Sie sind auf Seite 1von 11

Representation (arts)

Representation is the use of signs that stand in for and take the place of something else.[1] It is through
representation that people organize the world and reality through the act of naming its elements.[1] Signs are
arranged in order to form semantic constructions and express relations.[1]

For many philosophers, both ancient and modern, man is regarded as


the "representational animal" or animal symbolicum, the creature
whose distinct character is the creation and the manipulation of signs
– things that "stand for" or "take the place of" something else.[1]

Representation has been associated with aesthetics (art) and


semiotics (signs). Mitchell says "representation is an extremely
elastic notion, which extends all the way from a stone representing a
man to a novel representing the day in the life of several
Dubliners".[1]

The term 'representation' carries a range of meanings and


interpretations. In literary theory, 'representation' is commonly
defined in three ways.

1. To look like or resemble


2. To stand in for something or someone Bust of Aristotle, Greek philosopher
3. To present a second time; to re-present[2]

Representation began with early literary theory in the ideas of Plato and Aristotle, and has evolved into a
significant component of language, Saussurian and communication studies.[2]

Contents
Defining representation
History
Contemporary ideas about representation
Peirce and representation
Semiotics and logic
Using signs and objects
Saussure and representation
Notes
See also
References
External links

Defining representation
To represent is "to bring to mind by description," also "to symbolize,
to be the embodiment of;" from representer (12c.), from L.
repraesentare, from re-, intensive prefix, + praesentare "to present,"
lit. "to place before".

A representation is a type of recording in which the sensory


information about a physical object is described in a medium. The
degree to which an artistic representation resembles the object it
represents is a function of resolution and does not bear on the
denotation of the word. For example, both the Mona Lisa and a
child's crayon drawing of Lisa del Giocondo would be considered
representational, and any preference for one over the other would
need to be understood as a matter of aesthetics.

History
Since ancient times representation has played a central role in
understanding literature, aesthetics and semiotics. Plato and Aristotle
Reproduction of the Mona Lisa
are key figures in early literary theory who considered literature as
simply one form of representation.[3] Aristotle for instance,
considered each mode of representation, verbal, visual or
musical, as being natural to human beings.[4] Therefore, what
distinguishes humans from other animals is their ability to
create and manipulate signs.[5] Aristotle deemed mimesis as
natural to man, therefore considered representations as
necessary for people's learning and being in the world.[4] Plato,
in contrast, looked upon representation with more caution. He
recognised that literature is a representation of life, yet also
believed that representations intervene between the viewer and
the real. This creates worlds of illusion leading one away from
the "real things".[6] Plato thus believed that representation needs
Greek theatrical masks depicted in
to be controlled and monitored due to the possible dangers of Hadrians Villa mosaic
fostering antisocial emotions or the imitation of evil.[5]

Aristotle went on to say it was a definitively human activity.[1]


From childhood man has an instinct for representation, and in this respect man differs from the other
animals that he is far more imitative and learns his first lessons though imitating things.[1] Aristotle
discusses representation in three ways—

1. The object: The symbol being represented.


2. Manner: The way the symbol is represented.
3. Means: The material that is used to represent it.

The means of literary representation is language. An important part of representation is the relationship
between what the material and what it represents. The questions arising from this are, "A stone may
represent a man but how? And by what and by what agreement, does this understanding of the
representation occur?"[1]

One apprehends reality only through representations of reality, through texts, discourses, images: there is no
such thing as direct or unmediated access to reality. But because one can see reality only through
representation it does not follow that one does not see reality at all... Reality is always more extensive and
complicated than any system of representation can comprehend, and we always sense that this is so-
representation never "gets" reality, which is why human history has produced so many and changing ways of
trying to get it.[7]

Consequently, throughout the history of human culture, people have become dissatisfied with language's
ability to express reality and as a result have developed new modes of representation. It is necessary to
construct new ways of seeing reality, as people only know reality through representation.[7] From this arises
the contrasting and alternate theories and representational modes of abstraction, realism and modernism, to
name a few.

