum of potentials belonging to the same phy-
lum are vaguely determined to mutually include one another, and by which
that mutual inclusion is iteratively expressed through the serial emergence
of fully constituted actual forms punctuating phase transitions occurring
at the interface with an outside process. There is not room to unpack this
here, or to deal adequately with the complicated question of digital tech-
nology in architectural design. It will be sufficient to get a provisional idea
of why I would defend digital design procedures as an abstract machine to
replace “generative principle” in the definition I just gave with “algorithm”;

27
continuum of potentials with “permutational iterations”; emergence with
“stochastic operator”; and to construe any form at which the process of
form-generation is stopped as the fully constituted actual form. What then
are the outside processes with which this digital process interfaces? First:
human perceptual processes, at the inter-process threshold of the literal
interface of the screen. Second: the forces of the intended site and the
larger environment, and the values of the architect and/or client. Third:
both of these as they return to the process to modulate it.

What is unique about the digital design process it that it allows


any of its encounters with outside processes to be folded back into itself,
so as to become creative factors for its own iteration. It can turn outside
constraints into internal factors of creation, simply by folding them back
into its own process in the form of a tweaking of the generative parameters.
This infolding of external constraints transformed into internal creative
factors can be of many kinds. It might be a stylistic preference (curvilinear-
ity, for example) or a zoning imperative. It may be a desire to pre-engineer a
structural characteristic like load-bearing without dichotomizing aesthetic
form and architectonic structure. It may be to enable computer milling or
to experiment with modularity in response to cost constraints. One way
in which outside “constraints” may be integrated as creative factors into
digital design is to program basins of attraction or repulsion and limits of
divergence or fusion which inflect the forms generated so that a certain
value, or lived quality, is embodied in the resulting building. Lynn was an
early pioneer in this approach, for example in his Long Island House proto-
type which translated the constraint placed on the design by the client for a
certain view into a generative factor internal to the digital abstract machine
of the form-generating process itself.

28
I do not mean to privilege digital design techniques over others. The
same translation of external limits or constraints into creative factors can
be achieved by other means (as the current interest in analogue computing
clearly illustrates). I just mean to say that every technical or procedural
innovation provides architecture as a living process with an opportunity
to renegotiate its relation to its outsides, and in doing so to renew the
relational autonomy it lives by. There is no reason not to call this process of
disciplinary readjustment to constituent outsides a “critical” practice. It is
not critical in the sense of judging according to a preestablished standard
(of taste, political ideology, etc.). It is creatively critical in its operative en-
counter with the outside. It is critical in the sense that it benefits by these
encounters to carry the process across thresholds and to effect phase shifts.
These thresholds and phase shifts are “critical” points in the sense that
what is at stake is the changing nature of the process, and as a consequence
the very definition of the discipline claiming that process as its own. This
bringing into question of the process occurs as a function of its own ongo-
ing operations. It is a form of what Deleuze calls “immanent critique.” You
might also call it “operative” or “effective” critique.

An effective critique belongs to a gift economy, not an administra-


tion of judgment. By producing the effects that it does, the process gives of
itself – and gives itself up. It gives itself up to selection. The way in which
its takings-effect couple with outside process will have positive feedback
effects or inhibiting effects. This will affect the process’ viability and self-
expressive capacity. In short: it is the city that “judges” architecture. Except
it is not a judgment. It is a living out.

Or is it real estate speculation that “judges” architecture? It could


well be that the outside process of speculation is in a stronger position to

29
select. Critical architecture practice is more concerned with how the disci-
pline gives itself to which outside, than in what content standards it sets
for itself as a discipline. Critical practice is part of what Isabelle Stengers
calls an ecology of practices where “judgment” is lived out processually, in
outside encounter. Prime among the larger processes with which architec-
ture couples is the process of capital itself, with its fearsome global powers
of capture. It goes without saying that every architectural practice must
grapple with the forces of capital, which at the same time constitute the
most powerfully enabling of the outside constraints that it has available
to translate into a creative factor for itself, and the most cruelly selective
environment. The same could actually be said of any practice today. Im-
manent critique of any kind has no choice but to be in some way, however
humble, an operative critique of capitalism.

30
Bergsonism Gilles Deleuze
Zone Books, 1990

reviewed by Nicholas Risteen

In their introduction to Bergsonism, Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara


Habberjam, both extensive translators of Deleuze, offer an excerpt from
Deleuze’s letter to Michel Cressole relating Deleuze’s efforts to escape the
‘scholasticism of post-war French academic philosophy’:

My way of getting out of it at that time, was, I really think,


to conceive of the history of philosophy as a kind of buggery
or, what comes to the same thing, immaculate conception. I
imagined myself getting onto the back of an author, and giv-
ing him a child, which would be his and which would at the
same time be a monster. It is very important that it should
be his child, because the author actually had to say everything
that I made him say. But it also had to be a monster because
it was necessary to go through all kinds of decenterings, slips,
break-ins, secret emissions, which I really enjoyed. My book on
Bergson seems to me a classic of this case. 

This passage underscores Deleuze’s desire to set his text squarely


on Bergson’s shoulders; the words of the text are Bergson’s, the ideas pre-

i. Deleuze, Bergsonism, p. 8

31
formed, and their explication is a means of discovery more than argument.
Deleuze seems to be exploring the work of Bergson as much for himself as
for an academic reader looking to discover some ‘new’ insight on Bergson’s
philosophy. In a sense, Bergsonism construes the accumulated philosophy
under examination as a kind of data set, working in a scientific fashion to
elicit the underlying structure of Bergson’s writings.

“Intuition as Method,” the first chapter, details what Deleuze de-


clares to be “one of the most fully developed methods in philosophy” ii by
describing three essential rules to intuition as a method, or more precisely
three “distinct sorts of acts that in turn determine the rules of the method:
The first concerns the stating and creating of problems; the second, the
discovery of genuine differences in kind; the third, the apprehension of real
time”.iii Most important in this litany is the issue of ‘problems,’ specifically
the identification of false problems and their most common basis in the
misdiagnosis of “differences in degree” as “differences in kind.” Deleuze
quotes Bergson directly on this front:

The truth is that in philosophy and even elsewhere it is a ques-


tion of finding the problem and consequently of positing it,
even more than solving it. For a speculative problem is solved
as soon as it is properly stated. iv (emphases his)

Finding the problem, for Bergson (and subsequently here for De-
leuze as well) comes down to distinguishing between differences in kind,
and understanding that “there are no differences in kind except in dura-

ii. Ibid, p. 13
iii. Ibid, p. 14
iv. Ibid, p. 15

32
tion—while space is nothing other than the location, the environment, the
totality of differences of degree.” 

Bergson’s concept of “duration,” or lived time, is one of his most


famous and complex philosophical contributions. This issue occupies the
bulk of the next three chapters of Deleuze’s study, as extrapolating the
nuances enveloped in Bergson’s ideas becomes more complicated. Noting
the descriptions given of duration in Bergson’s Time and Free Will and
Creative Evolution, Deleuze describes duration as “a case of a ‘transition,’
of a ‘change,’ a becoming, but it is a becoming that endures, a change that is
substance itself,” further noting to the reader that “Bergson has no difficulty
in reconciling the two fundamental characteristics of duration; continuity
and heterogeneity.” vi How does Bergson presume to do so? By positing
duration itself as a multiplicity, based on the realization that duration

...divides up and does so constantly ...but it does not divide


up without changing in kind, it changes in kind in the process
of dividing up: This is why it is a nonnumerical multiplicity,
where we can speak of ‘indivisibles’ at each stage of the divi-
sion. There is other without there being several; number exists
only potentially. In other words, the subjective, or duration, is
the virtual. vii (emphases his)

Enter here another crowning piece to the puzzle: the virtual.


Deleuze’s study appears to flounder a bit at the introduction of the virtual,
as Bergson’s philosophy seems to almost spin out of control in a string of

v. Ibid, p. 32
vi. Ibid, p. 37
vii. Ibid, p. 42

33
equanimities: duration is the subjective is the virtual is memory is a multi-
plicity... In some instances this could be read as sticky philosophy, and the
subsequent chapters appear a bit convoluted to be sure, but not without
significant gains for Bergson’s argument. Those gains rest primarily on a
distinction between the ‘virtual’ and the ‘possible,’ a distinction which, in
Bergson’s inspection, philosophy (and also science) seemed to conspicu-
ously lack.

Deleuze draws the distinction between the virtual and the possible
from their respective relations to the real (and the means by which both
come into the real). Within Bergson’s philosophy, the virtual and the pos-
sible can be distinguished from each other “from at least two points of
view:”

From a certain point of view, in fact, the possible is the opposite


of the real, it is opposed to the real; but, in quite a different op-
position, the virtual is opposed to the actual. We must take this
terminology seriously: The possible has no reality (although it
may have an actuality); conversely, the virtual is not actual, but
as such possesses a reality. viii (emphasis his)

The second point from which to distinguish the virtual from the
possible rests in the process of ‘realization.’ Possibilities, for Bergson, come
to be realized through a process of limitation, “by which some possibles
are supposed to be repulsed or thwarted, while others ‘pass’ into the real”,ix
and work essentially in a negative fashion. The rules of actualization for the
virtual, by contrast, “are not those of resemblance and limitation, but those

viii. Ibid, p. 96
ix. Ibid, p. 97

34
of difference or divergence and of creation”. 

Bergsonism insists that this movement from the virtual to the actual
is not a dialectical process, which leaves the former behind in preference for
the latter (Bergson proffers the dialectic as a “false movement” due to its
imprecision). Instead, duration (or the virtual, or memory) retains its mul-
tiplicity in its process of actualization as “the conservation and preservation
of the past in the present” (emphasis his).xi In this way, Bergson’s duration
is “defined less by succession than by coexistence”.xii Positing duration
as virtual coexistence lends credence to the process of differentiation, as
the process of actualization need not thwart one virtual in preference for
another but instead allow them to develop along divergent lines.

The distinction that Deleuze elicits between the possible and the
virtual is the opposition between a negative and a positive process of re-
alization, respectively. That Bergson would come down on the side of the
positive process of actualizing the real should be clear from the introduc-
tion of Bergson’s method of intuition, which places the utmost importance
on the proper identification and creation of the problem itself (a positive
act). Reliance on the possible to describe the real would qualify as a false
problem for Bergson, as “it is not the real that resembles the possible, it is
the possible that resembles the real, because it has been abstracted from the
real once made, arbitrarily extracted from the real like a sterile double”.xiii
The movement from the possible to the real is a false movement, a kind
of conceptual back-tracking that seeks to identify a sequence of abstract
possibilities but only after the fact.
x. Ibid, p. 97
xi. Ibid, p. 57
xii. Ibid, p. 60
xiii. Ibid, p. 98

35
Movement for the virtual, by contrast, describes an entirely differ-
ent process:

We know that the virtual as virtual has a reality; this reality,


extended to the whole universe, consists in all the coexisting
degrees of expansion and contraction. A gigantic memory, a
universal cone in which everything coexists with itself, except
for the differences of level. On each of these levels there are
some ‘outstanding points,’ which are like remarkable points
particular to it. All these levels or degrees and all these points
are themselves virtual. They belong to a single Time; they
coexist in a Unity; there are enclosed in a Simplicity; they form
the potential parts of a Whole that is itself virtual. They are
the reality of this virtual ... When the virtual is actualized, is
differentiated, is ‘developed,’ when it actualizes and develops
its parts, it does so according to lines that are divergent, but
each of which corresponds to a particular degree in the virtual
totality. There is here no longer any coexisting whole; there are
merely lines of actualization, some successive, others simul-
taneous, but each representing an actualization of the whole
in one direction and not combining with other lines or other
directions ... For what coexisted in the virtual ceases to coexist
in the actual and is distributed in lines or parts that cannot
be summed up, each one retaining the whole, except from a
certain perspective, from a certain point of view. These lines of
differentiation are therefore truly creative: They only actualize
by inventing, they create in these conditions the physical, vital
or psychical representative of the ontological level that they

36
embody. xiv (emphases his)

This truly creative enterprise finds its fullest outlet in ‘the human
organism’ as expressed through the élan vital. Often translated as the ‘vital
impetus’ (which lacks particular subtleties of the French ‘élan’), the élan
vital manifests as the culmination of self-conscious creation, of the organ-
ism becoming aware of its ability not only to be affected by this process of
actualization but to effect it in turn to “create an instrument of freedom,
‘to make a machine which should triumph over mechanism,’ ‘to use the
determinism of nature to pass through the meshes of the net which this
very determinism had spread.’” xv Using intuition as method to arrive at
the interval between instinct and intelligence (that differentiating point at
which the human organism separates itself from its “animalistic” counter-
part), Bergson offers ‘emotion’ as the final working method of his creative
evolution. It is emotion that differs “in nature both from intelligence and
instinct, from both intelligent individual egoism and quasi instinctive so-
cial pressure” in an effort to liberate man “from the plane or the level that
is proper to him, in order to make him a creator, adequate to the whole
movement of creation”.xvi Bergsonism’s ideal creative emotion takes place
in a kind of ‘privileged soul,’ like an artist or a mystic, far more so than in
the work of philosophers: “At the limit, it is the mystic who plays with the
whole of creation, who invents an expression of it whose adequacy increases
with its dynamism.” xvii

Deleuze’s unpacking of Bergson in this short text covers enormous


ground, and shows numerous inklings of ideas and issues tackled in later
xiv. Ibid, pp. 100-101
xv. Ibid, p. 107
xvi. Ibid, pp. 110-111
xvii. Ibid, p. 112

37
decades in Deleuze’s own philosophy: multiplicity, duration, the virtual.
But it is important to remember that initial letter to Michel Cressole, and
the necessity to read this work by Deleuze as the kind of “buggery” or “im-
maculate conception” he intended it to be. After all, it is Bergson himself
who had to “say everything that I made him say.”

As such, tracing lines of descent from Bergson to Deleuze through


this text becomes a tricky matter. Deleuze does leave us some insight into
what elements within Bergsonism he took to be worth pursuing further, in
short afterward appended to the translation of the text in 1988 titled “A
Return to Bergson.” In taking stock of Bergson against modern advances
in science, technology and society, Deleuze offers three main features of
Bergsonism that can be useful in continuing his appraisal of metaphysics as
a rigorous discipline today: the method of intuition, the necessity of view-
ing metaphysics as a complement to science, and a continued examination
of the nature of multiplicities. Those three threads permeate much of
Deleuze’s own work, but it would be overstating the case to offer Bergsonism
as the ‘foundation’ (as some have done, even going so far as to say Deleuze’s
work constitutes “the new Bergsonism”). What would be fair, though, is
to see this text, this “immaculate conception,” as a work foundational to
the development of Deleuze’s own work in subsequent years, as Deleuze
worked through, against, and within the utility of Bergson to at last create a
body of work that was his own ‘monster.’

38
Kant’s Critical Philosophy Gilles Deleuze
University of Minnesota, 1985

reviewed by Izabel Gass

Deleuze’s 1963 study of Kant, Kant’s Critical Philosophy, which


Deleuze once described as a “book on an enemy,” is a subversive exercise
in delineating an impetus toward immanentism within the Kantian theory
of the transcendent subject. While, on one level, Deleuze’s book offers a
close textual reading and faithful synopsis of Kant’s three Critiques, it also
illuminates particular logical practices within the Kantian method— largely
the philosophical ties that bind Kant to empiricism — that serve to refigure
the traditional conception of the Kantian Transcendental Method. Most
radically, Deleuze depicts Kantian reason as a self-interested process aimed
at folding empirical experience into its own framework, exacting a legisla-
tive agency on the objects of experiential phenomena. In Deleuze’s reading
of Kant, reason becomes an engine or operative function that assimilates
experience to the mind of the subject, collapsing the distinction between

39
the subject and the objects of the subject’s perception. Deleuze herein
posits a limited commonality between Kant’s transcendent subject and his
own model of ontological immanence in which subject-object distinctions
are obliterated.

An Immanent Critique: Reason as Reason’s End

Deleuze defines Kant’s work as “a struggle on two fronts: against


empiricism and against dogmatic rationalism.”  The conflicting ontologies
of empiricism and rationalism differ fundamentally in their respective
answers to the skeptical question: how can we confirm the existence of the
self? For the rationalists, cognition objectively confirms being, which is to
say, to think is to exist. Descartes’ well-known formulation, “Cogito ergo
Sum,” (I think therefore I am) presupposes an objective existence for the
thinking self:

The fact that I [the “I” of Descartes’ formulation] exist is an


objective fact . . . Whatever the world contains, it contains the
thinking being who I am ii

Thus, for the rationalists, the thinking being can objectively con-
firm his own existence because of his very cognitive capacity to ask the
skeptical question. And because thought confirms being, thought (reason)
is determined to precede, or ground, “experience” in the construction of
knowledge, which is to say that

rationalism derives all claims to knowledge from the exercise

i. Deleuze, Kant’s Critical Philosophy, p. 1


ii. Scruton, Kant: A Very Short Introduction, p. 17

40
of reason, and purports to give an absolute description of the
world, uncontaminated by the experience of any observer. It is
an attempt to give a God’s-eye view of reality iii

In other words, empirical experience is superfluous to the work of


reason because reason is innate to the mind and is the ontological precedent
for experience.

By contrast, the empiricist viewpoint, most radically articulated by


David Hume and John Locke, skeptically erodes the possibility for objective
knowledge, positing that only conscious perception or “experience” can be
subjected to philosophical inquiry. What “experience” leaves just outside
its purview is any evidence of the mechanism that synthesizes it, which is to
say, any confirmation of a “self,” as differentiable from a world of perceiv-
able objects:

In basing all knowledge on experience . . . all claims to objectiv-


ity become spurious and illusory. . . Hume took his scepticism
so far as to cast doubt upon the existence of the self . . .saying
that neither is there a perceivable object that goes by this name,
nor is there any experience that would give rise to the idea of
it iv

For the empiricists, the “self” has no perceptible correlate, and


therefore falls outside the range of philosophical investigation. Thus, Hume
opens his Treatise of Human Nature with the claim that an evaluation of
the experiential marks the limit of a science of man:

iii. Ibid, p. 21
iv. Ibid, p. 25

41
Tho’ we must endeavour to render all our principles as universal
as possible, by tracing up our experiments to the utmost, and
explaining all effects from the simplest and fewest causes, ‘tis
still certain we cannot go beyond experience; and any hypoth-
esis, that pretends to discover the ultimate original qualities of
human nature, ought at first to be rejected as presumptuous
and chimerical 

What is crucial to note here is that, if inquiry into the nature of the
self is impossible for the empiricists, it is because the self cannot be distin-
guished from experience —in fact, this very indistinguishability between
“self” and “phenomena” is what Deleuze particularly takes hold of in his
own work on Hume. Because Hume’s empirical method has no means at
its disposal for differentiating the subject (“the ultimate original qualities
of human nature”) from phenomena (“experience”), he implicitly proposes
a collapse of the subject-object dichotomy. The individuation of the self
goes unconfirmed; experience is a single “plane of immanence” that fully
integrates both subject and object.

Kant’s “struggle on two fronts” is also a synthesis on two fronts, in


this regard. Kant first rejects empiricism on the grounds that an a priori
framework for knowledge must necessarily ground experiential perception.
Kant argues that reason is, in Deleuze’s terms, a “faculty of ends,” which is
to say, reason is absolutely necessary for the cognitive synthesis of the world
of objects, making reason a faculty without which empirical “experience”
would be impossible. Thus, Kant upholds the notion of innate ideas in the
mind and names them the “a priori.”

v. Hume, Treatise of Human Nature, p. xvii

42
However, Kant also refutes the rationalist notion that all knowledge
is innate, and experience superfluous to thought, positing instead that
while the a priori grounds experience, it must be also be actuated through
experience. Kant’s innate ideas are

concepts and principles which the reason derives from within


itself on the occasion of experience. A child is not born with, for
example, an idea of causality. But on the occasion of experience
its reason derives the concept from within itself. [This is] an a
priori concept in the sense that it is not derived from experience
but is applied to and in a sense governs experience. There are,
therefore a priori concepts and principles which are grounded
in the mind’s own structure. These concepts are ‘pure’, in
the sense that they are, of themselves, empty of all empirical
content or material vi

The Kantian a priori then, as a grounds for the experiential, is also


paradoxically reliant on experience for its actuation.

Deleuze herein delineates Kant’s rejection of rationalism (the tri-


umph of reason over experience) in terms of value, absurdity, and conflict.
Kant makes the “argument from value” that without cultural experience,
there is nothing to distinguish human reason from “animality,” or an ab-
ject, primitive existence — in other words, there is a value to reason as it is
cultivated through experience. Second, Kant poses the “argument from the
absurd,” which, in Deleuze’s terms, makes the claim that “if Nature had
wanted to achieve its own ends in a being endowed with reason” it would

vi. Copleston, A History of Philosophy, p. 213

43
not have provided the possibility for experience.vii Finally, Kant makes the
“argument from conflict,” suggesting that if reason were intended to pro-
vide an ends to knowledge without experience, or culture, then there would
be no conflict between man “as both animal and moral species;” in other
words, the cultural assimilation of the primitive or animalistic through law
and order would not be necessary. viii

Thus, Deleuze concludes that for Kant, “only the cultural ends of
reason can be described as absolutely final,” meaning, only reason that is
actuated within experience has achieved its intended, final “end.” ix Simply
put:

Neither experience nor reason is alone able to provide knowl-


edge [...] Only in their synthesis is knowledge possible; hence
there is no knowledge that does not bear the marks of reason
and of experience together 

It is crucial here that in stock summaries of Kantian philosophy what


Deleuze calls “the ends of reason” is simply referred to as “knowledge,”
the nominal term for a sublation of “reason” and “experience.” Frederick
Copleston’s above summary comes closer to Deleuze’s aim by describing
the a priori as that which “governs” experience, but it is by selectively
honing in on a language of “ends” and “means” that Deleuze uniquely il-
luminates Kantian reason as a self-interested process. For Deleuze, reason
is “self-interested” in the sense that it has its own goal (reason is a means
for achieving its own ends), and reason is a “process” in the sense that its
vii. Deleuze, Kant’s Critical Philosophy, p. 2
viii. Ibid, p. 2
ix. Ibid, p. 1
x. Scruton, Kant: A Very Short Introduction, p. 27

44
“goal” is merely an interminable exercise of its own faculties — simply put,
reason’s interest is in reasoning.

Deleuze here illuminates the implicit empiricist immanentism in


the Kantian Transcendental Method. In Deleuze’s formulation, reason
goes beyond itself, or reaches into the realm of experience, only so as to
subsume, or reintegrate, experience into reason’s own logic. In other words,
reason wants only to reason, and it assimilates experience to its own self-
interest in this regard. Deleuze contrasts this with the rationalist viewpoint,
in which

What reason recognizes as an end is still something external


and superior to it: a Being, a Good or a Value, taken as a rule
of will xi

Instead, Deleuze argues

Against rationalism, Kant asserts that supreme ends are not only
ends of reason, but that in positing them reason posits nothing
other than itself. In the ends of reason, it is reason which takes
itself as its own end . . . The ends or interests of reason cannot
be justified in terms of experience, or of any other authority
outside or above reason xii

And it is reason pursuing reason’s end that will enable the methods
for Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, in which

xi. Deleuze, Kant’s Critical Philosophy, p. 2


xii. Ibid, p. 2-3

45
an immanent Critique — reason as the judge of reason — [be-
comes] the essential principle of the so-called transcendental
method xiii

Kant’s first critique is thus understood as an attempt to “undertake


a critical investigation into the powers of the pure reason itself,” delineat-
ing the a priori conditions of the mind and their processes in the role of
the understanding. xiv As Kant describes in his preface to the Critique, the
work presents reason’s inquiry into reason’s capacities, a quest to define the
axioms of metaphysics:

Human reason has the peculiar fate in one species of its cogni-
tions that it is burdened with questions which it cannot dismiss,
since they are given to it as problems by the nature of reason
itself, but which it also cannot answer, since they transcend
every capacity of human reason.

Reason falls into this perplexity through no fault of its own. It


begins from principles whose use is unavoidable in the course
of experience and at the same time sufficiently warranted by
it. . . The battlefield of these endless controversies is called
metaphysics . . .

Reason should take on anew the most difficult of all its tasks,
namely, that of self-knowledge, and to institute a court of
justice, by which reason may secure its rightful claims while
dismissing all its groundless pretensions, and this not by mere

xiii. Ibid, p. 3
xiv. Copleston, p. 213

46
decrees but according to its own eternal and unchangeable
laws; and this court is none other than the critique of pure
reason itself xv

Thus, Deleuze emphasizes that Kantian reason, as it governs the


mind as much as the mode of inquiry for the first Critique, is a machine
for assimilating, collapsing, or folding experience into itself so as to make
knowledge available to its own ends. Deleuze ensuingly describes each of the
subsidiary faculties of the mind as a sequence of self-interested processes
that in turn serve the final ends of reason.

The Self-Interest of the Faculties: Powers of the Mind as Processes

In the “Transcendental Doctrine of Elements” of the Critique of


Pure Reason, Kant sets forth the parameters for his Transcendental Method,
positing that

Our cognition arises from two fundamental sources in the


mind, the first of which is the reception of representations (the
receptivity of impressions), the second the faculty for cogniz-
ing an object by means of these representations (spontaneity of
concepts); through the former an object is given to us, through
the latter it is thought in relation to that representation (as a
mere determination of the mind)xvi

The terminology here functions as follows: a “representation” is an


object as it appears to the mind, the “subject” is the cognitive conscious-

xv. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, p. 99-101


xvi. Ibid, p. 193

47
ness that contains this representation, and the “object” is the represented
entity, an entity assumed to be external to the mind of the subject. In Kant’s
Transcendental Method, the faculties of the mind synthesize “sensitive
knowledge” (“the receptivity of impressions”) and “intellectual knowledge”
(“concepts”). xvii

Deleuze deciphers two implications of the term “faculty,” or power


of the mind, in the Transcendental Method. The first meaning of faculty is
the type of relation constructed between a representation, its subject, and
its object:

Every representation is related to something other than itself;


both to an object and to a subject. We can distinguish as many
faculties of mind as there are types of relations xviii

Deleuze names three primary “types of relations,” or three faculties,


each of which informs one of Kant’s three Critiques. Within the faculty of
knowledge, the subject of the Critique of Pure Reason, a representation is
“related to the object from the standpoint of its agreement to or conformity
with it;” that is to say, the capacity of the faculty of knowledge is to pull the
representation into accordance with the object it represents.

Deleuze demonstrates that each of the faculties of the mind, or


types of relations, has a “higher form,” which is to say, a capacity to

find in itself the law of its own exercise (even if this law gives
rise to a necessary relationship with one of the other faculties).

xvii. See Copleston, p. 196


xviii. Deleuze, Kant’s Critical Philosophy, p. 3

48
In its higher form, a faculty is thus autonomous. The Critique
of Pure Reason begins by asking: ‘Is there a higher faculty of
knowledge?’ xix

The higher form of the faculty of knowledge —knowledge being


the relation of conformity between the object and the representation — is
to uncover the law by which the mind draws phenomena into accord with
itself. To do this, the faculty must explore the first order cognitive synthesis
that underlies the second order cognitive synthesis of empirical knowledge
— the relation of the representation to the object. The first order synthesis
here occurs not between the object and the representation, but between the
representation and the mind. This law is defined as the a priori synthesis:

As long as the synthesis [between phenomena and the mind] is


empirical, the faculty of knowledge appears in its lower form: it
finds its law in experience and not in itself. But the a priori syn-
thesis defines a higher faculty of knowledge. This is in fact no
longer governed by objects which would give a law to it; on the
contrary, it is the a priori synthesis which attributes a property
to the object which was not contained in the representation xx

The higher form of the faculty of knowledge herein relays empirical


knowledge to reason, inasmuch as “synthetic a priori judgments are them-
selves the principles of what should be called ‘the theoretical sciences of
reason.’” xxi Thus, the higher faculty of knowledge reveals that

xix. Ibid, p. 4
xx. Ibid, p. 5
xxi. Ibid, p. 5

49
Reason has a natural speculative interest: and it has it for ob-
jects which are necessarily subject to the faculty of knowledge
in its higher form xxii

Which is to say, yet again, the cognitive process is self-contained:


reason governs experience in order that it may return experience to reason’s
end, and, as Deleuze establishes in delineating Kant’s immanent critique,
“in the ends of reason, it is reason which takes itself as its own end.” xxiii
Thus, the objects of experience are presided over by reason; phenomena is
selectively represented by reason so as to return representation to reason’s
ends.

This first sense of the term “faculty”— faculty as the type of


relation between the representation, its subject, and its object — reveals
that all of the faculties ultimately serve reason’s end, which is to say, all
representational relations are interests of reason. The second sense of the
term “faculty” addresses the question of how these relations perform the
function of returning experience to reason’s ends:

How does an interest of reason realize itself?’ That is to say,


what assures the subjection of objects [to the mind, to reason],
how are they subjected? What is really legislating in a given
faculty? Is it imagination, understanding, or reason?xxiv

Deleuze answers this question by defining the second meaning of


the term faculty as “a specific source of representations,” attributing catego-
ries of representation to corresponding faculties of (or, sources within) the
xxii. Ibid, p. 5
xxiii. Ibid, p. 3
xxiv. Ibid, p. 9

50
mind. Each of these sources, in containing representations, is then assumed
to maintain responsibility for the organization of presentations:

The important thing in representation is the prefix: re-presen-


tation implies an active taking up of that which is presented;
hence an activity and a unity distinct from the passivity and
diversity which characterize sensibility as such. From this
standpoint we no longer need to define knowledge as a syn-
thesis of representations. It is the representation itself which
is defined as knowledge, that is to say, as the synthesis of that
which is presented xxv

Together, these two senses of the term faculty — a type of relation


and a source for representations — delineate the capacity of the mind as a
set of self-referential processes that order experience so as to return it to the
ends of reason. In sum, reason assimilates phenomena to its own end.

Legislators of Nature: Consciousness as a Power Relation

In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant put forth what he termed


his “Copernican Revolution,” an inversion of the rationalist philosophical
schema for the relationship of “reason” to “experience.” Kant’s “revolution”
proposes that: rather than assuming, as the traditional rationalist viewpoint
contends, that reason provides us with a cognitive framework for objective
knowledge, metaphysics could resituate its project from the perspective that
the objects of experience manifest themselves in accord with the nature of
the mind, rather than the mind accommodating the objects of experience.
In short, the common and colloquial formulation of this is: “objects conform

xxv. Ibid, p. 8

51
to the mind; the mind does not conform to objects.” Kant writes:

Up to now it has been assumed that all our cognition must


conform to the objects [of the senses — objects outside of the
mind]; but all attempts to find out something about them a
priori through concepts that would extend our cognition have,
on this presupposition, come to nothing. Hence let us once try
whether we do not get farther with the problems of metaphysics
by assuming that the objects must conform to our cognition,
which would agree better with the requested possibility of an
a priori cognition of them, which is to establish something
about objects before they are given to us. This would be just
like the first thoughts of Copernicus, who, when he did not
make good progress in the explanation of the celestial motions
if he assumed that the entire celestial host revolves around the
observer, tried to see if he might not have greater success if
he made the observer revolve and left the stars at rest. Now in
metaphysics we can try in a similar way regarding the intuition
of objects. If intuition has to conform to the constitution of the
objects, then I do not see how we can know anything of them a
priori; but if the object (as an object of the senses) conforms to
the constitution of our faculty of intuition, then I can very well
represent this possibility to myself xxvi

Deleuze notes that Kant’s Copernican Revolution is foundational to


his “struggle on two fronts” against empiricism and rationalism inasmuch
as:

xxvi. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, p. 110

52
In dogmatic rationalism the theory of knowledge was founded
on the idea of a correspondence between subject and object, of
an accord between the order of ideas and the order of things.
This accord had two aspects: in itself it implied a finality; and
it demanded a theological principle as source and guarantee of
this harmony, this finality. But it is curious that, from a com-
pletely different perspective, Hume’s empiricism had a similar
outcome: in order to explain how the principles of Nature were
in accord with those of human nature Hume was forced to
invoke explicitly a pre-established harmony xxvii

For the rationalists, because cognition precedes and grounds experi-


ence, the mind can be assumed to function in accordance with the objects
of experience; objective knowledge of phenomena is possible because (even
prior to experience) the mind always already possesses it. Similarly, for the
empiricists, the mind cannot be individuated from experience, and thus is
necessarily in harmony with — in fact fully integrated with — the objects
of experience. By contrast, Kant’s Copernican Revolution inverts the power
relation of the mind’s subordination to experience. Deleuze explains this as
the empowerment of the mind, the endowing of the mind with a legislative
agency:

The fundamental idea of what Kant calls his ‘Copernican


Revolution’ is the following: substituting the principle of a
necessary submission of object to subject for the idea of a har-
mony between subject and object (final accord). The essential
discovery is that the faculty of knowledge is legislative, or more
precisely, that there is something which legislates in the faculty

xxvii. Deleuze, Kant’s Critical Philosophy, p. 13

53
of knowledge . . . The rational being thus discovers that he has
new powers. The first thing that the Copernican Revolution
teaches us is that it is we who are giving the orders. There is
here an inversion of the ancient conception of Wisdom: the
sage was defined partly by his own submission, partly by his
‘final’ accord with Nature. Kant sets up the critical image in
opposition to wisdom: we are the legislators of Nature xxviii

Deleuze depicts reason as a will or force to be executed over and


against objects, in turn effecting, forming, these objects. Deleuze here rep-
resents the Kantian Transcendental Method as a power relation in which
the act of interpretation actively reformulates the object it interprets.

In this way, Deleuze manages to bring “reason as the ends of reason”


full circle to explain reason’s power relation — and thus, its full authority
over and integration within — the experiential. If we recall Deleuze’s stipu-
lation that, for the rationalists, the will of reason was to achieve “something
external and superior to it: a Being, a Good or a Value,” then here we see
that the will of Kantian reason is to assimilate experience to its own logic,
or to return, through all the processes of the mind, to its own ends. Reason
is an engine that drives all phenomena back into reason. xxix

Time is out of Joint; I is Another

In the introduction to his book, Deleuze proposes four “poetic


formulas” for summarizing Kant’s critical philosophy. In understanding
reason as a legislative engine, a law which governs the forms of the objects

xxviii. Ibid, p. 13
xxix. Ibid, p. 2

54
of experience, we can unravel the meaning of at least two of the “poetic
formulas.” The first of these is

Hamlet’s great formula, ‘The time is out of joint’. Time is out


of joint, time is unhinged. The hinges are the axis around which
the door turns. Cardo, in Latin, designates the subordination
of time to the cardinal points through which the periodical
movements that it measures pass. As long as time remains on
its hinges, it is subordinate to movement: it is the measure of
movement, interval or number. This was the view of ancient
philosophy. But time out of joint signifies the reversal of the
movement-time relationship. It is now movement which is
subordinate to time. . .Time is no longer related to the move-
ment which it measures, but movement is related to the time
which conditions it: this is the first great Kantian reversal in the
Critique of Pure Reason. xxx

In defining reason as a legislative act, Deleuze illuminates a dy-


namic relation between the time of the subject and the time of experiential
phenomena. As opposed to the “objective” framework of rationalist reason,
which posits a fixity, or constancy, between the time-space of the subject
and the time-space of experience, for Kant, time is the time of reason as it
approaches experience and folds experience back into its own logic. Time
is in flux because it is subject to a continual modulation in accordance
with reason’s legislative function and participation in the experiential. Kant
writes:

time is not something objective and real; it is neither an

xxx. Ibid, p. vii

55
accident, nor a substance, nor a relation; it is the subjective
condition, necessary because of the nature of the human mind
of coordinating all sensibilia by a certain law xxxi

The second of Deleuze’s poetic formulas is borrowed from Rimbaud:


“I is Another,” meaning that

The I is an act which constantly carries out a synthesis of time,


and of that which happens in time, by dividing up the present,
the past, and the future at every instant xxxii

Again, because reason governs the constitution of objects in the


material world, it is the “unity of consciousness” that “synthesizes the
manifold” of experiential phenomena:

Representation means the synthesis of that which is presented.


... My representations are mine in so far as they are linked in
the unity of a consciousness, in such a way that the ‘I think’
accompanies them xxxiii

And yet, because Kantian reason relies on experience to actuate


itself,

Knowledge implies a necessary relation to an object. That


which constitutes knowledge is not simply the act by which the
manifold is synthesized, but the act by which the represented

xxxi. Kant, quoted in Copleston, p. 197


xxxii. Deleuze, Kant’s Critical Philosophy, p. viii
xxxiii. Ibid, p. 14-15

56
manifold is related to an object xxxiv

Thus, the objects of experience and the reason that governs them
are in a continuous, reciprocal self-definition that constitutes the ever-
changing “I” of the Kantian consciousness.

xxxiv. Ibid, p. 15

57
58
Ambiguous Etiologies
Robert Crawford and Federico Cavazos

Ambiguous Etiologies, a design


for an outdoor pavilion in the
plains of Wyoming, is a reconfigu-
rable modular lattice system that
harnesses snow drifts to create a
landscape of differentiated spatial
zones.

The pavilion challenges the


understanding of space as a “dis-
crete multiplicity,” and instead
approaches architecture as the
dynamic distribution of intensive
material properties: light, heat,
density, turbulence, pressure. Am-
biguous Etiologies acknowledges
architecture’s full immersion in the
flux of material energies, revealing
the absurdity of dialectic categories
such as the “natural” and the “arti-
ficial,” or the “landscape” and the
“building.” This project is an engine
for the organization of matter.

59
Conditions A
1
A
2
A
3
A
4

The pavilion is climatic-dependent. 12


11
Snow accumulation peaks in late February, 10

Snowfall (in)
which is immediately followed by a spike in 9
8
wind and a temperate summer that usually 7
hovers around the 70’s. Our pavilion seeks to 6
decrease the large swing in temperature to 5
4
create an inhabitable space. The modules 3
act as space heaters in addition to snow 2
1
fences during the winter. Their location J J A S O N D J F M A M
upwind heats the spaces downwind. The
Month
snow is melted into a series of pools during
the summer, also upwind, whose purpose is
the opposite: to cool the breeze before it
reaches the inhabitable space. 13
12

Wind (MPH)
11
10
A 0% Accumulation Level 9
1
Average Temperature (F): 75 8

Average Wind (mph): 8 7

Average Snowfall (in): 0 6


5
J J A S O N D J F M A M

A 13% Accumulation Level Month


2 Average Temperature (F): 32
Average Wind (mph): 9
105
Average Snowfall (in): 4.5
90
Temperature (F)

75
A 70% Accumulation Level 60
3
Average Temperature (F): 16 45
Average Wind (mph): 10 30
Average Snowfall (in): 7.5 15

0
J J A S O N D J F M A M

A 100% Accumulation Level Month


4
Average Temperature (F): 29
Average Wind (mph): 11
Average Snowfall (in): 6

H 1 2

15H

60
Snow Fence Diagrams

Density - Snow mounds up directly Form - The fetch closely follows the
against solid walls, but not porous shape of the fence.
walls.

Height - The higher the fence the Form + Height - It is clear the hieght
longer the fetch. of the snow fence plays a larger role
than the form.

Four Stages of Growth


1. A lens-shaped drift forms as saltating particles are caught by the fence. The wind force diminishes for a distance
equal to about 15 times the height of the fence (15H). Some blowing snow deposits on the ground, but the wind still
carries some particles from the shelter of the fence. This lens shaped deposite becomes deeper until the wind no
longer follows its curvature. At this stage, an eddy or recirculation zone forms downwind of the lens, causing a
slip-face to form.

2. At the third stage, the drift adds significant resistance to approaching wind. The recirculation zone helps trap
particles blowing off the top of the drift. The lens-shaped drift becomes deeper but not much longer. The efficiency
of the fence may actually increase as the drift adds resistance to the wind. The slip-face and
recirulation zone that form in this stage trap some of the snow that blows off the top of the drift.

3. As the downwind drift approaches its maximum depth (for 50% porous fences, 1 to 1.2 times the height of the
fence), the third stage of growth begins. The recirculation zone fills in as the drift lengthens downwind. This stage is
characterized by a decline in trapping effiiciency as the recirculation zone diminishes in size.

4. The fourth stage of growth begins when the drift first assumes a smooth profile without the slip-face, marking the
disappearance of the recirculation zone. At this stage, the drift is about 20H in length. Subsequent growth is slow as
the drift elongates to its final length of 35H.

Source: Tabler, Ronald. Snow Fence Guide. National Research Council

3 4

35H

61
Connection Matrix
Plan Front Right Axo
Connection Type 1
Density: Loose
Angle: 90 to 90
Legs: Long to Long

Connection Type 2
Density: Loose
Angle: 90 to 90
Legs: Short to Short

Connection Type 3
Density: Loose
Angle: 90 to 90
Legs: Long to Long

Connection Type 4
Density: Loose
Angle: 30 to 90
Legs: Medium to Long

Connection Type 5
Density: Loose
Angle: 90 to 90
Legs: Long to Short

Connection Type 6
Density: Moderate
Angle: 90 to 90
Legs: Long to Short

Connection Type 7
Density: Moderate
Angle: 30 to 30
Legs: Medium to Medium

Connection Type 8
Density: Moderate
Angle: 30 to 90
Legs: Medium to Short

Connection Type 9
Density: Tight
Angle: 30 to 90
Legs: Medium to Short

Connection Type 10
Density: Tight
Angle: 90 to 90
Legs: Short to Short

Connection Type 11
Density: Tight
Angle: 90 to 90
Legs: Short to Short

62
Simulations
Temperature Connection Type 3
Environment: 5 °F
Nichrome: 200 °F

The warmth exuded by

tested by holding he environ-


ment temperature and air
velocity constant.

The denser module


configurations block more
Right Front
wind and give off more
heat, as can be seen in the Connection Type 6
following flow trajectory visu-
alizations of temperatue.

Mock-Up

Right Front

Connection Type 10

The physical mock-up


tested the wiring, heating,
and structure of the module.

Right Front

63
Plan Phases
Phase 4 - 100% Accumulation (with connection types)

The fences which do not produce mounds may only make use of
planar connection types such as 1, 2, 3, 5, 6, 10 and 11.

The fences in front of the ‘snow fences’ are composed mainly of


dense connection types 10 and 11 as to more easily melt the mounds
they inhabit.

The fences behind the ‘snow fences’ vary much more in density as to
create more or less private micro-climates.

Lounge

Bar
Outdoor Seating

Dance Floor

64
Phase 1 - 0% Accumulation
The hardscape.

Phase 2 - 40% Accumulation


The begining of the snow accumula-
tion.

Phase 3 - 70% Accumulation


Snow continues to accumulate, but
not where the ground is paved, such as
the dance floor.

Phase 5 - 0% Accumulation
The melted snow is collected into pools in
front of the snow fences. The topography is
constructed to maintain access to the pavil-
ion and maximize the amount of wind that will
blow over the water and cool the space in the
Summer months.

65
Module
1. Heats Space
2. Melts Moguls
3. Delineates Space
4. Provides Light and Shade
5. Creates Moguls
6. Reduces Wind Chill

The profile of the branch is a triangle to assure a


rigid connection yet allow for variable configurations.

66
Electrical wire is threaded throughout the branches.
Nichrome, a hybrid of nickel and chromium that heats with
electricity, is spliced in at the connections.

The cap piece is


rotated 15 degrees off center
to allow for multiple connec-
tions to occur in a column-like
fashion without the modules
intersecting.

67
68
Brian Boigon
with Izabel Gass

Gass: I want to discuss a pedagogical exercise that you and Sanford Kwinter
explored in a studio, “Manual for 5 Appliances in the Alphabetical City.”
You set your students to the task of designing five “appliances” as a way
of addressing architecture as a problem of the diagram, in the Foucauld-
ian sense — architecture as the manipulation and organization of human
and material activity. While years have passed since Manual’s publication,
I think its conception marks an important point in the understanding of
what might constitute a “temporal architecture,” — an understanding of
which contemporary discourse has largely lost sight. Two ideas in particular
interest me here:

1. First, you proposed Manual as a way to “reconceive architecture


outside the classical framework, which is the problem of form and its rep-

69
resentation (hylomorphism).” In many ways, contemporary practices that
claim to embrace an ethos of “dynamism” still understand the architectural
act as the conjuring of “form” from a formless material substrate. Innova-
tions in digital technology have in fact increased this tendency in thinking,
providing programs that administer “forces” on “matter”, resulting in
computer-generated representations of “form.” Using “Manual for 5 Ap-
pliances” as a springboard, in what ways could architecture really transcend
its reliance on the hylomorphic mindset to become actually dynamic?

Boigon: In the academic mayhem of architecture and urbanism (now one


and the same), the question of what you have called dynamically generated
form should first be historically framed by identifying the mediocrity of its
trailer park attendees and their attendant rules, known, to the outside world,
as “Design Pedagogy.” While there have been intensive transformations in
the tools, language, and influencers that have surpassed ‘real’ architecture,
there has been very little homework done by the staff of the surrounding
amusement parks called “Universities” and “Colleges” to update their
rides.

Compare: The recent computational masterpiece of folding mat-


ter in the feature film The Transformers, or the real time online motion
pathways contained by X-Box 360s, Halo3, or the new urbanisms called
Social Networks, such as Facebook (where up to 40% of a teenager’s time
is spent consuming-producing space and event sequences using everything
from a mobile phone-cam to the new dimensional elevation of architecture
known to tween-kind as IM chat windows).

With: Architectural teachings.

70
And you get to see: How off-mark the world of architecture is from
its internal banter and its failure to keep up with the downloadable Jone-
ses.

We (meaning the pedagogical angels of academia itself) have yet


to catch up to the follow-me generation with relevant upgrades to our
pedagogy 1.0 circa 17th Century Descartes, 18th Century Johnson, 19th
Century Rousseau and 20th Century Pavlov. Now this... the 21st Century-
South Park, Second Life, Grey’s Anatomy, YouTube, Futurama, Jetman,

Jackass, Perez Hilton, the Ipod, Facebook, Cell phone with unlimited Text
Messaging, Bratz TV, Batteries sold separately...are the new fuel and pro-
grammable chips for our architecture design schools. Professors then must
press enter after they type in this question on their computers: “Is this thing
working?,” this thing, meaning the actual production of pedagogy itself.
Pedagogy is never really examined in the same way that the actual discourse
of form has been audited throughout the centuries.

71
Professors may look better with laptops, internet, WiFi and course
uploads, podcasts and YouTube lectures, but isn’t the pedagogical model
still basically stuck inside Rousseau’s theory of education as nobilizing the
savagery grafted onto the French Judicial system, (alias — design critique)
guilty until proven innocent?

Are we, as teachers, just playing our golden oldies on new plat-
forms?

Unaccountable atoms aside, Pedagogy has, since the 17th century,


positioned the teacher as the purveyor of intellectual produce and the
student as mass consumer. The flaw, here in today’s world, of thinking and
being, is that the digital age has reduced all matter to an inconsequential
set of talking numbers...and that has coincided with the rise of new con-
sumer-producer culture (Playlists, YouTube, on Demand Cable, Facebook,
My Space, Secondlife.com). In truth, the student has become the producer
and the teacher has become the consumer. This reversal of information
ecology at the level of a Pedagogical discourse (the assembly of pedagogical
texts, reliable sources— not Wikipedia and Google) has been hiding from
the guns and roses of video games and flirt networks. We (meaning anyone
who teaches a thing) are negligent in our practice to not look first at what
Heidegger called “the first dwelling,” our bodies, and to see where they have
landed in time and space before we utter a language of knowledge that sets
out to describe an order of things which no longer exists.

By the way... I divided your question of student producing com-


putational automaton form into two coupled parts: a dynamical system is
fundamentally a coupling of A THING, like a car, and another THING,
like a trailer. There is the bilateral movement of the hitch pin against the

72
friction of wind, left to right, and then there is the subscription to forward
motion by the pull of the car. In other words, when you start your engines,
everything is moving and you never stand still. Our X and our Y axes are
vibrating in a blender.

We must therefore foreground any discussion of dynamical systems


theory in what I currently call the “follow me generation.” This — or rather,
“they” — are the moving conveyors of the social. If we are to understand
dynamical system theory at all, it would not wholly reside within the math-
ematical formula that was first rendered into a CGI script by Alias Software
in Toronto. To reduce the mathematician’s formula for computational
lathing around a behavioral axis called the “spline” would do some justice
to the advancement of life at Pixar but it would also ignore the devices that
intermediate between self and others such as mobile phones, texting and
Instant Messaging.

A dynamical system for architecture today is actually a social matrix


and not a system at all. Intermittent lines of flight are what we now have
here... and there. Imagine us at a Toshiba ring assembly plant all working
on a car made out of virtual macrame—rendered across a desert of multiple
screens (Computer/Laptop/Mobile Phone/Television). This is the world of
dynamical dwelling. This and That are of concern to me as are Here, There
and everywhere as the social interweaving rises into a chaotic critical mass
...spikes and then settles down to reframe itself like a house party does. I ask
you: Design and Pedagogy: “Is this thing working?”

Gass: Secondly, in the Manual, you explore the Diagram as a way of un-
derstanding architecture, “not by how it appears but by practices: Those
it partakes of and those that take place within it.” What might it mean

73
for architecture to extrapolate a theory of form along these lines, perhaps
in the vein of, say, Pierre Bordieu’s Outline of a Theory of Practice, or any
similar anthropological approach? (Certainly Foucault’s work would be of
paramount relevance here.)

Boigon: When Sanford Kwinter and I first conceived of the studio “5 Ap-
pliances in The Alphabetical City”, there were several fundamental social
attributes that we decided to define as having architectural meaning. The
most pervasive of those attributes was—and still remains for me—the Dia-
gram. Specifically, diagrams that impact the body in real time and space.
For example: social lines, chalk on the pavement that becomes a hop-scotch
game; sports lines, such as those inscribed on basketball courts, football
fields, tennis courts and running tracks; traffic control for the “parking
spot” and roadway lines. We referred to these types of diagrams (from a
quote in my book Speed Reading Tokyo from 1990) as “Diagrammatical
Reality.” Meaning, we found diagrams that were first and foremost cast
as guidelines for the body and its machines. As we excavated the diagram
from the thousand plateaus of innocuous presence, we made it clear in
our studio that a diagrammatical reality could be as physically restrictive
as the extrusions of windows, walls, floors and corridors which grow out of
the lines which one uses to distinguish the total architecture of a potential
building. And now this, the diagram was simply a tipping point into a world
of geometry that never led to form and yet changed the movement of bodies
in space which in turn would set off a chain reaction then leading to some
awesome climax called a goal, basket, hole, spot, love and culminating in
the coupled words hitched together in the bliss against time: “The Finish
Line” and “Game Over.”

Gass: In what ways can the chronotope of the “diagram” permeate the

74
representational realm? Might we find a correlation, for instance, between
the Deleuzian notion of “smooth space” (the space of lines rather than
contours, vectors rather than segments, the space of ‘direction’ not ‘place’)
and the dynamic landscape that you have explored in technological innova-
tions of the cartoon?

Boigon: The answer is yes. One can most certainly draw a correlation be-
tween the life of the diagram in “vectors/direction” and landscape in “the
cartoon.”

Despite its 2 dimensions, the diagram can impact the third dimen-
sion. The 2-cause and 3-effect dyad is not without segmentation and a loss
of depth. What is at stake in setting out to demarcate the surface is the
“stake” itself. What we have lost is the ability to hold ground for more than
an instant. The Automobile, Electricity, The Internet, Mobile Phone to
name but a few of the accelerators of time and space conduct our move-
ments. Such is the life of a mobile society which gives up its stake in the
ground for a currency of lines and interoperability that constantly gives
you the option to either take part with or without your body and multiple
personality.

As particle physics has revealed, the surface is deep and nowhere is


that more apparent than in the brilliant luminosity of the blinking cursor at
the entry line on a computer text code line/word processing program. The
Cursor and its Double has both surface and infinite depth as it breathes,
as it beats, as it glows, as it pulses. The cursor is alive and stakes out life,
living computational consciousness, across the screen. There has been no
other creature born in computational space that has such profound allu-
sions to life and to which we can recall every frame from every television

75
show, feature film, how the cursor buys time for the director, creates space
for the user, turns the effervescence of light from simply being a screen to
that of becoming a being. We have here, the cursor, the very first offspring
of digital space that is both diagram, representation, signage, border and
the emotional intelligence. The cursor is the first interface to dwell in a new
architecture of computer networks and communications.

To Note: Architecture is one of the great cross disciplinary arts and


must be defended against the master narrative of Architecture = Build-
ing. If you want to make your architecture into a building, enter through
Marcel Duchamp’s “Door 11.” An architecture design school should offer
Duchamp’s “Door 11” and other doors that lead to absolutely nothing and
everything. We must, still to this day, oppose the reductionism and surren-
dering of architecture to its profession as a “building-only” public service,
when indeed architecture as a discourse and discipline provides a completely
infinite and provocative speculation on the meaning of dwelling and shelter
from the multi-identities that one fashions on through electronic devices
— say, the fakery of a cell phone call on the street to create a social buffer.

76
Architectures of Time Sanford Kwinter
MIT Press, 2001

reviewed by David Dahlbom

There is an underlying, indeed motivating, dissatisfaction with the


current state of affairs evident throughout Sanford Kwinter’s Architectures
of Time: Toward a Theory of the Event in Modernist Culture (2001, from
material originally published 1984 - 87). Kwinter states flatly: “the era of
cultural production we are traversing is unarguably one of impoverishment
and mediocrity.”  His book must therefore be understood as a response to
this condition—an attempt to find a way out. Kwinter emphasizes that this
way out cannot be found in critique, which is doomed by its very nature to
a continual re-inscription within existing conditions, but instead in, and

i. Kwinter, Architectures of Time, p. 5

77
only in, novelty. Much of the work is therefore dedicated to exploring the
conditions necessary for the creation of novelty, and specifically defining a
conception of novelty in an immanentist cosmology.

Kwinter outlines two conceptions of morhpogenesis, one appropri-


ate to a world capable of sustaining transcendental ontological categories,
and the another inherent in a world of perfect immanence. According to the
classical, hylomorphic model, a necessarily limited number of possibilities
(forms or images) are reproduced (mirrored in reality) over a substratum, in
a linear time-line. The insufficiency of such a model, however, is evident in
its inability to find a place for novelty. Something either is or is not possible.
This model cannot account for new possibilities and it fails to confront the
inevitable imperfections and degradations evident in all of its realizations. It
is indeed the inevitability of corruption and imperfection inherent in classi-
cal “creation” that points to the second mode of morphogenesis. This mode
is dependent on an understanding of the world as “a ceaseless pullulation
and unfolding, a dense evolutionary plasma of perpetual differentiation
and innovation.” ii In this world forms are not carried over from some tran-
scendent realm, but instead singularities and events emerge from within
a rich “plasma” through the continual and dynamic interaction of forces.
The morphogenetic process at work in such a world is not one whereby
an active subject realizes forms from a set of transcendent possibilities,
but rather one in which virtualities are actualized through the constant
movement inherent in the very forces that compose the world. Virtuality is
understood here as “free difference or singularity, not yet combined with
other differences into a complex ensemble or salient form.” iii Kwinter offers
the example of Hans Jenny’s Kymatic images, in which tones were emitted

ii. Ibid, p. 4
iii. Ibid, p. 8

78
across steel plates on top of which had been placed a layer of fine powder.
The patterns produced in this powder (the actualization) are the product
of the way the tone interacts with the complex metallurgical properties of
the plate (the virtual components). Kwinter is keen to emphasize here both
that the virtual is real even when it is not actualized, and that actualization
itself occurs in and with time.iv

It is of course this immanentist description of the world and its at-


tendant mode of morphogenesis that Kwinter posits as viable, and he is clear
that it leaves no room for the classical model, at least from an ontological
standpoint. There is no “threshold beneath which classical objects, states,
or relations cease to have meaning yet beyond which they are endowed with
a full pedigree and privileged status.”  Indeed, it is the nature of real time
to ensure “a constant production of innovation and change” in all condi-
tions.vi This is evidenced precisely by the “imperfections” introduced in an
act of “realizing” a form. The classical mode of morphogenesis, then, has to
be understood as a false model which is imposed on what is actually a rich,
perpetually transforming universe. But the sort of novelty which the enact-
ment of the classical model produces, a novelty which from its own perspec-
tive must be construed as a defect, is not of primary concern for Kwinter.
The novelty which interests him registers its status as having emerged from
a complex collision of forces. Above all, it is a novelty uncontaminated by
procrustean notions of subjectivity and creation.

Kwinter offers a series of models of this sort of novelty, the most


significant of which are found in the works of Sant’Elia and Kafka. Kwinter

iv. For complete discussion, see Ibid. pp. 6-10


v. Ibid, p. 49
vi. Ibid, p. 109

79
does not, however, put forward their work as something which is to be di-
rectly imitated; this would only mean a return to a representational mode of
thought. Indeed, the crux of his examination of both of these figures lies in
establishing the non-representational nature of their productions. Sant’Elia
embodies “a new orientation toward a phenomenal field of events and in-
teractions—not objects, but the abstract regimes of force that organize and
deploy them.” It is precisely his “orientation” toward the world that permits
the works to “assume, rather than represent, an extended field of movement
and circulating forces.” vii Similarly, Kafka is portrayed as an author who does
not attempt to bring forth works from his private, creative internal space,
but as someone fully embedded in his world. He is characterized as a sort
of catalyst whose productions are the result of his own complex mechanism
interacting with the forces surrounding and traversing him.

What is at stake here then is not establishing models of works to


be imitated so much as identifying the conditions for the emergence of
novel works. To pose a question more specifically: what behavior or mode
of existence is Kwinter encouraging in order to maximize the production
of that radical novelty which might overturn the present state of affairs? To
address this question properly we must first examine the behaving mecha-
nism itself, what it has traditionally been called “the subject.”

From the outset, it must be made clear that the category of the
subject (like that of the object) has no place in an immanent world. There
can be no transcendent, subjective essence. What, then, is the ontological
status of a body and its attendant instance of consciousness? In what would
it exist? Kwinter here offers:

vii. Ibid, p. 83

80
It would exist precisely in the ever-shifting pattern of mixtures
or composites: both internal ones —the body as a site marked
and traversed by forces that converge upon it in continuous
variation; and external ones—the capacity of any individu-
ated substance to combine and recombine with other bodies
or elements (ensembles), both influencing their actions
and undergoing influence by them. The ‘subject’ ... is but a
synthetic unit falling at the midpoint or interface of two more
fundamental systems of articulation: the first composed of the
fluctuating microscopic relations and mixtures of which the
subject is made up, the second of the macro-blocs of relations
or ensembles into which it enters. The image produced at the
interface of these two systems—that which replaces, yet is too
often mistaken for, subjective essence—may in turn have its
own individuality characterized with a certain rigor. For each
mixture at this level introduces into the bloc a certain number
of defining capacities that determine both what the ‘subject’
is capable of bringing to pass outside of itself and what it is
capable of receiving (undergoing) in terms of effects.viii

This description is sufficient to explain the immanent nature of the


subjective bloc as something entirely embedded in and conditioned by its
surroundings. What it does not offer—and what is not offered in any detail
in the entirety of the work— is an in-depth account of what, exactly, these
“defining capacities” are. To be sure, it would be unfair to demand a com-
plete description of these capacities. Kwinter himself has elsewhere referred
to the states of the nervous system as “magically complex” and he continues
to express a deep interest in the study of human cognitive and perceptual

viii. Ibid, p. 110

81
apparatus.ix Regardless of the specificity with which these capacities can
presently be defined, we must nonetheless agree that it is at this interface, as
he calls it, at this location where so many systems are densely overlaid, that
consciousness is produced. We may be convinced that this consciousness,
this apparent internal space of thought, is derived entirely from immanent
conditions and can only be granted the ontological status of an effect, but
this effect still manages to produce certain difficulties when attempting to
define modes of behavior appropriate to an immanent world.

There is a palpable suspicion of the role of consciousness throughout


Kwinter’s work, at least insofar as it is equated with some kind of internal,
subjective space. (In one text he optimistically awaits the day when this
space will “be left utterly in shreds.” xi) The basis of this suspicion is mul-
tiple and obvious. Among the capacities of consciousness is the ability to
attribute to itself the (false) image of a stable and transcendent essence.
The workings of consciousness are precisely what allow the subjective bloc
to orient itself in a sequence of time, separating itself from an absolute
experience of the moment. It is within consciousness that limiting and
arbitrary moral categories seem to most stubbornly lodge themselves. (To
be sure this is the location of all critical thought.) And, above all, conscious-
ness may serve as the repository for conditioned behaviors which believe
themselves to be free of external determination. Consciousness, in short,
contains within itself an enormous number of limiting factors which would

ix. Kwinter, ‘Virtual City, or the Wiring and Waning of the World’, Assemblage 29, p. 92 See
the discussion of architecture and science in the previous issue of Manifold for more on Kwinter’s
interest in the potentials of scientific examination of the human perceptual apparatus.
x. For a discussion of the derived nature of the “subject-effect”, see Kwinter’s discussion of the
event, Architectures of Time, p. 98
xi. Boigon and Kwinter, ‘Manual for 5 Appliances in the Alphabetical City: a pedagogical text’,
Assemblage 15, p. 35

82
retard the production of novelty. Insofar as it appears to possess the ca-
pacity for self-determination, this capacity would seem most productively
applied by turning on itself—that is, precisely by making the choice not
to make conscious decisions and instead to permit oneself to be seized by
extra-subjective forces.xii

The basic incongruity of consciousness in an immanent world finds


its most clear expression in Kwinter’s invocation of Bataille’s claim that
“[t]he true impulse at the basis of life is the impulse towards indistinction,
continuity, unconsciousness (notably the philosophical un-self-conscious-
ness), and death.” xiii In particular, this impulse may be manifested in a
fascination with animality: “For animality is immediacy (l’immédiateté)
and immanence. The animal, in other words, inhabits its world in pure and
perfect continuity; its glance is totally devoid of “intelligence” (science)
and self-consciousness—and yet the animal is neither a mere object nor
does it belong to this world of the human.” xiv But for all the desire to free
oneself from the limiting confines of consciousness, it is clear that neither
becoming animal nor “inflicting a mortal wound to one’s biological being”
constitutes a viable option.xv

Kwinter does however offer us various examples of behaviors that


seem to sidestep the limitations of conscious behavior. In his “pedagogi-
cal” text, “Manual for Five Appliances in the Alphabet City,” written with
Brian Boigon, he notes that in fact an instantaneous, non-reflective mode

xii. Instructive in this connection is Alain Badiou’s characterization of Deleuze’s theory of


choice. See Badiou, The Clamor of Being, p. 11. See also Deleuze’s discussion of Bresson and the
“purified automaton” in Cinema 2: The Time-Image, pp. 177-179
xiii. Kwinter, Architectures of Time, p. 177
xiv. Ibid, p. 178
xv. Ibid, p. 179

83
of “inhabitation happens all the time, at the cinema and watching TV,
weaving through traffic, or reading an air terminal schedule (not to men-
tion all recently emerged forms of provisional tenancy such as logging on,
downloading, jacking in).” xvi Much of the text, moreover, is devoted to
strategies that would limit conscious guidance and critical or evaluative
reflection. The “principle of speed,” which does not permit the reflective
consciousness to interrupt the constant flow of production, is an obvious
example.xvii Indeed, the whole process of making evaluative judgments is
purposely subverted by a continually affirmative (and explicitly amoral)
philosophy of “‘just say yes.’” xviii

Other models of non-reflective behavior are discussed in the open-


ing chapter of Architectures of Time, specifically those of the surfer and of
the rock climber. In these activities also the subjective bloc abandons, or
at least does not activate, its capacity for conscious guidance or evaluation.
The surfer depicted in the opening image of the book could not possibly
survive the wave he is about to engage if he were forced to consciously
calculate and determine every minute adjustment of his body. Rather, he
must intuitively find his way down, spontaneously reacting to the unpre-
dictable development of the water beneath him. Similarly the rock-climber,
whose every limb and digit is conditioned to operate spontaneously and
independently in response to a complex and unpredictable surface, could
never afford “a strategic command center that programmed the body to
behave globally in response” to a generalized understanding of the climbing
conditions.

xvi. Boigon and Kwinter, p. 35


xvii. Ibid, p. 36
xviii. Ibid, p. 35

84
To these examples we might also add the experiment (scientific or
otherwise), insofar as this is understood to be an establishment of what is
ultimately an impersonal process that leads to results independent of any
specific guiding hand.xix

While we may agree that genuine novelty cannot be brought into


existence by some consciously guided, “creative” process, we need to fur-
ther specify the role of conscious behavior in the creation of the conditions
for the production of novelty. We may begin by noting that while all of
the activities above involve a period in which conscious guidance is neces-
sarily relinquished, in every case there is also at least a moment in which
conscious guidance must be exercised. The examples of the rock climber
and surfer are particularly notable for the obvious need of prior condition-
ing before the more spectacular performances are possible. This process
of conditioning inevitably involves some degree of conscious evaluation.
One must isolate an area for mastery (surfing, rock-climbing), familiarize
oneself with the basic techniques in this realm, learn to shift one’s weight
in ways that at first might seem counterintuitive, tell oneself to stay calm.
It is only once these various conscious actions have been ingrained in the
subjective bloc, once they have become automatic mechanisms, that con-
scious guidance can again be relinquished. Similarly, the construction of an
experiment demands a period of conscious construction that precedes the
impersonal course of its actual execution.

To approach the same issue from another position, we might note


that the mere ability to get outside of one’s confining internal space,
though a necessary condition for the production of substantial novelty, is

xix. Kwinter, ‘Virtual City, or the Wiring and Waning of the World’, Assemblage 29, p. 92. For
a brief discussion of the experiment, see Manifold I, p. 11.

85
not the only such condition. Let us return to the example of the television,
mentioned earlier as a model of non-reflective behavior:

Herein lies the specific beauty and insidiousness of television:


it easily lures attention with its flow—it lures attention easily
because it lures it initially along its pathway of least work or
resistance—then, once captured, confines and tunnels it into
rigid, disconnected pathways of predigested, continually, but
only infinitesimally, varying monotony.xx

To be clear, Kwinter never makes the inane suggestion that simply


giving oneself up to anything, be it television or scientific experiment, is
a guarantee of novelty. What is perhaps not given sufficient attention,
though, is the critical, evaluative process whereby one would make the
determination of whether watching TV is the worth the time.

All of this is to suggest that the conditioning of the subjective bloc


can never be escaped entirely. The dangers and limitations of acting as a
self-determining “creator” of forms are made perfectly evident in this study.
Insofar as the consciousness associated with a given subjective bloc takes its
own existence as evidence of some fixed subjective essence, it has become a
blockage point in the production of novelty. It is doomed to act within the
boundaries of what it thinks it knows, capable only of critique and represen-
tation. But activity that is never interrupted by conscious reflection exposes
itself to limitations of its own. The subjective bloc that exhibits behavior
characterized by the “relative blindness of an immanent viewpoint” is open
to novelty but is incapable of monitoring itself.xxi It exposes itself to the risk

xx. Kwinter, ‘Virtual City’, p. 95


xxi. Kwinter, Architectures of Time, p. 127

86
of falling into unconscious and unproductive patterns. Consciousness must
finally be seen not as the grounds for some creative process, but, in part,
as an auto-regulatory mechanism. This mechanism must be continually
activated to introduce alterations not only into “the world,” but also within
the nebulous and changing boundaries of subjective bloc out of which it
arises.

87
88
Duration and Simultaneity Henri Bergson
Clinamen Press, 1999

reviewed by Matthew Conti

Duration and Simultaneity was written by Henri Bergson in the


early 1920’s to explore how his concept of duration (lived time) fit with
Einstein’s special theory of relativity. As with almost all of Bergson’s major
writings, he set out to see if he could solve a specific problem. In this case,
Bergson’s goal was to update philosophy and its conception of time in a
similar manner to the way Einstein’s flurry of papers on relativity displaced
a stale Newtonian physics in 1905.

Duration and Simultaneity presents a flawed and at times para-


doxical argument that has endured almost continuous controversy in the
80 years since its publication. The predicament a reader of Duration and
Simultaneity finds oneself in is twofold. On one hand, the reader has to
understand Einsteinian physics, and the mistakes Bergson is making in his
reading of the special theory of relativity. On the other hand, the reader
needs to understand how this book relates to Bergson’s earlier writings,

89
especially Bergson’s concept of duration, which he first lays out in Time
and Free Will, and develops further in Matter and Memory and Creative
Evolution.

In these and other earlier writings, Bergson investigates the char-


acteristic differences between time as it is lived and time as a measurable
and quantifiable phenomenon. Through this, he builds a scientific founda-
tion for intuition that accounts for what he sees as two critically different
and mutually exclusive ways of knowing. One way, the way of Newtonian
science, sees the universe in discrete and spatial terms (as an actual or
“discrete multiplicity”). The other way, the way of intuition, sees the uni-
verse as continuous, immediate and in a perpetual state of flux (a virtual or
“continuous multiplicity”).

Focusing on the continuous multiplicity, Bergson argues that hu-


man understanding does not move from perception to recollection, but
instead moves from recollection to perception. With this observation he
articulates his notion of duration, a concept he illustrates with his famous
diagram of a cone (representing the totality of recollections accumulated
in one’s memory) and a plane (representing the perceivable universe). It
is at the intersection of the cone’s point and the plane where difference
is developed in relation to the contraction and relaxation (position in the
cone) of the totality of memory, where the past and present exist at once.
This differentiation, which can only be grasped by intuition, is continuous
and qualitative and is the defining feature of lived time or duration. It is
this immediate and individualized definition of duration, not the expanded
version described in Creative Evolution, which Bergson is attempting to
reconcile with the special theory of relativity in Duration and Simultane-
ity.

90
Bergson’s central criticism of Einstein in Duration and Simul-
taneity is that Einstein mistakes a discrete multiplicity for a continuous
multiplicity, failing to see that time begins with duration, not the relative
speeds of objects in space. Bergson appreciates the radicality of relativity,
but believes the theory is undermined by its dependence on the observer.
However, as he tries to prove this, the paradoxical aspects of Duration and
Simultaneity become apparent. For Bergson, the notion of simultaneity
implies at least two perceptions understood through a single mental act,
the smallest possible division of duration. Given this, Bergson is critical of
Einstein’s ability to ascertain if two events are simultaneous, but Bergson is
also locking himself into a phenomenological argument which is even more
dependent on the observer than Einstein’s thought experiments with light
clocks. This paradox is further complicated by Bergson’s investigation of
the role of the Lorentz equations, which leads him to believe in complete
reciprocity between the relative times of different frames of reference. In
essence, Bergson’s conclusion here is that the special theory of relativity can
be simplified because the multiple times it predicts are mathematical fic-
tions, and the time dilation which the hypothetical observer sees is nothing
more complicated than the Doppler Effect with lightwaves.

The glaring omission here is that Bergson only briefly discusses time
dilation, and when he does, he gets it wrong. To be fair to Bergson, this
concept is only alluded to in the special theory of relativity, and is explained
with clarity only in the general theory of relativity, which Bergson does not
explore. Nonetheless, Bergson fails to acknowledge that it is possible for
subjective consciousness to accelerate from one temporal frame of refer-
ence to another, which is to say, he fails to acknowledge that duration also
presents a form of time that is by nature inconstant. Bergson thus falsely
concludes that there is one universal duration (time) encompassing all

91
other durations.

While this conclusion seems like a fatal error for Bergson’s argu-
ment, the mistake does not completely derail Bergson’s central argument
that the “temporality” of time itself begins with duration. Bergson’s intent
is to update the philosophical conception of time through an investigation
of Einsteinian relativity. Although his flawed analysis of the special theory
of relativity brings him into conflict with Einstein and other physicists, the
concept of a single duration still has traction regardless of the nature of
time dilation, inasmuch as an intuitive duration does not imply an absolute
and universal temporal frame of reference.

When Bergson and Einstein met in 1922, Einstein concluded their


conversation by stating that there was an unbridgeable gap between the
time of the physicist and the time of the philosopher. The closest a physicist
will get to defining time is to say that it is what we measure with clocks. It is
therefore left to the philosopher to interpret time as duration. And thus the
gap remains between physics and philosophy, until neuroscience and more
recent developments in physics take us inside the flow of duration.

92
LECTURES

93
94
Islands and Worlds Reinhold Martin
reviewed by Jamie Chan

Troubled by the “difficulty that by material conditions.” He spoke


many architects, students, and theo- with urgency, arguing that the
rists seem to have today in thinking ability for a creative mind to think
a radical thought and imagining a a utopian thought is what drives
utopian future,” Reinhold Martin future change, and thoughts today
spoke boldly of a “re-theorization” about changing the world are van-
of the Postmodern project in archi- ishing rapidly.
tecture — the formulation of a new
framework for utopian thinking by Understanding the present is es-
way of reexamining postmodern- sential to thinking about the future.
ism. Martin’s introduction therefore
dove straight into the heart of the
According to Martin, utopia present globalization debate where
is not a place or an ideal city but mega-structures and transnational
rather a “thought made possible networks threaten to ‘undermine

95
the authority of capital cities’ and that globalization not only paral-
breed inhuman spaces. This is lels postmodernism; it upholds it.
the place of the Multi-National Clearly more than stylistic mixing
City (MNC), and Multi-National or suburban sprawl, the term ‘post-
Corporation—an acronym coined modernism’ in Martin’s lecture is
from Martin’s previous work. He used in an abstract sense, to de-
remarked that, ‘The term Multi- scribe ‘displacement and untimeli-
National Corporation can seem ness.’ The point was driven home
dated in one place while all too as he referred to ‘that hallmark of
current in another.’ In essence, postmodernism—“the presence of
our present, globalized condition is the past.”’
characterized by “a certain disjunc-
tion, a certain déjà vu in both time And just as we began to ask,
and space.” This image of disjunc- ‘where is utopia in all of this?’
tion led Martin to quote colleague Martin told us that it never left us
Andreas Huyssen, who describes inasmuch as Postmodernism’s very
the present interdisciplinary de- utterance is also a negation—that
bates on globalization as analogous is, a negation of Modernism. There-
to those of postmodernism in the fore, the Modernist desire for uto-
1980’s because both are defined by pia remains embedded within the
the same anachronistic qualities. Postmodern ‘undead,’ a ghost that
By matching these descriptions of haunts us in unexpected places;
anachronism in postmodernism Martin declares: “the name of the
and globalization, Martin implied ghost is Postmodernism itself.”

96
Thus we are haunted intermi- ‘hole’ in the island that leads back
nably, unable to escape this ghost to the outside world is real; partici-
of Postmodernism as we continually pants are never trapped inside. In
catch glimpses of a ghastly utopia, another words, ‘an island is never
or as Martin tells us, ‘what’s not just an island’—it leads back to the
supposed to be there.’ Utopia and mainland.
its ghost were made more evident
in Martin’s numerous examples. Martin also uncovered the
He presented French semiologist association between ‘nowhere
Louis Marin’s diagrams of Thomas and no-place’ and utopia, as he
More’s Utopia—a crescent-shaped was quick to point out that, in
island drawn three times, each de- multiple instances, “postmodern
picting a capital city in a different architecture is full of roads that
location with respect to the water’s lead to nowhere.” Among many
edge—which served the purpose of examples there was the Strada
disclaiming Utopia’s fixed image. Novissima (‘the very image of his-
Martin also showed a map of Dis- tory going nowhere’) and Hejduk’s
neyland, in which its participants Berlin Mask (which ‘performs a
were cut off from the real world story about nowhere’). He also
while they enjoyed themselves in discussed the work of Ungers, who
a scaled-down reconstruction of it. documented American communes
Martin pointed out that despite the and created an inventory of uto-
common criticism of Disneyland’s pian experiments. Through these
isolated, counterfeit reality, the examples Martin demonstrated

97
that the ‘island of architecture has sible” through architecture. If one
a hole in it that leads back out to sees the value of his argument, it is
the world at large.’ an empowering and enormous first
step.
It may seem odd at first when
one realizes that Martin, with his
roundabout logic and negation-
based dialectics, is using the very
thing he is trying to escape to make
his argument, but it serves to prove
his point that we are still unable to
flee the paradigm of Postmodern-
ism. We are made aware that if we
choose not to acknowledge it, to
throw it out the window, so to speak,
we trap ourselves in another world
within it once again. By identifying
the ‘ghost’, Martin cleverly uses
Postmodernism as a springboard—a
starting point at which he ushers
in a new way of thinking in which
“another world can be made pos-

98
Writing on Architecture Yale University
reviewed by Stephen Nielson

Panel Discussion tecture. The night’s talk, moderated


Yale School of Architecture by Yale University Press Director
“Writing on Architecture” John Donatich, aimed to shift our
focus from the visual to the textual.
Peter Eisenman Summoning the haunting verse of
Luis Fernández-Galiano John Ruskin, Donatich defined the
Kurt Forster dual nature of architecture as hav-
Paul Goldberger ing both responsibilities to shelter
Robert A.M. Stern and speak to us. Focusing on the
John Donatich, Moderator latter he hoped that with the varied
perspectives of the panel the dis-
Presented in conjunction with the cussion might “parse the qualities
Whitney Humanities Center of not only the ways in which build-
ings speak to us [and] chat about
Monday, October 8 what the jobs of those who write
about architecture is.” Through a
series of questions directed mostly
towards architectural criticism, he
A panel of six representatives
attempted to define oppositions
from various positions in the field
around the relationship of people to
convened to discuss, inflate, and
the built environment. The critic is
deflate the role of writing in archi-
asked to try on many hats as poten-

99
tial educator, aesthetic champion, defined criticism as, “a disinterested
soldier of public well-being, or social endeavor to learn and propagate the
activist. These provocations speak best that is known and thought in
to the question of architectural the world.” It was from this point
communication. that he built his case for the critic
as primarily an educator. To him,
As the only official “critic” on the lofty ambition of the critic to,
the panel, Paul Goldberger was the through written communication,
one to address the questions posed serve as an ambassador of intellect
by Donatich in defining the role to the people is in fact at least a
of the critic. He first cited notable part of the job. This task, however,
‘critics of critics,’ quoting Sir Henry comes with the peril of judgment.
Walton’s comparison of the critic to While honest journalism is of
the “washer of nobleman’s clothes” course a necessity to good criticism
and increased the fervor of his as- it is in promotion and chiding that
sault with a line from Lord Byron a qualitative assessment must be
who wrote that, “one might as soon made. For clarity in judgment he
seek roses in December, ice in June, insisted that the critic maintain a
hope constancy in the wind, or corn distance from issues of aesthetic
in the chaff, believe a woman or an choice. With these issues in check,
epitaph before you trust in critics.” the remaining requirement for the
To these rather disheartening com- critic is quite simply a love of the
ments Goldberger noted a positive subject. If the critic can effectively
rebuttal in Matthew Arnold who convey that love to his or her read-

100
ers, his or her potential to make 2. Not so young architects with
their lives more meaningful and some professional work under their
pleasurable is great. belts write about their work to make
more of it than there really is.
With a panel comprising three
architects, a historian and but one 3. More mature architects
critic, the ensuing conversation was write to carry forward a line of in-
dominated by the question of why vestigation with some seriousness.
architects write, and whether they For example they may look for con-
have any place doing so. Bob Stern, nections with other fields.
with stinging efficacy, distilled
what he believes are the motivators 4. Architects write to make the
behind architects writing, quoted public aware of the contribution
in part, below: architecture makes to the wider
culture.
“1. Very young architects with
little or no work experience in the 5. Architects, like those in so
profession write to make space for many other fields, write to justify
themselves. In this they reach out to the trajectory of their work with the
members of their own generation. hope of influencing history, and in
They also write to create the kind that way with the hope of justifying
of intellectual noise that is likely to their lives. While most other cul-
get the attention of older architects tural figures write autobiographies,
– for better or for worse. Architects prefer to gather their work

101
together in monographs. Blame Pal- coax the two “strange bedfellows”
ladio, whose lead we follow. I would of architecture and writing into
be less-than-candid were I not to cohesive publications, so he further
say that the monographs architects distilled the relationship to the
write about themselves or publish “word” and the “image” in which the
about themselves are self serving. subject, Architecture, clearly favors
But insofar as the work and words in the image. Beyond merely noting
their pages inspire others to spend this hierarchy, Fernández-Galiano
time contemplating the discipline, persecuted architectural writing,
I would also argue that such books citing the poor writing of Vitruvius
serve architecture as a whole.” who was, in his words, “sadly lacking
substance and intellectual distinc-
Luis Fernández-Galiano would tion.” In confirmation of Stern’s
be the only of the presenters to rise comments on self-promotion,
from the table and take the podium. Fernández-Galiano pointed toward
From his pulpit he expounded on the image-heavy monograph as a
“the asymmetrical relationship means of advertising. While the
where architecture is always the general tone of his talk was a humor-
master and writing is reduced to the ous and mildly self-deprecating jab
status of servant” likening the phrase at architectural writing, he did not
“architectural writing” to “British criticize the architect for a reliance
Cuisine” or “German Humor.” As on the image, but simply insisted
the editor of Arquitectura Viva, he, that we come to terms with the
through editorial necessity, must reality of the situation. In the end,

102
Fernández-Galiano admitted that, offer insight beyond the actual sub-
while the craft of writing within ject under consideration. Forster
the field is historically abysmal, evoked Marco Polo, the poet Gurte,
there is nothing to be ashamed of and Karl Friedrich Schinkel as hav-
in this regard, and that we may not ing whetted the appetites of a great
be “happier or wiser if in the world many readers from the far east to
of architecture the word were the northern Europe, respectively. He
master and the image the slave.” observed that Gurte recognized the
existence of a “...third life, amal-
Kurt Forster’s response provided gamating truth and fiction [and]
the much-needed intoxication felt that precisely this borrowed life
to Fernández-Galiano’s sobering enchanted the reader.” Nelson’s
accusations in a discussion of the journals, beginning in 1932, offer
recently re-issued articles of George an American sensibility applied
Nelson. Nelson, a young man of 25, to a transitional period in Europe.
offers what Forster deems, “a kind He wrote home about encounters
of writing about architecture which with an idling Mies van der Rohe,
one could compare to writing home an ambitious though disappointed
about what you’ve seen.” He sum- Le Corbusier, and a remarkable
marized with a German proverb: Margarita Sanfranti. Forster folded
“If you take the trip, you’ll have his tale back into the lesson of the
something to write home about.” day when he commiserates on the
The benefit of this type of writing is inability to locate America, the
the potential for the writing itself to book of Sanfranti, the “Godmother

103
of Italian Architecture.” Forster and so, were it not for publications,
concluded, “so much for the fate of we would have no record of the ex-
books that we typically find inter- istence of a number of buildings; in
twined with the fate of buildings.” this service, “there’s nothing wrong
with a few pictures.” Eisenman of-
Peter Eisenman took specific fered the immortalizing examples
issue, as he does on a weekly basis in of Palladio’s four books – for which
his design studio at Yale, with Luis Palladio himself redrew all of his
Fernández-Galiano. He countered designs as their initial unrealized
that, while architects may, in fact, intent – and Le Corbusier’s Oeuvre
be guilty of the self-promoting Complète and Vers Une Architec-
monograph, “writers also write ture as models, without which we’d
books about themselves and create have lost the buildings to time and
characters that are surrogates for situation. Beyond the book as a
themselves,” citing Proust’s Swann, means of immortalizing the archi-
and Roth’s Zuckerman as examples. tecture, Eisenman cited Venturi’s
He argued that we then must allow Complexity and Contradiction as a
architects a similar outlet. Perhaps text, with minimal readable imag-
the most striking, and insightful, ery, which will certainly far outlast
comment offered by Eisenman was and take priority over its built
that “books are more important counterparts. Including Koolhaas
than buildings.” Eisenman noted with the aforementioned collection
that buildings have a “life of about of writing architects, Eisenman
thirty years, in terms of their value,” concluded that their various un-

104
dertakings are better described as agreed, adding that the architect
“writing architecture.” With this, is the last person you’d want to ask
Eisenman drew a line in the sand, “what it is, or why it is.” Eisenman
making a distinction between the then, again, turned the discussion
independent field of architectural to Complexity and Contradiction
writing, which is comprised of crit- as a book, not about Bob Venturi,
ics and most theorists, and “writing but about presenting a new idea
architecture” which is architecture to American architecture — “the
in the form of productive text and most important book written in the
diagram in support of, and of equal United States about architecture.”
or greater importance to, the built. Bob Stern used this remark to rein-
force his earlier comments, noting
Upon conclusion of the that what Venturi, Koolhaas, Le
increasingly specific individual Corbusier, and Sullivan do is “[try]
presentations, the initially moder- to carve a new place, seeing things
ated conversation returned to the fresh.”
question of the monograph. When
asked of the monograph’s value, On the issue of the visual and
Paul Goldberger characterized it the verbal, Eisenman distinguished
as mostly reference material for between the abilities of the ar-
providing plans and pictures, where chitect and the writer, offering
“rarely is there critical insight that is Jacques Derrida as someone with
meaningful.” This was a comment tremendous ideas to offer those
with which Eisenman promptly who could “see,” whilst lacking

105
the ability to “see,” himself. When to canonical texts do not rely on
asked to provide a philosopher representational imagery, and that
who can “see” Paul Goldberger there is an important distinction
instead looked to Marcel Proust to be drawn between image as rep-
and, upon Eisenman’s suggestion, resentation of a reality and image
Sal Bellow, both of whose writing, as clarification of an architectural
he argued, was about architecture concept—simply a matter of the
and “describe[s] place and build- photograph versus the diagram.
ing often more convincingly than For Eisenman, plans and sections,
architects have.” while consumed by the eye, are not
perceptual phenomena, but instead
The earlier provocations of a means of conveying information
Fernández-Galiano then came to a to the intellect. While Fernán-
head with Eisenman over the utili- dez-Galiano refuses to allow this
zation of images to describe archi- distinction, the point is clarified
tectural ideas. Fernández-Galiano by Paul Goldberger who refined
cited the total editorial control of Eisenman’s descriptor of “picture
Palladio and Le Corbusier, illustrat- postcards” to “sexy, colorful, pretty,
ing the reliance of architectural seductive images ... architectural
texts on the image. It is precisely the porn,” a realm of the visual that,
definition, or classification, of the at least in architecture, Eisenman
image that he and Eisenman have cannot subscribe to.
difficulty synchronizing: Eisen-
man insists that the oft referred Thus, at the conclusion of the

106
evening we saw a rift presenting two
distinct camps. Architectural writ-
ing finds its merit, independent of
architecture’s theoretical projects,
through an inspiration of love for
the subject, or “letters home,” to
much the same end, while “writing
architecture” is subsumed into the
project of architectural autonomy.

107
108
talk20 Philadelphia University of Pennsylvania
reviewed by Jason Nguyen

Entering the Institute for Con- Given the institution’s predilec-


temporary Art (ICA) at the Univer- tion for liberal and intellectual aes-
sity of Pennsylvania on the evening theticism, it’s of little surprise, then,
of October 11th, you would have that such an event found its home
thought you were interrupting an at the ICA, that groundbreaking
ongoing party and not the prelude institution most known for hosting
to a presentation on contemporary the first solo Andy Warhol exhibi-
architecture and design. With syn- tion in 1965 and originating the
thesized beats emanating from the highly controversial Robert Map-
lecture hall, beer and wine being plethorpe: “The Perfect Moment”
served by the glassful and throngs of show in 1989. Though it is unlikely
students and young designers mill- that talk20 will compete with such
ing about the current exhibits, the milestone events, what it does do
scene was fitting for the an event is usher in a refreshing and much-
advertising itself as “not as a lecture needed approach to contemporary
but a gathering, an open forum for architectural discourse.
the dissemination of ideas in art,
architecture and design.” Talk20 began in Philadelphia in

109
February of 2006. Since then, it has issues of theory, practice, fabrica-
spread to six other cities – Boston, tion and culture, all while avoiding
Barcelona, Chicago, Mexico City, (or attempting to avoid, at least)
Spartanburg (South Carolina) and the trap of esotericism which has
Toronto. Its intrigue lies not only come to plague much of theoretical
in the content covered but also in discussions within academe.
the structure of the event itself.
As opposed to having one speaker The October 2007 installment
lecturing, talk20 organizes a central of talk20 Philadelphia, its fourth,
theme and opens the podium to centered on “Feedback.” Though
the designers and academics which the organizers offered little more
typically constitute the audience. than that single word as guidance,
To maintain a swift, steady and it’s hardly shocking that the major-
brevity-attuned dialogue, each ity of the presenters latched on, at
speaker is allowed twenty slides least implicitly so, to prevailing De-
with an allotted speaking time of leuzian philosophy. Though some
twenty seconds per slide. Such a presented projects which adopted
structure forces a direct yet disci- the once-revolutionary, but now
plined conversation which is part seemingly mainstream, use of the
dialogic, part artistic, part critical algorithm as a means of producing
and wholly dynamic. The discus- an architecture representative of
sion remains frank, cutting directly such an ontology, there were quite a
to the conceptual underpinnings few who addressed the theme with a
of each project. Presenters address refreshing and slightly more critical

110
hand. As a complete review of each camera, no set agenda and a jovial
discussion would be far too wide- spirit, his group set out to see what
ranging for a concise review, I’d like it meant to experience Philadelphia
to cover two presentations which for one twenty-four hour period.
addressed the theoretical concepts The experiment was less a lesson
of “feedback” innovatively. in good urbanism, urban semiotics
or post-modern meaning and more
Scott Knowles, Next American an analysis of non-linear, empirical
City existence. As the group transitioned
from one location to another—from
Scott Knowles, a professor of tourist venues leading impromptu
political science at neighboring tours to municipal parks playing
Drexel University, offered an inter- football—each subsequent move
esting perspective of “Feedback” was determined solely by the
in his presentation on the recent adjacencies of the location and
endeavors of non-profit research action taking place. While some
group, The Next American City—a could view this endeavor as mere
group whose interests lie in the spontaneity gone urban, what it ac-
realm of psycho- and political-ge- tually constituted was a lighter, less
ography. In his short presentation, esoteric, approach of addressing the
Mr. Knowles rather chaotically temporal existence which makes up
presented an experiment which he the actual act of experience. The set
and his group conducted the sum- of events – the actions and reactions
mer prior. Equipped with a video which conspired in the creation

111
of the overall experience – was interested in the multiple scales of
not one of reducible, linear, time- urban socio-politics. A quick glance
contingent entities. Instead, these at his oeuvre reveals an interest in
individual events fused to create a the dissolving of physical bound-
whole new event altogether. Fur- aries, architecturally, politically,
ther, their treatment of the city less economically. In his presentation
as an object representing cultural on the project No Man’s Land, he
modulations and more as an active, addressed the dually ecological and
participatory container assisting political role that water takes in
in the propagation of these event the Dead Sea region of the Middle
themselves, proved a fresh, material East. As the Dead Sea continues to
alternative to the algorithmic-based shrink, he claims, the ecological,
architectures of recent years. economical and political nature of
the ever-volatile region has begun
Phu Hoang, Phu Hoang Office LLC to shift. His proposal, thus, takes
(New York) the resorts which line the shores of
the Dead Sea (and which have pos-
Another presentation which of- sibly contributed to its recession)
fered a fresh and decidedly critical and relocates them to a series of ar-
approach to “Feedback” concluded tificial islands within the Sea itself.
the event. Phu Hoang, New York- Interspersed within this system of
based architect and design critic artificial islands would be stations
at the University of Pennsylvania, for desalination for potable water
leads a design and research practice generation, ecological refuge and

112
future development. Such a system with many of the issues which per-
is organized “externally,” each meate contemporary architectural
“island” interacting and affecting discourse. Through the dissemina-
its neighbor in innovative architec- tion of theoretical positions in a
tural and political ways. What he forum for honest, unpretentious
appears to suggest in this proposal dialog, the event allowed for an
is that through transposing current event both casual and intellectual,
social and political entities (enti- dynamic and laid-back, provisional
ties being materially converted to and sustainable.
phylum-organized “islands” in this
project), new cultural realities can
become possible. Furthermore, in a
world where ecological concerns are Talk20 currently exists in seven
becoming increasingly intertwined cities across the globe: Boston,
with the political, it is becoming in- Barcelona, Chicago, Mexico City,
creasingly imperative to introduce Philadelphia, Spartanburg (South
meaningful ideas of sustainabil- Carolina) and Toronto. For more
ity—and its impacts on the critical information, please see http://www.
agenda—to the discourse. talk20.org.

During the whole of the event,


the lecture hall at the ICA was inun-
dated with a series of innovative and
novel proposals implicitly dealing

113
114
FOA Alejandro Zaera-Polo
reviewed by Francis Bitonti

Alejandro Zaera-Polo (of For- discourse has regarded architectural


eign Office Architects) began his surfaces such as floors, walls etc. as
lecture by presenting a taxonomy of differential and continuous. Con-
envelope types: flat, spherical and nectivity of surfaces and various
vertical. The lecture brought forth topological transformations such as
the notion of “envelope” as a coun- stretching and folding have domi-
ter-critique of common themes that nated an architectural language
Alejandro Zaera-Polo has identified oriented towards mediating inten-
in the past five years, both at FOA sive differences between social and
and across the discipline. Zaera-Polo material flows.
noted that architectural projects
are becoming increasingly driven In his lecture, Zaera-Polo
by envelopes and volumes rather brought into question the role of
than flows of intensive properties “the surface” and the significance of
engaging transformations of surface the building envelope. Zaera-Polo
driven geometries. Contemporary argued that architects are asked by

115
developers to define architecture in envelope of a building is inherently
terms of dimension with particular political, and a poignant point of
preference to volume rather than departure for a discussion about the
topological models which are more relationship between politics and
concerned with connectivity. In architecture. The envelope defines
doing so, Zaera-Polo chooses to the legal limits of property and ne-
emphasize volumes above the non- gotiates the division between public
Euclidian geometries which have and private. Zaera-Polo stated that a
recently dominated architectural way of thinking about politics, more
discourse. This brings architecture specifically a “politics of things,” has
into an intellectual arena where been absent from architecture in
extensive rather than intensive recent years. He criticized previous
thinking assumes paramount im- generations of architects for being
portance. In his lecture Zaera-Polo overly pragmatic.
defined envelopes as mediators of
intensive properties rather than As Zaera-Polo describes it, a
surfaces, and therefore imposed an “politics of things,” can be under-
alternate understanding of materi- stood through an emphasis towards
als and geometric transformation the building envelope. The defini-
which hybridizes extensive and tion of geometry, described above,
intensive thinking. accounts for the differentiation of
the three envelope types. While as
In support of his argument, far as topology is concerned each
Zaera-Polo pointed out that the of these three envelope types (flat,

116
spherical, and vertical) are identi-
cal cells, by standards of Euclidian
geometry they define three unique
entities. This perspective allows
architectural typology rather than
topology and nuanced negotiations
between architectural form and
fluctuating cultural and economic
conditions to be reflected through
a contemporary discourse that
politicizes geometric and inten-
sive difference. The emphasis on
Euclidian and metric differences
allows our understanding of mate-
rial organizations to be more closely
linked to economy. As a result the
architectural volume is free to as-
sume a highly politicized role while
intensive differences are regarded
in relation to an understanding
of topology that operates as an
organizing rather than geometric
principle.

117
This may seem to be a surpris- analogous to the notion of the
ing argument from Alejandro “epigenome” in contemporary ge-
Zaera-Polo. However, it should netics. The notion of an epigenome
be noted that projects from FOA, reflects the idea that certain genes
despite being topologically driven can be activated and deactivated as
for many years (for example the a result of conditions in the physi-
Yokohama Port Terminal and cal environment, thus creating
Virtual House), show a tendency differentiation from a single entity
to understand architectural differ- operating autonomously. In Zaera-
entiation though formal typology. Polo’s text, architectural speciation
Phylogenesis, meaning genesis of or rather “Phylogenesis” becomes
type, discusses in great detail the the product of a particular architec-
emergence and mutations of archi- tural genome operating in opposi-
tectural form. The introduction to tion to various local factors such as
the text describes the challenge of socio-economic and programmatic
maintaining the identity of a single demands.
architectural practice while at the
same time taking advantage of the Rather than discussing archi-
potential mutations of architectural tectural projects in terms of static
form that occur when the architect typologies, the text instead looks to
is asked to work within a variety of the patterns through which a type
geographic locations. emerges. This is the realization of
type through intensive differences;
This argument is somewhat in short, architecture has its own in-

118
telligence and does not necessarily the envelope becomes a mecha-
need to borrow geometric models nism through which inhabitants
for expression but only for criticism. mediate their relationship between
Intensive differences create traces themselves and the collective or
upon architecture only in so much “foam” as it is described in the
as they inform the evolution of a essay. Sloterdijk lays a philosophi-
species with its own requirements cal framework for thinking about
for geometric organization. This architecture in terms of envelopes.
justifies structuring the discussion In the case of the apartment build-
around Euclidian transformations ing, Sloterdijk describes the living
which are more appropriate for unit as a discrete and self referential
discerning differences of type with entity while at the same time part
regard to architecture. of a large aggregation.

The philosophy of Bruno Latour While Sloterdijk focuses on


and Peter Sloterdijk were cited in the discrete living unit, Zaera-Polo
the lecture as being an appropriate discussed the building envelope in
point of reference for this discus- relation to the large urban context,
sion. Sloterdijk recently published rather than as a single self referential
an essay in Log titled “Cell Block, entity part of a larger architectural
Egospheres, Self-Container” that composition. Zaera-Polo then dis-
discusses the emergence and sig- cussed the three envelope types.
nificance of the apartment building
in the 20th century. For Sloterdijk, Flat envelopes are horizontal

119
and serve to redefine the ground
plane. Spherical ones are as equally
tall as they are wide; they are
neither horizontal nor vertical.
These volumes have a tendency
to become extremely dense, so it
becomes important for the designer
to always balance their volume with
their surface area. Vertical volumes
have an even stronger relationship
to their skin. The surfaces of these
volumes become a negotiation
between expressing program and
structure.

The argument for envelope-


based design that Zaera-Polo
presented offers a design logic that
engages the larger composition of
the city through the inward looking
model of building construction—
the processes and organizations
that are unique to architecture.

120
Shrinkwrapping Vague Things Neil Denari
reviewed by Molly Wright Steenson

Neil Denari knows how to Ankles, eyes, hands, codes, soft-


interact with his audience, how to ware
explain his projects, how to gauge
the room, how to wield an image. Denari frames arguments with
He can argue about the lineup of photographs. The images oper-
80’s bands that you probably don’t ate on a Lilliputian level, his lens
know. Above all, he is a deft archi- catching young adults in Shibuya
tect with a broad portfolio of built on a sultry August night. From the
projects, one who practices design street-grade vantage, he catches the
at every scale. Denari’s November 7, ankles of his subjects as the camera
2007 lecture at Princeton featured looks up at them against a black
his scalar acrobatics and cultural night sky. They are illuminated by
ergonomics: the process of organiz- small signs and doorways on a side
ing into place a shrinkwrapping of street, and by Shibuya’s grand-
vague things. est interface: the Qfront with its
famous living billboard (the one

121
you remember from Lost in Trans- developed in the early 1980’s out of
lation, with the walking elephant). the desire for the interior behavior
The photographs capture moments of a computer to meet the molded
at different scales. These instances exterior of its hardware. Doing this
shift from the body, to the door, effectively requires an understand-
to the sign, to the street, to the ing of several levels of interiority:
billboard. They catch people’s in- human behavior, system function,
teractions with devices, and yet the and site limitation, to name a few.
devices stand in juxtaposition with Could we see his projects, especially
the spaces they inhabit: a boy holds his interior renovations, as a new
a game controller in a crowded type of software that brings many
arcade; a photocopier backs against interactions into focus?
a sea of blue cubicles opposite a
religious shrine. It is the relation- Pristine, in effect
ship of the hand, the eye, and the
billboard, a triangular interaction, Denari twice mentions
micro-to-mini-to-macro, that De- Antonioni’s Blow-Up during his
nari brilliantly catches. lecture. This isn’t a surprise, given
the ways his zooming in and zoom-
Denari’s moves reflect the ap- ing out reveals what is not available
proach of interaction design. This upon first glance. MUFG Nagoya
discipline creates the products, (a private client center for one
systems and interfaces (usually elec- of the world’s largest banks) uses
tronic) with which people engage. It separations of scant millimeters on

122
panels and joints on its 28-meter and the eye. In construction, the
black stainless steel façade; zygotic elements meld together smoothly,
shapes forming into circles and then vacuum-formed and glossy.
lighting for the entrance; tangerine
custom furniture for the lobby. But Or do they?
zooming out to the High Line 23,
a residential building in New York, With the 1956 House of the Fu-
Denari occupies a different dimen- ture, Peter and Alison Smithson cre-
sion altogether. Here, it is a matter ated a plastic house with undulating,
of hacking building code. Each white, pristine surfaces—at least,
facet of the “leftover” site the 13- in effect. In reality, the Smithsons
story residential tower will occupy is achieved this surface effect through
won through negotiation. “Zoning layers of plaster on plywood: the re-
x Desire = What it takes to build sult of detailed crafting and not of
in Manhattan,” quips the DMNA space-age manufacture. As Denari
website. The building is the mani- zeroes in on the ceiling detail of
festation of these interstices. For the MUFG Ginza banking branch,
the projects he showed, the typical he first shows the underlying metal
plan and program are straightfor- framing. He then notes the mo-
ward, nearly boring. It is always the ment where the wooden surface
building section that shows the po- bends to meet the white, planar
tential and kinetic energy; it is the pathways of the ceiling. But here,
ceiling plan that shows the ulterior appearance and construction differ.
motive for circulation of the body Handworked stucco achieves the

123
effect, not technology. It is similar to Tokyo. Through all its scales of
to the prototyping tools industrial operation, it is the dance of interac-
and automotive designers use as tion that sculpts his immaculate
they model the form factor: they surfaces of covert construction.
sculpt it from clay. Denari wins
with cleverness, for knowing the (Thanks to Shawn Protz and En-
right design tool for the job. When rique Ramirez for their insights.)
technology can’t offer pristine
effects, it doesn’t matter whether
the year is 1956 or 2007. The hand
completes the curve and the eye is
none the wiser.

Shrinkwrapping vague things,


then, commands an understanding
of motion beneath the surface,
bringing things into alignment, the
structures the film clings to. Denari
plies these things on all levels in his
conversations as well as his build-
ings. It is eye, hand and billboard,
the laws and politics governing the
site as much as it is 80’s avant-garde
rock and a contrail connecting LA

124
Mass Mysteria David Erdman
reviewed by Izabel Gass

David Erdman, formerly a


member of the design collaborative
SERVO and now a founding partner
of the firm DavidClovers, was the
2007 Cullinan Visiting Professor of
Architecture at Rice University. He
presented his design work to the Rice
community in a school-wide lecture
titled, “Mass Mysteria.” Erdman
opened his lecture by announcing
his own professional transition
out of SERVO and into practice

125
with wife Clover Lee, explaining between puzzles — quantitative
that their design partnership was problems, or questions with a single
founded “more on our differences or definitive answer — and myster-
than our similarities.” Erdman then ies — questions that can be resolved
showed a slide in which two col- analytically in a number of differ-
umns of text read, respectively: He ent ways. Erdman sees his work as
Likes, She Likes, including state- cultivating “mystery” inasmuch as
ments such as “He Likes Mystery; it develops a visual and spatial com-
She Likes Mass,” and so on. While plexity that demands to be resolved,
this initial introduction expressed a or at least explored, by an engaged
flippant regurgitation of stereotypi- viewer, rather than reverting to the
cal gender roles geared at marketing immediately recognizable iconicity
the “cuteness” of a husband-wife — or “branding strategies”— com-
design team, Erdman’s following mon to the visual language of much
description of his work left little to contemporary architecture.
be desired and in fact suggested a
timely and provocative rupture in Erdman’s field of work backs up
the contemporary museum as well this claim brilliantly. The SERVO
as the domicile. exhibit “Dark Places,” an instal-
lation for a video art show at the
The title of Erdman’s lecture Santa Monica Museum of Art, was
alludes to a definition of “mystery” designed with the ambition “that
derived from pop-Economist Mal- the artwork could cross contami-
colm Gladwell, who distinguishes nate itself.” A translucent video

126
projector armed with eight separate
screens showcased the works of sev-
eral different artists in ever-variable
rotation. As Erdman explained, “as
much as we were working with dif-
ferent elements [in designing the
projector] what became important
was the commingling of strands,”
meaning, the plasticity of the
architecture lent itself to a similar
plasticity in the presentation of the
digital work, inasmuch as the ever
changing juxtapositions of the films
redefined their immediate contex-
tualization and, consequently, their
meaning. Dark Places effectively
develops an architectural morphol-
ogy for a hypertextual system of
classification: the exhibit becomes
a liquid archive in which discrete
cultural artifacts are continuously
redefined by means of their ever-
changing contexts and arrange-
ments. The project emulates the

127
distinctive construction of frames spatial geometries.
of knowledge in the digital era,
immersing the viewer in a fresh and Perhaps the most enticing qual-
complex perceptual field in which ity in Erdman’s work, on the whole,
she must continually redefine her is its perceptual difficulty—which
interpretation of the visual material is to say, its capacity to engage the
at hand in terms of its ever fluctuat- inhabitant/viewer on a level of cog-
ing surroundings. nitive participation more complex
and provocative than the simplistic
In partnership with Lee, Erd- image recognition, or market-
man has recently won a competi- oriented branding strategies, that
tion for a housing complex in the dominate contemporary visual
Greater Beijing Arts District, in culture. Erdman’s work maintains
which discrete housing units are de- space and form as its own distinctive
rived from formal distortions of the mode of knowledge to be unraveled
geometric “box,” allowing for a play by a perceiving subject, but does so
of luminosity and a liquid interior without recourse to Phenomenol-
space. The spatially “mysterious” ogy.
domicile created seems almost a
contemporary iteration of the un-
heimlich, calling to mind Anthony
Vidler’s uncanny house, but forgo-
ing the ‘mystery’ of a supernatural
‘Other,’ in lieu of the mysteries of

128

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen