Feminist Theory
2014, Vol. 15(1) 89–100
Judith Butler’s post-Hegelian ! The Author(s) 2014
Reprints and permissions:
ethics and the problem with sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav
DOI: 10.1177/1464700113512738
recognition fty.sagepub.com
Hannah Stark
University of Tasmania, Australia
Abstract
Judith Butler’s recent work is exemplary of the trend in contemporary theory to con-
sider ethics. Her deliberation over ethical questions, and the place of ethics in intellec-
tual work, has undeniably intensified since September 11. This article will demonstrate,
however, that this is a rendering explicit of what has always been implicit in her work.
Rather than perceiving the ethical dimension of Butler’s writings in her increasing inter-
est in thinkers such as Emmanuel Levinas and Hannah Arendt, I contend that it is in her
sustained interest in Hegel, and specifically in Hegelian recognition, that her work can
be read as engaged with ethical concerns. This article highlights the growing critical
concern with the prevalence of recognition in ethical theory and questions the possi-
bility of theorising ethics outside of the recognition-paradigm.
Keywords
Difference, ethical turn, ethics, Judith Butler, recognition, subjectivity
In the year 2000 Judith Butler acknowledged her ambivalence about the return to
ethics, fearing that it would engender a turn away from politics and an intensifi-
cation of moralism (2000a: 15).1 Despite this ambivalence, or, perhaps, because of
it, the corpus of her work is pervaded by an ethically vexed tone. Her deliberation
over ethical questions, and the place of ethics in intellectual work, has undeniably
intensified since September 11. This article will demonstrate, however, that this is a
rendering explicit of what has always been implicit in her work. Rather than
perceiving the ethical dimension of Butler’s writings in her increasing interest in
thinkers such as Emmanuel Levinas and Hannah Arendt, I contend that it is in her
sustained interest in Hegel, and specifically in Hegelian recognition, that her work
can be read as engaged with ethical concerns. In this article I investigate the
Corresponding author:
Hannah Stark, School of Humanities, University of Tasmania, Private Bag 41, Hobart, Tasmania 7001, Australia.
Email: hannah.stark@utas.edu.au
rather realises – at the very moment its identity would cohere – that it cannot return
to its prior state. The foundational moment of identity thus entails self-loss, and
reveals a ‘subject that cannot remain bounded in the face of the world’ (1999b: xv).
Moya Lloyd describes Butler’s dialectic as ‘non-synthetic’, because it refuses dia-
lectic synthesis. This dialectic can therefore be seen as a constant conflict without
the possibility of resolution into identity through the overcoming of difference.
Lloyd continues that this is what enables Butler to prioritise difference over identity
(2007: 19).7
Butler’s early interest in the relationship between recognition and community is
evident in Subjects of Desire although this book can be described as more philo-
sophical than political or ethical. Because existence is confirmed by the ‘acknowl-
edging look of the Other’, she writes, ‘[t]rue subjectivities come to flourish only in
communities that provide for reciprocal recognition’ (Butler, 1999b: 58). In prioritis-
ing the foundational nature of intersubjectivity for the constitution of the subject,
Butler highlights our essential dependence on others. In Frames of War, she explains
that this is because the Hegelian process of relation ensures that ‘the subject that I am
is bound to the subject I am not’ (Butler, 2009: 43). This foundational binding not
only underpins her theory of how subjectivity relates to alterity but also foreshadows
her later political focus on intersubjectivity as a locus of ethical engagement. In
driving the subject into relation with others, it is its unfinished nature that can be
seen to mark the conditions under which it is in community.
Butler gives our binding to others ontological priority. Contextualised with
Jean-Luc Nancy’s claim in relation to Hegelian subjectivity that ‘I am unbound
of myself’ (2002: 37), this focus suggests that ecstatic undoing occurs precisely in
the binding of ourselves to others. Constituted by our ties to each other, ontologic-
ally ‘the forming and un-forming of such bonds is prior to any question of the
subject and is, in fact, the social and affective condition of subjectivity’ (Butler,
2009: 182–183). This is why Butler speaks only of the ‘social ontology of the sub-
ject’ (2009: 147, emphasis mine). It is not only to suggest that particular connec-
tions form and un-form us, but rather that the mere possibility of our connection to
others (which does not presume an actual encounter) is central to our sense of self
and our existence as a subject. This relational structure is beyond individual choice:
there is no possibility of existing without the impingement of others on our lives.
As a result, although a particular ‘you’ may be lost, the possibility of an ‘indexical
you’ remains and it is this you ‘without whom I cannot be’ (Butler, 2009: 44). It is
not surprising, then, that Butler’s recent work has turned to ethical concerns.
The ecstatic nature of the subject is examined in ‘Beside Oneself’, in which Butler
utilises grief to illustrate how undeniable intersubjectivity is. In its connection to
others, Butler’s subject always vacillates between ‘loss and ecstasy’ (2005: 28).
Implicit in the examination of grief is the differential treatment of a grievable
life. Returning to the notion of ecstasy, Butler theorises the relational structures
which both constitute and undo identity.8 As an ecstatic state, loss is transforma-
tive. The grief that follows the rupture caused by loss demonstrates both the
undoing of the subject and that fundamental reliance on others that continues
from infancy. The experience of grief lays bare the ways in which we are enmeshed
in relational structures that are centrally important to our sense of self. Grief also
implies the prior ecstatic relations that structure desire and love. ‘Let’s face it’,
Butler insists, ‘We’re undone by each other. And if we’re not, we’re missing some-
thing. And if this seems so clearly the case with grief, it is only because it was
already the case with desire’ (2004: 19). This is an explicitly political statement not
only because she is theorising loss in relation to AIDS deaths and American politics
post-9/11, but also because this reveals something about our ties to others, the
kinds of community that such ties constitute, and the ethical responsibility they
imply.
Butler insists that this intersubjective embodied sociality is ‘fundamental’
(2004: 22). The political motivation in her more recent work on recognition is evident
notably in Bodies that Matter (1993), in which she asks why some bodies are assumed
to be more important than others. This question is part of a broad Hegelian agenda
as its concern is: who is protected by recognition and who comes to occupy the
position of negativity by being designated unrecognisable? Examining the embodied
nature of recognition is her supplement to Hegelian subjectivity because, as she
concedes, there is little mention of embodiment in Hegel’s work except as the con-
tainer of consciousness (Butler, 1997b: 34). As the site where we are exposed to one
another, the body is important for experiences of pleasure and pain but also for
recognition, and the policing and challenging of norms. As the location of corporeal
normalisation and resistance, the body also registers failures in both. The pre-text of
Butler’s contention in ‘Beside Oneself’, that the body comes into being through
sociality, is her argument in Bodies that Matter (1993) that the body is never prior
to discourse or society. In being embodied, the subject is always ‘given over’ (Butler,
2005: 101) to the other in a way that it cannot choose or control.
Embodiment is evidence of a common corporeal vulnerability in Butler’s more
recent work, as can be seen in her repeated evocation of the precariousness of
life. Vulnerability is a political tool because it enables us to understand our
implication in the lives of others who are similarly embodied and exposed. To
envisage the world in this way appeals to our proximity to others and disrupts
the subject’s sovereignty. This view is commensurate with Jean-Luc Nancy’s
notion of the ‘trembling subject’: ‘I cannot stop trembling before the other,
and even further, at being in myself the trembling that the other stirs up’
(Nancy, 2002: 45). Nancy’s reading of the Hegelian subject evokes that precar-
iousness of our relations which frames Butler’s discussion of the ‘constitutive
sociality of the self’ (Butler, 2004: 19).
Focusing on community, Butler asks how the act of recognition in our inter-
subjective relations creates and polices the categorical distinction between the
human and the less-than-human. The Hegelian tradition, she concludes, ignores
the fact that the category of the human is an exclusionary mechanism for confer-
ring humanness on some while depriving others of its status (Butler, 2004: 2). Her
epistemological critique of Hegel is central to her ethics and an ongoing concern in
her work. This is evident in her discussion of how the politics of inclusion structure
mean for alterity? When social relations are processed through the matrix of rec-
ognition, what violence is done not only to the other but also to the subject? How
does this assume a specific subject capable of granting recognition to the other, and
an other who both requires and desires that recognition be granted? What ration-
ality does the structure of recognition assume? And, ultimately, what is the con-
ceptual cost of Hegelian recognition?
The stakes are high in this debate for imaginings of community. Recognition
has, of course, proved extremely useful for theorising intersubjectivity. The use-
value of recognition, according to Scott Lash and Mike Featherstone, is that it
provides a way to think about community so that recognition itself becomes the
source of the ‘social bond’ (2001: 14, emphasis in original). In this context recog-
nition can be seen to imply that there is commonality through difference. This can
be seen to have gained significance in relation to the identity politics of the 1980s
and 1990s. These political movements are, however, complicit with regimes of
visibility, so that recognition becomes coded as that which is visible and articulable
and what is beyond recognition is coded as invisible.13 In Butler’s work she argues
for the political importance of the visibility of minority groups and practices. For
example, in the 1999 preface to Gender Trouble she writes that although we need
not tolerate all minority sexual practices, we do need ‘to be able to think them
before we come to any kinds of conclusions about them’ (1999a: viii). Although I
acknowledge the importance of Butler’s concern with the erasure of minorities, I
am uneasy that in placing so much value on recognition and the rendering visible of
what the dominant order refuses to acknowledge, what is at risk of erasure is
actually difference, contradiction, and incoherence.
The Hegelian system of recognition has already been criticised by a range of
important contemporary thinkers. Elizabeth Grosz, for example, is extremely crit-
ical of recognition and of Butler’s reliance on this concept. ‘In spite of its place in
the rhetoric of radical politics since Hegel’, she writes, ‘recognition is the force of
conservatism, the tying of the new and the never-conceived to that which is already
cognized’ (Grosz, 2001: 103). Her claim here alludes to the most significant prob-
lem with recognition: that it requires that things which are fundamentally strange,
which we do not and cannot have knowledge of, be subjected to already existing
systems of meaning and value. The epistemological structure of thought categorises
and hierarchises being so that it is reduced to systems that pre-date the particular
encounter. Alain Badiou, like Elizabeth Grosz, is deeply critical of recognition:
‘[t]he truth is that, in the context of a system of thought that is both a-religious and
genuinely contemporary with the truths of our time, the whole ethical predication
based upon recognition of the other should be purely and simply abandoned’
(Badiou, 2001: 25). The reason why this is important is that what is beyond our
recognition requires ethical valence.
The critique of recognition has important implications for theorising subjectiv-
ity, because, as Oliver comments, ‘theories of identity and subjectivity based on
recognition are implicit if not explicit in almost all types of contemporary theory’
(2001: 4). It is therefore central to thinking through both the apparent prevalence
of Hegelian models of subjectivity and also the ethics which these models permit. The
recourse to the subject and the human in contemporary ethical work, and specifically
in Butler’s project, requires interrogation. The turn to ethics, and with it the rise of
interest in alterity and such humanistic terms as ‘friendship, hospitality, responsi-
bility, care, and love’ (2004: 685), is problematic, Rey Chow asserts, because what is
emphasised in ‘so many forms of mea culpa, self-analysis, self-reflexivity, and self-
admonition’, is ‘the self, the subject, the centre, and the origin that is the West’ (2004:
685). Examining the kinds of subjectivity that are supported in different ways of
theorising ethics is important because this is related to the ways in which intersub-
jectivity, otherness, and difference are imagined. Attridge alludes to the impact that
recognition has on the figure of the Other. He states that ‘insofar as I apprehend the
already existing other, it is not other: I recognize the familiar contours of a human
being, which is to say I accommodate him or her to my existing schemata’ (Attridge,
1999: 24). Oliver asks if we can even imagine intersubjectivity outside of the ‘warring
struggle’ of the Hegelian recognition-paradigm (2001: 6). Answering this question is
central to thinking through both the dominance of Hegelian models of subjectivity
and also the ethics which these models permit.
This also has important implications for feminism. In Becoming Undone,
Elizabeth Grosz insists that even though the struggle for recognition has historic-
ally been a central prerogative for feminists, moving beyond recognition and the
predominance of the subject must become a driving force for feminist theory (2011:
84). ‘At its best,’ she writes, ‘feminist theory has the potential to make us become
other than ourselves, to make us unrecognizable’ (Grosz, 2011: 87). This focus on
what is beyond recognition sits Grosz’s work in stark contrast with Butler’s. It also
invites questions about the kinds of ethics and politics, and specifically the forms of
feminism, which might be possible beyond the Hegelian model. It is worth con-
sidering what feminism beyond recognition might look like and whether we would
even know it when we saw it. This might require us to find new resources for
feminist theory in the work of philosophers who offer a critique of Hegel and of
Hegelian recognition (Gilles Deleuze comes to mind).
Butler’s work is exemplary of a larger trend in critical theory, both in her ethical
concerns and also in the Hegelian foundation of these concerns. I believe that we
must go beyond Hegelian recognition in order to encounter what is unknown in the
world and that this is the basis of ethics. The criticism of recognition has already
started in academic debate and it is gaining momentum. This critique of recogni-
tion is imperative because it is the first step in rethinking difference, identity and
political community. Moving beyond recognition enables new conceptualisations
of ethics, which may facilitate an opening to the unknown.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Jessica Murrell – my first and best reader – for her generous reading
(and re-reading) of this piece. I would like to acknowledge Ken Ruthven, Mandy Treagus
and the anonymous reviewers at Feminist Theory for their helpful and insightful comments
and suggestions.
Notes
1. The ethical ‘turn’, which has become apparent in contemporary critical theory, phil-
osophy, and literary theory, is conventionally dated from the controversy surrounding
Paul de Man’s apparent support of National Socialism in 1987 and Jacques Derrida’s
insistence that justice be exempt from deconstruction (1992: 15). The increasing
importance of ethics in Humanities scholarship, and particularly in literary criticism,
is evident, for example, in the inclusion of Geoffrey Galt Harpham’s entry on this
matter in the 1995 updated edition of Lentricchia and McLaughlin’s Critical Terms for
Literary Study, the first edition of which was published in 1990.
2. The influence on Butler of Kojève, Hyppolite and Sartre is particularly significant
because their treatment of Hegel was the subject of her doctoral thesis, which she
later revised and extended for publication as Subjects of Desire.
3. On the thematic repetition in her work Butler has commented in an interview ‘I return to
the same problems again and again, in different ways and in different contexts’. See
Zajdermann (2006).
4. Lloyd argues that Butler is able to render Hegel’s subject as ‘ecstatic’ only because her
deliberately partial reading of Phenomenology of Spirit refuses the metaphysical closure
achieved by the unity of subject and substance (Lloyd, 2007: 15).
5. Butler aligns this desire for recognition with Spinoza’s conatus. To persist in one’s own
being, she argues, is to be recognised. An unrecognisable being lacks possibility, and
only possible beings are capable of persistence. To not meet the normative requirements
for recognition is therefore to be negated in a literal sense (Butler, 2004: 31).
6. Butler attributes the French interest in Hegel during the 1930s and 1940s to a desire to
find new life in the concept of negation after the First World War, and the eventual
outbreak of another. ‘The negative’, she writes, ‘is also human freedom, human desire,
the possibility to create anew; the nothingness to which human life had been consigned
was thus at once the possibility of its renewal . . . The negative showed itself in Hegelian
terms not merely as death, but as a sustained possibility of becoming’ (Butler, 1999b: 62,
emphasis in original).
7. Butler’s positioning in critical and political theory as central to the politics of difference,
as well as her foundational role in queer theory, can be seen to support a reading of the
vitality of her concepts of difference and identity.
8. The ‘ecstatic’ nature of subjectivity is evident in Butler’s rejection of the autonomous
subject which was central to her work in the 1990s, as for her the subject has never
possessed an interior agency but has always found itself in the external structures of
language, discourse and power which it then internalises. To describe this as a ‘return’ is
to highlight her re-adoption of her earlier terminology.
9. See ‘Contingent Foundations: Feminism and the Question of ‘‘Postmodernism’’’
(Butler, 1995) and ‘Restaging the Universal: Hegemony and the Limits of Formalism’
(Butler, 2000b) respectively.
10. Butler also contextualises this with her work on gender. She comments, ‘gender is
always a failure. Everyone fails. And it is a very good thing that we fail’. See
Zajdermann (2006).
11. This continues Butler’s earlier examination of the structures of address in Excitable
Speech (1997a), which draws on Althusser’s notion of interpellation and the speech
act theory of J. L. Austin. Giving an Account of Oneself is preoccupied with the structure
of address as an ethical site.
12. I thank one of the anonymous reviewers at Feminist Theory for raising this point. For a
further critique of subversive repetition in Butler’s work see Saba Mahmood’s Politics of
Piety (2005).
13. A contemporary example of the correlation of identity politics and visibility is activism
around marriage equality. Gay marriage is of course an important step for the legal and
political rights of same-sex attracted people. However, the way that this debate has been
staged in the media and in celebrity culture has been premised on the rendering visible of
gay and lesbian identity and same-sex relationships. For example, in my own context of
Australia, the comedian Magda Szubanski ‘came out’, thus rendering her identity as a
lesbian visible, as a way of supporting marriage equality. Marriage is itself a form of
rendering visible in which public recognition of a relationship and its official documen-
tation occurs. While this visibility is important it also contributes to the rendering invisible
of relationship practices that fall outside of the recognisable structure of marriage.
References
Attridge, Derek (1999) ‘Innovation, Literature, Ethics: Relating to the Other’. PMLA,
114(1): 20–31.
Badiou, Alain (2001) Ethics: An Essay on the Understanding of Evil. Trans. Peter Hallward.
London: Verso.
Butler, Judith (1993) Bodies that Matter: On the Discursive Limits of ‘Sex’. New York:
Routledge.
Butler, Judith (1995) ‘Contingent Foundations: Feminism and the Question of
‘‘Postmodernism’’’. In: Benhabib Seyla, Butler Judith, Cornell Druscilla and Fraser
Nancy (eds) Feminist Contentions: A Philosophical Exchange. New York: Routledge,
pp. 35–57.
Butler, Judith (1997a) Excitable Speech: A Politics of the Performative. New York:
Routledge.
Butler, Judith (1997b) The Psychic Life of Power: Theories in Subjection. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Butler, Judith (1999a) Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. New York:
Routledge.
Butler, Judith (1999b) Subjects of Desire: Hegelian Reflections in Twentieth-Century France.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Butler, Judith (2000a) ‘Ethical Ambivalence’. In: Garber Marjorie, Hanssen Beatrice and
Walkowitz Rebecca L. (eds) The Turn to Ethics. New York: Routledge, pp. 15–28.
Butler, Judith (2000b) ‘Restaging the Universal: Hegemony and the Limits of Formalism’.
In: Butler Judith, Laclau Ernesto and Žižek Slavoj (eds) Contingency, Hegemony,
Universality. New York: Verso, pp. 11–43.
Butler, Judith (2004) Undoing Gender. New York: Routledge.
Butler, Judith (2005) Giving an Account of Oneself. New York: Fordham University Press.
Butler, Judith (2009) Frames of War: When Is Life Grievable? London: Verso.
Chow, Rey (2004) ‘Toward an Ethics of Postvisuality: Some Thoughts on the Recent Work
of Zhang Yimou’. Poetics Today, 25(2): 673–688.
Derrida, Jacques (1992) ‘Force of Law: The ‘‘Mystical Foundation of Authority’’’. Trans.
Mary Quaintance. In: Cornell Drucilla, Rosenfeld Michel and Gary Carlson David (eds)
Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice. New York: Routledge, pp. 3–67.
Fraser, Nancy (2003) ‘Social Justice in the Age of Identity Politics: Redistribution,
Recognition, and Participation’. In: Fraser Nancy and Honneth Axel (eds)
Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-Philosophical Exchange. New York: Verso,
pp. 7–119.
Fraser, Nancy and Honneth Axel (2003) Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-
Philosophical Exchange. New York: Verso.
Grosz, Elizabeth (2001) Architecture from the Outside. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Grosz, Elizabeth (2011) Becoming Undone: Darwinian Reflections on Life, Politics and Art.
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Harpham, Geoffrey Galt (1995) ‘Ethics’. In: Lentricchia Frank and McLaughlin Thomas
(eds) Critical Terms for Literary Study. Chicago: Chicago University Press, pp. 387–405.
Hegel W, George (1977) Phenomenology of Spirit. Oxford: Clarendon.
Hyppolite, Jean (1974) Genesis and Structure of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. Evanston:
Northwestern University Press.
Kojève, Alexandre (1980) Introduction to the Reading of Hegel: Lectures on the
Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans. James H. Nichols. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Lash, Scott and Featherstone Mike (2001) ‘Recognition and Difference: Politics, Identity,
Multiculture’. Theory, Culture and Society, 18(1): 1–19.
Lloyd, Moya (2007) Judith Butler. Cambridge: Polity.
Magnus, Kathy Dow (2006) ‘The Unaccountable Subject: Judith Butler and the Social
Conditions of Intersubjective Agency’. Hypatia, 21(2): 81–103.
Mahmood, Saba (2005) Politics of Piety: The Islamic Revival and the Feminist Subject.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Nancy, Jean-Luc (2002) Hegel: The Restlessness of the Negative. Trans. Jason Smith and
Steven Miller. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Oliver, Kelly (2001) Witnessing: Beyond Recognition. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Zajdermann, Paule (2006) Judith Butler: Philosophe En Tout Genre [video]. Paris: Arte.