Contemporary ideas about representation


It is from Plato's caution that in the modern era many are aware of political and ideological issues and the
influences of representations. It is impossible to divorce representations from culture and the society that
produces them. In the contemporary world there exist restrictions on subject matter, limiting the kinds of
representational signs allowed to be employed, as well as boundaries that limit the audience or viewers of
particular representations. In motion picture rating systems, M and R rated films are an example of such
restrictions, highlighting also society's attempt to restrict and modify representations to promote a certain set
of ideologies and values. Despite these restrictions, representations still have the ability to take on a life of
their own once in the public sphere, and can not be given a definitive or concrete meaning; as there will
always be a gap between intention and realization, original and copy.[5]

Consequently, for each of the above definitions there exists a process of communication and message
sending and receiving. In such a system of communication and representations it is inevitable that potential
problems may arise; misunderstandings, errors, and falsehoods. The accuracy of the representations can by
no means be guaranteed, as they operate in a system of signs that can never work in isolation from other
signs or cultural factors. For instance, the interpretation and reading of representations function in the
context of a body of rules for interpreting, and within a society many of these codes or conventions are
informally agreed upon and have been established over a number of years. Such understandings however,
are not set in stone and may alter between times, places, peoples and contexts. How though, does this
‘agreement’ or understanding of representation occur? It has generally been agreed by semioticians that
representational relationships can be categorised into three distinct headings: icon, symbol and index.[5]

For instance objects and people do not have a constant meaning, but their meanings are fashioned by
humans in the context of their culture, as they have the ability to make things mean or signify something.[6]
Viewing representation in such a way focuses on understanding how language and systems of knowledge
production work to create and circulate meanings. Representation is simply the process in which such
meanings are constructed.[6] In much the same way as the post-structuralists, this approach to representation
considers it as something larger than any one single representation. A similar perspective is viewing
representation as part of a larger field, as Mitchell, saying, "…representation (in memory, in verbal
descriptions, in images) not only 'mediates' our knowledge (of slavery and of many other things), but
obstructs, fragments, and negates that knowledge"[8] and proposes a move away from the perspective that
representations are merely "objects representing", towards a focus on the relationships and processes
through which representations are produced, valued, viewed and exchanged.

Peirce and representation


Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) was an innovative and accomplished logician, mathematician, and
scientist, and founded philosophical pragmatism. Peirce's central ideas were focused on logic and
representation.
Semiotics and logic

Peirce distinguished philosophical logic as logic per se from


mathematics of logic. He regarded logic (per se) as part of
philosophy, as a normative field following esthetics and ethics, as
more basic than metaphysics,[9] and as the art of devising methods
of research.[10] He argued that, more generally, as inference, "logic
is rooted in the social principle", since inference depends on a
standpoint that, in a sense, is unlimited.[11]

Peirce held that logic is formal semiotic,[12] the formal study of


signs in the broadest sense, not only signs that are artificial,
linguistic, or symbolic, but also signs that are semblances or are
indexical such as reactions. He held that "all this universe is
perfused with signs, if it is not composed exclusively of signs",[13]
along with their representational and inferential relations,
interpretable by mind or quasi-mind (whatever works like a mind Charles Sanders Peirce
despite perhaps not actually being one);[14] the focus here is on sign
action in general, not psychology, linguistics, or social studies).

He argued that, since all thought takes time, "all thought is in signs"[15] and sign processes ("semiosis") and
that the three irreducible elements of semiosis are (1) the sign (or representamen), (2) the (semiotic) object,
the sign's subject matter, which the sign represents and which can be anything thinkable—quality, brute fact,
or law—and even fictional (Prince Hamlet), and (3) the interpretant (or interpretant sign), which is the sign's
meaning or ramification as formed into a kind of idea or effect that is a further sign, for example, a
translation.[16] Even when a sign represents by a resemblance or factual connection independent of
interpretation, the sign is a sign because it is at least potentially interpretable. A sign depends on its object in
a way that enables (and, in a sense, determines) interpretation, forming an interpretant which, in turn,
depends on the sign and on the object as the sign depends on the object and is thus a further sign, enabling
and determining still further interpretation, further interpretants. That essentially triadic process is logically
structured to perpetuate itself and is what defines sign, object, and interpretant.

An object either (1) is immediate to a sign, and that is the object as represented in the sign, or (2) is a
dynamic object, which is the object as it really is, on which the immediate object is founded. Usually, an
object in question, such as Hamlet or the planet Neptune, is a special or partial object. A sign's total object is
the object's universe of discourse, the totality of things in that world to which one attributes the object. An
interpretant is either (1) immediate to a sign, for example a word's usual meaning, a kind of interpretive
quality or possibility present in the sign, or (2) dyanamic, an actual interpretant, for example a state of
agitation, or (3) final or normal, a question's true settlement, which would be reached if thought or inquiry
were pushed far enough, a kind of norm or ideal end with which any actual interpretant may, at most,
coincide.

Peirce said that, in order to know to what a sign refers, the mind needs some sort of experience of the sign's
object, experience outside, and collateral to, the given sign or sign system. In that context he spoke of
collateral experience, collateral observation, collateral acquaintance, all in much the same terms.[17] For
example, art work can exploit both the richness and the limits of the audience's experience; a novelist, in
disguising a roman à clef, counts on the typical reader's lack of personal experience with the actual
individual people portrayed. Then the reader refers the signs and interpretants in a general way to an object
or objects of the kind that is represented (intentionally or otherwise) by the novel. In all cases, the object (be
it a quality or fact or law or even fictional) determines the sign to an interpretant through one's collateral
experience with the object, collateral experience in which the object is newly found or from which it is
recalled, even if it is experience with an object of imagination as called into being by the sign, as can happen
not only in fiction but in theories and mathematics, all of which can involve mental experimentation with the
object under specifiable rules and constraints. Through collateral experience even a sign that consists in a
chance semblance of an absent object is determined by that object.

Peirce held that logic has three main parts:

1. Speculative grammar,[18] on meaningfulness, conditions for meaning. Study of significatory


elements and combinations.
2. Logical critic,[19] on validity, conditions for true representation. Critique of arguments in their
various distinct modes.
3. Speculative rhetoric, or methodeutic,[20] on conditions for determining interpretations.
Methodology of inquiry in its mutually interacting modes.

1. Speculative Grammar. By this, Peirce means discovering relations among questions of how signs can be
meaningful and of what kinds of signs there are, how they combine, and how some embody or incorporate
others. Within this broad area, Peirce developed three interlocked universal trichotomies of signs, depending
respectively on (1) the sign itself, (2) how the sign stands for its object, and (3) how the sign stands for its
object to its interpretant. Each trichotomy is divided according to the phenomenological category involved:
Firstness (quality of feeling, essentially monadic), secondness (reaction or resistance, essentially dyadic), or
thirdness (representation or mediation, essentially triadic).[21]

1. Qualisigns, sinsigns, and legisigns. Every sign is either (qualisign) a quality or possibility, or
(sinsign) an actual individual thing, fact, event, state, etc., or (legisign) a norm, habit, rule, law.
2. Icons, indices, and symbols. Every sign refers either (icon) through similarity to its object, or
(index) through factual connection to its object, or (symbol) through interpretive habit or norm
of reference to its object.
3. Rhemes, dicisigns, and arguments. Every sign is interpreted either as (rheme) term-like,
standing for its object in respect of quality, or as (dicisign) proposition-like, standing for its
object in respect of fact, or as (argument) argumentative, standing for its object in respect of
habit or law. This is the trichotomy of all signs as building blocks of inference.
Lines of joint classification of signs.
Some (not all) sign classes from different trichotomies intersect Every sign is:[22]
each other. For example, a qualisign is always an icon, and is 1. 2. 3.
never an index or a symbol. He held that there were only ten
I. Qualisign or Sinsign or Legisign
classes of signs logically definable through those three
universal trichotomies.[23] He thought that there were further and
such universal trichotomies as well. Also, some signs need II. Icon or Index or Symbol
other signs in order to be embodied. For example, a legisign and
(also called a type), such as the word "the," needs to be III. Rheme or Dicisign or Argument
embodied in a sinsign (also called a token), for example an
individual instance of the word "the", in order to be expressed. Another form of combination is attachment
or incorporation: an index may be attached to, or incorporated by, an icon or a symbol.

Peirce called an icon apart from a label, legend, or other index attached to it, a "hypoicon", and divided the
hypoicon into three classes: (a) the image, which depends on a simple quality; (b) the diagram, whose
internal relations, mainly dyadic or so taken, represent by analogy the relations in something; and (c) the
metaphor, which represents the representative character of a sign by representing a parallelism in something
else.[24] A diagram can be geometric, or can consist in an array of algebraic expressions, or even in the
common form "All __ is ___" which is subjectable, like any diagram, to logical or mathematical
transformations.
2. Logical critic or Logic Proper. That is how Peirce refers to logic in the everyday sense. Its main
objective, for Peirce, is to classify arguments and determine the validity and force of each kind.[19] He sees
three main modes: abductive inference (guessing, inference to a hypothetical explanation); deduction; and
induction. A work of art may embody an inference process and be an argument without being an explicit
argumentation. That is the difference, for example, between most of War and Peace and its final section.

3. Speculative rhetoric or methodeutic. For Peirce this is the theory of effective use of signs in
investigations, expositions, and applications of truth. Here Peirce coincides with Morris's notion of
pragmatics, in his interpretation of this term. He also called it "methodeutic", in that it is the analysis of the
methods used in inquiry.[20]

Using signs and objects

Peirce concluded that there are three ways in which signs represent objects. They underlie his most widely
known trichotomy of signs:

Icon
Index
Symbol[25]

Icon

This term refers to signs that represent by resemblance, such as portraits and some paintings though they can
also be natural or mathematical. Iconicity is independent of actual connection, even if it occurs because of
actual connection. An icon is or embodies a possibility, insofar as its object need not actually exist. A
photograph is regarded as an icon because of its resemblance to its object, but is regarded as an index (with
icon attached) because of its actual connection to its object. Likewise, with a portrait painted from life. An
icon's resemblance is objective and independent of interpretation, but is relative to some mode of
apprehension such as sight. An icon need not be sensory; anything can serve as an icon, for example a
streamlined argument (itself a complex symbol) is often used as an icon for an argument (another symbol)
bristling with particulars.

Index

Peirce explains that an index is a sign that compels attention through a connection of fact, often through
cause and effect. For example, if we see smoke we conclude that it is the effect of a cause – fire. It is an
index if the connection is factual regardless of resemblance or interpretation. Peirce usually considered
personal names and demonstratives such as the word "this" to be indices, for although as words they depend
on interpretation, they are indices in depending on the requisite factual relation to their individual objects. A
personal name has an actual historical connection, often recorded on a birth certificate, to its named object;
the word "this" is like the pointing of a finger.

Symbol

Peirce treats symbols as habits or norms of reference and meaning. Symbols can be natural, cultural, or
abstract and logical. They depend as signs on how they will be interpreted, and lack or have lost dependence
on resemblance and actual, indexical connection to their represented objects, though the symbol's individual
embodiment is an index to your experience of its represented object. Symbols are instantiated by specialized
indexical sinsigns. A proposition, considered apart from its expression in a particular language, is already a
symbol, but many symbols draw from what is socially accepted and culturally agreed upon. Conventional
symbols such as "horse" and caballo, which prescribe qualities of sound or appearance for their instances
(for example, individual instances of the word "horse" on the page) are based on what amounts to arbitrary
stipulation.[5] Such a symbol uses what is already known and accepted within our society to give meaning.
This can be both in spoken and written language.

For example, we can call a large metal object with four wheels, four doors, an engine and seats a "car"
because such a term is agreed upon within our culture and it allows us to communicate. In much the same
way, as a society with a common set of understandings regarding language and signs, we can also write the
word "car" and in the context of Australia and other English speaking nations, know what it symbolises and
is trying to represent.[26]

Saussure and representation


Swiss linguist Ferdinand de Saussure (1857–1913) played a major
role in the development of semiotics with his argument that language
is a system of signs that needs to be understood in order to fully
understand the process of linguistics.[27] The study of semiotics
examines the signs and types of representation that humans use to
express feelings, ideas, thoughts and ideologies.[28] Although
semiotics is often used in the form of textual analysis it also involves
the study of representation and the processes involved with
representation.

The process of representation is characterised by using signs that we


recall mentally or phonetically to comprehend the world.[29]
Saussure says before a human can use the word "tree" she or he has
to envision the mental concept of a tree.

Two things are fundamental to the study of signs:[30]

1. The signified: a mental concept, and


2. The signifier: the verbal manifestation, the sequence of Ferdinand de Saussure
letters or sounds, the linguistic realisation.

The signifier is the word or sound; the signified is the representation.

Saussure points out that signs:

Are arbitrary: There is no link between the signifier and the signified
Are relational: We understand we take on meaning in relation to other words. Such as we
understand "up" in relation to "down" or a dog in relation to other animals, such as a cat.
constitute our world – "You cannot get outside of language. We exist inside a system of
signs".[30]

Saussure suggests that the meaning of a sign is arbitrary, in effect; there is no link between the signifier and
the signified.[31] The signifier is the word or the sound of the word and the signified is the representation of
the word or sound. For example, when referring to the term "sister" (signifier) a person from an English
speaking country such as Australia, may associate that term as representing someone in their family who is
female and born to the same parents (signified). An Aboriginal Australian may associate the term "sister" to
represent a close friend that they have a bond with. This means that the representation of a signifier depends
completely upon a person's cultural, linguistic and social background. Saussure argues that if words or
sounds were simply labels for existing things in the world, translation from one language or culture to
another would be easy, it is the fact that this can be extremely difficult that suggests that words trigger a
representation of an object or thought depending on the person that is representing the signifier.[32] The
signified triggered from the representation of a signifier in one particular language do not necessarily
represent the same signified in another language. Even within one particular language many words refer to
the same thing but represent different people's interpretations of it. A person may refer to a particular place
as their "work" whereas someone else represents the same signifier as their "favorite restaurant". This can
also be subject to historical changes in both the signifier and the way objects are signified.

Saussure claims that an imperative function of all written languages and alphabetic systems is to "represent"
spoken language.[33] Most languages do not have writing systems that represent the phonemic sounds they
make. For example, in English the written letter "a" represents different phonetic sounds depending on
which word it is written in. The letter "a" has a different sound in the word in each of the following words,
"apple", "gate", "margarine" and "beat", therefore, how is a person unaware of the phonemic sounds, able to
pronounce the word properly by simply looking at alphabetic spelling. The way the word is represented on
paper is not always the way the word would be represented phonetically. This leads to common
misrepresentations of the phonemic sounds of speech and suggests that the writing system does not properly
represent the true nature of the pronunciation of words.

Notes
1. Mitchell, W. 1995, "Representation", in F Lentricchia & T McLaughlin (eds), Critical Terms for
Literary Study, 2nd edn, University of Chicago Press, Chicago
2. O'Shaughnessy, M & Stadler J, Media and society: an introduction, 3rd edn, Oxford University
Press, South Melbourne, 2005
3. Childers J (ed.), Columbia Dictionary of Modern Literary and Cultural Criticism, Columbia
University Press, New York, 1995
4. <Vukcevich, M 2002, "Representation", The University of Chicago, viewed 7 April 2006
5. Mitchell, W, "Representation", in F Lentricchia & T McLaughlin (eds), Critical Terms for Literary
Study, University of Chicago Press, Chicago 1990
6. Hall, S (ed.), Cultural Representations and Signifying Practice, Open University Press,
London, 1997. ISBN 978-0761954323
7. Dryer 1993, cited in O’Shaughnessy & Stadler 2005
8. Mitchell, W, Picture Theory, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1994
9. On his classifications, see Peirce, C.S. (1903), CP 1.180–202 Eprint (http://www.princeton.ed
u/~batke/peirce/cl_o_sci_03.htm) Archived (https://web.archive.org/web/20111105121054/htt
p://www.princeton.edu/~batke/peirce/cl_o_sci_03.htm) 2011-11-05 at the Wayback Machine
and (1906) "The Basis of Pragmaticism" in The Essential Peirce 2:372–3. For the relevant
quotes, see "Philosophy" and "Logic" at Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms (http://www.hel
sinki.fi/science/commens/dictionary.html), Bergman and Paavola, editors, U. of Helsinki.
10. Peirce, C.S., 1882, "Introductory Lecture on the Study of Logic" delivered September 1882,
Johns Hopkins University Circulars, vol. 2, no. 19, pp. 11–12, November 1892, Google Book
Search Eprint (https://books.google.com/books?id=E0YFAAAAQAAJ&pg=PA11&dq=%22art+o
f+devising+methods+of+research%22). Reprinted in Collected Papers of Charles Sanders
Peirce v. 7, paragraphs 59–76, The Essential Peirce 1:214–214; Writings of Charles S. Peirce
4:378–382.
11. Peirce, C.S. (1878) "The Doctrine of Chances", Popular Science Monthly, v. 12, pp. 604–615,
1878, reprinted in Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, v. 2, paragraphs 645–668,
Writings of Charles S. Peirce 3:276–290, and The Essential Peirce 1:142–154. "...death makes
the number of our risks, the number of our inferences, finite, and so makes their mean result
uncertain. The very idea of probability and of reasoning rests on the assumption that this
number is indefinitely great. .... ...logicality inexorably requires that our interests shall not be
limited. .... Logic is rooted in the social principle."
12. Peirce, C. S. (written 1902), "MS L75: Logic, Regarded As Semeiotic (The Carnegie
application of 1902): Version 1: An Integrated Reconstruction", Joseph Ransdell, ed., Arisbe,
see Memoir 12 (http://www.cspeirce.com/menu/library/bycsp/l75/ver1/l75v1-05.htm#m12).
13. Peirce, C.S., The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, v. 5, paragraph 448 footnote,
from "The Basis of Pragmaticism" in 1906.
14. See "Quasi-Mind (http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/terms/quasimind.html)" at the
Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms, Mats Bergman and Sami Paavola, eds., University of
Helsinki.
15. Peirce, C.S. (1868), "Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man" (Arisbe Eprint
(http://www.cspeirce.com/menu/library/bycsp/question/qu-frame.htm)), Journal of Speculative
Philosophy vol. 2, pp. 103–114. Reprinted (Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, v. 5,
paragraphs 213–263, the quote is from paragraph 253).
16. For Peirce's definitions of semiosis, sign, representamen, object, interpretant, see the
Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms (http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/dictionary.htm
l).
17. Ten quotes on collateral observation from Peirce provided by Professor Joseph Ransdell can
be viewed here (http://lyris.ttu.edu/read/messages?id=57101#57101). Also see pp. 404–409 in
"Pragmatism" by Peirce in The Essential Peirce v. 2.
18. See "Grammar: Speculative
(http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/terms/grammarspec.html)" in Commens Dictionary of
Peirce's Terms.
19. See "Critic (http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/terms/critic.html)" in Commens Dictionary
of Peirce's Terms.
20. See "Methodeutic (http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/terms/methodeutic.html)" in
Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
21. "Categories, Cenopythagorean Categories (http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/terms/cate
gories.html)", Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms, Mats Bergman and Sami Paavola,
editors, University of Helsinki.
22. Peirce (1903 MS), "Nomenclature and Divisions of Triadic Relations, as Far as They Are
Determined", under other titles in Collected Papers (CP) v. 2, paragraphs 233–72, and
reprinted under the original title in Essential Peirce (EP) v. 2, pp. 289–99. Also see image of
MS 339 (http://www.mail-archive.com/peirce-l@lyris.ttu.edu/msg00850.html) (August 7, 1904)
supplied to peirce-l by Bernard Morand (http://www.iutc3.unicaen.fr/~moranb/) of the Institut
Universitaire de Technologie (France), Département Informatique.
23. See Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, v. 2, paragraphs 254–263, reprinted in
Philosophical Writings of Peirce pp. 115 (https://books.google.com/books?id=ClSjXRIbxAMC&
pg=PA115)–118, and in The Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 294–296.
24. On image, diagram, and metaphor, see "Hypoicon (http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/ter
ms/hypoicon.html)" in the Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms (http://www.helsinki.fi/scienc
e/commens/dictionary.html).
25. For Peirce's definitions of icon, index, symbol, and related terms, see the Commens Dictionary
of Peirce's Terms (http://www.helsinki.fi/science/commens/dictionary.html)
26. Dupriez, B, A Dictionary of Literary Devices, University of Toronto Press, Canada, 1991.
27. Culler, J 1976, Saussure, Fontana Modern Masters, Britain, 1976.
28. Ryder, M, Semiotics: Language and Culture, 2004 viewed 6 April 2006 see link below
29. Klarer, M, An Introduction to Literary Studies, Routledge, London, 1998.
30. Barry, P, Beginning Theory: an Introduction to Literary and Cultural Theory, Manchester
University Press, Great Britain, 2002.
31. Holdcroft 1991 no details
32. Chandler, D, Semiotics for Beginners: Modality and representation, viewed 8 April 2006
33. Arnason, D, Reference material, 2006, viewed 12 April 2006

See also
Aspectism Media influence Symbol
Cultural artifact Mimesis Western painting
Culture theory Painting Work of art
Figurative art Program music Conceptual art
Foundation for the Advancement of Art Realism (arts)
Representative realism

Aesthetics of Representation

References
Arnason, D, Semiotics: the system of signs (https://web.archive.org/web/20071212232406/htt
p://130.179.92.25/Arnason_DE/Saussure.html) (via the Wayback Machine)
Baldick, C, "New historicism", in The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Literary Terms, 1996,
viewed 8 April 2006 [1] (http://www.oxfordreference.com/views/ENTRY.html?subview=Main&en
try=t56.e652)
Barry, P, Beginning Theory: an Introduction to Literary and Cultural Theory, Manchester
University Press, Great Britain, 2002.
Burch, R 2005, "Charles Sanders Peirce", in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, viewed
24 April 2006 [2] (http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2005/entries/peirce/).
Chandler, D, Semiotics for Beginners: Modality and Representation, 2001, viewed 8 April 2006
[3] (http://www.aber.ac.uk/media/Documents/S4B/sem02a.html).
Childers J. (ed.), Columbia Dictionary of Modern Literary and Cultural Criticism, Columbia
University Press, New York, 1995.
Concise Routledge, Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, Routledge, London, 1999.
Culler, J., Saussure, Fontana Modern Masters, Britain, 1976.
Dupriez, B, A Dictionary of Literary Devices, University of Toronto Press, Canada 1991.
Fuery, P & Mansfield N, Cultural Studies and Critical Theory, Oxford University Press,
Australia, 2005. (ISBN 978-0-19-551294-6)
Hall, S (ed.), Cultural Representations and Signifying Practice, Open University Press,
London, 1997.
Holder, D, Saussure – Signs, System, and Arbitrariness, Cambridge, Australia, 1991.
Lentricchia, F. & McLaughlin,T (eds.), Critical Terms for Literary Study, University of Chicago
Press, London, 1990.
Klarer, M, An Introduction to Literary Studies, Routledge, London, 1998.
Mitchell, W, "Representation", in F Lentricchia & T McLaughlin (eds), Critical Terms for Literary
Study, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1990.
Mitchell, W, "Representation", in F Lentricchia & T McLaughlin (eds), Critical Terms for Literary
Study, 2nd edn, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1995.
Mitchell, W, Picture Theory, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1994.
Moon, B, Literary terms: a Practical Glossary, 2nd edn, Chalkface Press, Cottesloe, 2001.
Murfin, R & Ray, S.M, The Bedford Glossary of Critical and Literary Terms, Bedford Books,
Boston, 1997.
O'Shaughnessy, M & Stadler J, Media and Society: an Introduction, 3rd edn, Oxford University
Press, South Melbourne, 2005. (ISBN 978-0-19-551402-5)
Prendergast, C, "Circulating Representations: New Historicism and the Poetics of Culture",
Substance: The Review of Theory and Literary Criticism, no. 28, issue 1, pp. 90–105, 1999,
(online Humanities International Complete)
Ryder, M, Semiotics: Language and Culture, 2004, viewed 6 April 2006 [4] (http://carbon.cude
nver.edu/~mryder/semiotics_este.html).
Shook, J, The Pragmatism Cybrary: Charles Morris, in The Pragmatism Cybrary, 2005, viewed
24 April 2006 [5] (http://www.pragmatism.org/genealogy/morris.htm).
Vukcevich, M, Representation, The University of Chicago, 2002, viewed 7 April 2006.

External links
University of Chicago (http://humanities.uchicago.edu/faculty/mitchell/glossary2004/representa
tion.htm)

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Representation_(arts)&oldid=928584618"

This page was last edited on 30 November 2019, at 08:10 (UTC).

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. By using this
site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia
Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen