1
The Phenomenology of Psychoses
A. Tatossian (1979)
The history of phenomenological psychiatry
Introduction
The main thrust of phenomenological psychiatry is the teaching of a new
way of approaching experience. This will be developed in later parts of this
treatise. Here we are concerned with the history of the movement, which
itself brings out this theme quite adequately. It is not possible to go into the
entire complexity of the history, but we can trace two important strands,
both of which emanated from that historic day, the 25th November 1922,
which we can say marked the debut of phenomenological psychiatry. The
occasion was the 63rd meeting of the Swiss Society for Psychiatry, which
was held in Zurich, and where Minkowski presented his study of a case of
2
‘schizophrenic melancholy’ and of the disturbance of time which
underpinned it, and where Binswanger discussed his views on
phenomenology itself.
The two types of phenomenological psychiatry:
that of Minkowski, Straus and von Gebsattel;
and that of Binswanger and his evolution.
From that day onwards, there appeared two distinct strands to
phenomenological psychiatry, which are evident despite all sorts of
variations as time went on. One is illustrated by the early work of
Minkowski along with that of Straus and von Gebsattel, all of which make
only a peripheral appeal to any philosopher in respect to the theses put
forward, and do not rely in any systematic way on phenomenology in its
technical aspects. Binswanger, on the other hand, devotes a large part of his
earliest publications to a discussion of the notion of essences and to
Husserl’s views on intentionality, which he follows faithfully in his
psychiatric examples at this time. He remained committed to them even
during the 1930s, when Heidegger’s Being and time had become his
principal reference point, and when he was developing his own brand of
analysis which he referred to as Daseinsanalysis, and kept faith with them
3
even later when he returned to the fold of Husserl’s transcendental
philosophy and re-interpreted his own Daseinsanalysis in a purer Husserlian
light.
It should be stressed that Binswanger’s Heideggerian phase, and the return
to Husserl, had nothing arbitrary about them, but were dictated by his
continual attempts to accommodate theory and psychiatric experience. If
Husserl’s analysis of consciousness showed itself inadequate in getting to
grips with the psychiatric facts, then he resorted to a Heideggerian
interpretation of what it was to be a human being, even though he then lost
out in terms of Husserl’s emphasis on how the human world was constituted.
It was his recognition of this very fact that brought Binswanger back to strict
phenomenology in his later writings, not so much in respect of
consciousness and how it actively constituted the world, but more in the way
of a phenomenology of subjectivity, with an interest in the passive syntheses
which underlay the active syntheses. In short, Binswanger was trying to
adapt Husserl’s later notions about a ‘transcendental egology’. Whatever
one thinks about Binswanger’s rather peripatetic journey in all this, every
page of his works is testament to his faithfulness to one or other of these
philosophers. The other members of the phenomenological ‘quadrumvirate’
4
of the 1920s were much less inclined to set their work in the context of some
specific philosopher. Minkowski, Straus and von Gebsattel preferred to
keep closer to their clinical experience, and, unlike Binswanger, resisted the
temptation to bring this continually back to a systematic philosophical thesis.
The above contrast is not absolute, as Binswanger was at pains to emphasize
that his own deliberations on space and lived time were
anthropological or even psychological [and not properly philosophical]. But
our own purpose in pointing out the opposition between Binswanger and the
others is to draw attention to an ambiguity at the very heart of psychiatric
phenomenology, between philosophical and clinical analysis, even though
there are theoretical digressions in the works of the other three
psychopathologists mentioned. For example, one can find transcendental
themes in the writings of Minkowski, who latterly gave considerable weight
to the notion of a split at the core of schizophrenia, between, on the one
hand, a transcendental set of directives, and, on the other hand, a giving over
of oneself to the expressivity of others, a theme which mirrored the
intentionality and being-in-the-world poles of Heidegger.
5
More recently, phenomenological psychiatry has followed the path of
Binswanger rather than the other route. For example, the group of
psychopathologists who constitute what is known as the second Heidelberg
school – von Bayer, Kisker, Häfner, Tellenbach and Blankenburg – have
been particularly attracted to Heidegger’s existential analysis.
Two types of psychiatric phenomenology –
descriptive and genetic
In the course of the evolution of psychiatric phenomenology one can detect a
second general characteristic [in addition to the Binswanger v Minkowski,
Straus, von Gebsattel approaches]. This is a displacement of descriptive
phenomenology by genetic phenomenology [i.e. concerning the genesis of
phenomenology, nothing to do with genes]. The phenomenologists of the
1920s agreed with Minkowski, Straus and von Gebsattel that their interest
was purely descriptive, and distanced themselves from aetiological
approaches, whether psychological in general, or Freudian psychoanalytical
ones in particular, and including organic hypotheses as well. They adhered
6
to the principle of Jaspers, that, in the case of psychosis, there was an
interruption in the psychological plausibility of what was at stake, in short a
genetic incomprehensibility. But Binswanger’s Daseinsanalysis was not
compatible with this, focusing as it did on how a subject’s historical
situation intermeshed with their status as being schizophrenic, and focusing
on how their psychosis might well be comprehensible after all, not
psychologically, admittedly, but phenomenologically in some way. This
concern has given rise to a whole series of biographical accounts of how
psychosis can come about, accounts which we shall consider in our treatise.
Tellenbach and Blankenburg have been at the forefront of this trend ushered
in by Binswanger. One can say, therefore, that the original preoccupation
[by Minkowski, for example] with lived time, in general, in psychosis,
transformed itself into an actual search for the historical antecedents of a
psychosis.
The above schematic outline of our topic is by no means a clear-cut one.
There are peripheral inputs; there are also contributions purporting to inject
a proper ontological, as opposed to a phenomenological rationale, to the
7
subject matter : that of Boss, for example, or those inclined towards a
Hegelian perspective; there is the approach of Wyrsch, who was more
oriented to clinical matters; then there is that of von Baeyer, who selected
the paranoid encounter with the world as his focus of investigation. Other
versions of our theme include the anthropological theses of Zutt and
Kulenkampff. All of these challenge the very definition of psychiatric
phenomenology.
Nature and definition of psychiatric phenomenology
This last issue is not to be confused with the problems involved in defining
philosophical phenomenology, problems which Spiegelberg resolved by
isolating different versions according to how strictly they incorporated the
notions of essence, intentionality, and the ‘reduction’.
Diversity of psychiatric experience
The endeavours of psychiatric phenomenology have a familial resemblance,
in that they have as their basis a concern with the immediate character of a
psychiatric patient’s experience as it appears to the patient, coupled with an
investigator’s skill in showing such, but without a rigorous theoretical
framework as to how this should be done. The concept of experience
8
(Erfahrung) is therefore a central issue in this phenomenology, which,
moreover, takes care to mount a critique of it as well as be informed by what
the patient says about it.
In short, if psychiatry is deemed to be a ‘methodological chameleon’, as
Tellenbach (1975) referred to it as, and if psychiatry uses all sorts of
methods, then each approach to the subject matter necessarily reveals a facet
of experience which that method has determined. A scientific approach, for
example, treats the patient as a psychophysical organism, an organism which
doubles up as organic and psychic, and then views this organism as
submitting to causal laws. Because this way of looking at a patient retains
only those aspects of him or her which can be objectively verified, the
experience which it is concerned with only revolves around what is
technically able to be manipulated about the human being. Any other sort of
experience – be it what is psychologically comprehensible, or hermeneutic,
or phenomenological, or what is known as atmospheric – barely counts in
this search for what is verifiable, but is no less empirical as form of
experience for all that. The phenomenological experience stands out vis-à-
vis the others mentioned by its status as that experience which allows the
very essence of something which has earlier been achieved to illuminate
9
unique cases of whatever the essence has jurisdiction over, a characteristic
which simply does not occur in traditional empirical experience.
Phenomenological experience : empirical and
transcendental –eidetic
Phenomenology in general is bound up with the ambition to show that in
each experience there is more than ordinary empiricism recognizes, and that
what such ordinary empiricism deems to be experience is in fact a
‘curtailment’ of experience, the truth of the matter being rather as Goethe
saw, when he wrote that ‘experience is only part of what there is to be
experienced’. What there is in addition to the objective fact in experience is
the essence of what is encountered – its way of being, its ‘how it shows
itself’ – which adds to the bare and shrunken ‘what’ which science takes for
experience. This essence is the very thing which makes possible what is
given to us, and which transcendentally constitutes it. But what is properly
phenomenological is not the notion of the essence itself, but rather what is
visible, i.e. accessible to an intuitive grasp of what there is.
Phenomenology [as applied to psychiatry] does not pretend to be able to
explain anything, but it does claim to be able to provide an enlightenment
10
into psychiatric experience, i.e. to make explicit what a psychiatrist actually
already knows but does not necessarily know that he or she knows. As
Blankenburg (1965) put it:
It is not so much bringing to light new states of affairs,
but rather providing new insights into established ways
of looking at experience …….. it is a way of looking at
things which does not produce anything actually new
……. but rather like the mathematician who grasps
some formula for accommodating a whole series of
mechanical facts then subsumes these into his system
…… A formula of this sort is not the cause of these
facts, but rather a principle, and so are the essential
structures of phenomenology not causes of
psychopathological facts but are simply demonstrations
of what is ‘apriori’ and how such facts can appear.
Phenomenological experience is therefore twofold, at the same time
empirical – in its usual sense – and also apriori – as what is transcendentally
constituting the givenness of what is given, by providing the essences which
11
unify what are otherwise treated in diverse manner by [non-
phenomenological] philosophy and science alike. This project is serious
[but by no means easy]. For one thing, psychiatry deals with concrete and
individual human experience, and to say that there is some apriori constraint
on a melancholic that he or she will experience an immobilisation of life, or
a stagnation of lived time, does not accord with psychiatric practice, to wit,
the fact that obsessionals and schizophrenics also complain of these.
Introducing a transcendental component to understanding psychiatry can
only work if this is taken as part of the means whereby empirical experience
occurs, not as some isolated and additional way of knowing things.
Phenomenological experience is what is there at the root of everything, and
any other sort of method at getting at what psychiatric patients go through is
an abstraction from this. According to Binswanger, for example, clinical
experience, in its usual sense, is already a sort of reduction of any such
phenomenological experience, not only departing from the patients’ natural
experience, but foisting an organic or psychic façade on things, to such an
extent that one creates an alternate reality for the sake of turning him or her
into a clinical case.
12
Strict phenomenology regards what is reported as experience as the end-
product not the start of a whole series of factors. This is evident in
Binswanger’s studies of his various case histories – Suzanne Urban, for
instance, whose ‘experience’ he brings out as a progressive overcoming of
her actual phenomenological experience. It also explains why Binswanger
gives such weight to metaphor, or why [another phenomenologically-
oriented psychopathologist] Zutt puts his patients’ experience into everyday
German rather than struggles with their artificial translation into Greco-Latin
phraseology. We are trying to get to grips here with the distinction between
symptoms and what we regard as phenomenology. But this task is
completely obscured unless we recognize that a ‘symptom’ in physical
medicine is entirely different from a ‘symptom’ in psychiatry.
13
Schizophrenic autism according to Binswanger
Psychological and Daseinsanalytic approach
Although comments on the nature of schizophrenic autism are not absent in
the five case studies [which are the centrepiece of Binswanger’s work], at
this period [1940s, early 1950s] Binswanger was mainly at pains to promote
an ‘existential’ account of schizophrenia, treating the condition as a form of
‘inauthentic’ existence. Within this framework autism was understood as a
way of not-being-oneself (Ellen West), or as a form of disappearance of the
capacity for loving or being part of another’s existence (Jűrg Zűnd), or as an
alteration in existential temporality. There was then a transitional period,
14
when he came under the influence of the works of Szilasi (e.g. Szilasi 1959),
during which he shifted his allegiance from the existential notions of
Heidegger to the experiential preoccupations of Husserl. At this stage he
started to conceive of autism as being one of three ways in which the
customary natural attitude of a person had been lost : Verschrobenheit
[distortion, perverseness], Verstiegenheit [presumptuousness, extravagance]
and Manierlertheit [manneristic behaviour]. His use of these terms, which
clearly depart from customary language, reflected his thought at that time
that psychopathological use of language was itself a departure from
everyday language, and in the direction of the human being’s original
spiritual home in this respect.
His general aim at this time was to understand how psychopathological
symptoms were transformations of the usual mode of encountering the
world. Autism, for Binswanger, was not a specific schizophrenic
psychopathological entity, but a more pervasive consequence of not
encountering the world in the usual way. And it was something, moreover,
that had no obvious psychological explanation nor had its basis in any
rational account of experience. For example, he criticised the formulation of
Reboul-Lachaux, who had maintained that mannerisms were simply
15
involuntary movements, on the grounds that the opposition of involuntary
and voluntary was not the critical issue at stake. He similarly reproached
Minkowski, whose formulation of autism involved the notion of morbid
rationalization, by saying that something more basic was afoot. Gruhle, too,
whose general view of schizophrenia was to the effect that the patient was
[rationally] wanting to be other than himself or herself, came in for the same
criticism, in this case because the human being, according to Binswanger,
was not the sort of entity that could want to be other than itself. [In all these
alternative formulations of autism] Binswanger contested the very
anthropological basis of what was being credited to a human being –
whether in terms of conscious or unconscious motives, or voluntary or
involuntary initiation. According to Binswanger, autism, and its ways of
appearing, were simply manifestations of a human being’s propensity to
project certain ways of living a life, independently of the question of
whether we can know if there was an intention or not to desire such
particular forms of life.
Extravagance and its anthropological disproportion
16
[N.B. Tatossian translated Binswanger’s term Verstiegenheit as
présomption – presumptuousness – whereas I and Shepherd, 1987, took it to
mean extravagance. Both translations together enhance its meaning.]
Extravagance connotes the sense that one is in a situation that one has
climbed to a position from which one can neither advance further, nor
descend, and where one can only remain suspended or fall down, not unlike
an amateur climber in the Alps who misjudged the journey he had embarked
upon. The extravagant nature of the patient’s situation is shown in their go-
it-alone presumption, having lost all communications with an earlier
existential status, and are now shaping up to be some sort of person way
beyond what they are cut out to be, not unlike a character in an Ibsen play.
The patient is somehow aiming to be an ideal sort of person, shedding any
link with his or her mundane self. Binswanger returns again and again to
this theme in his case histories of schizophrenia – whether in the form of
bodily thinness, as in the case of Ellen West; or in the form of [a
pretentious] social distinctiveness, as in Jűrg Zűnd’s case; or in the way of a
total absence of familial security as in Suzanne Urban. Once their ideal
presumption has been alighted upon, their only outcomes are to come a
17
cropper, fall back on suicide, become autistic, or develop a schizophrenic
delusional state. In short, the extravagance or presumptuousness that we are
considering here is a sort of anthropological disproportion which insinuates
itself between the undoubted breadth of experience that anyone can make
use of and the loftiness of the problematic situation that they find themselves
in, but which favours a ‘vertical’ direction in any such dilemma. This
loftiness or verticality of the person’s new situation is somehow their only
route. It is not to be accounted for in terms of imagination, or love, or
enthusiasm, or art, nor is it achieved in a stepwise manner. It is rather a leap
into strangeness, leaving behind, and being incomprehensible by, the usual
sorts of psychological explanation for a change in lifestyle – e.g. versatility,
heightened imagination. It is rather proof that whatever has happened was
scarcely based on any sort of experience at all.
Perverseness and the primacy of usefulness
pushed to the extreme of ridiculousness
[NB Tatossian translated Binswanger’s term Verschrobenheit as distortion –
imbalance, disequilibrium – whereas Shepherd and I rendered it as
perverseness. Again the further dimension is a bonus.]
18
Perverseness or imbalance is exemplified in the schizoid father of one of
Binswanger’s five cases who gave her a coffin for a Christmas present; in
the act of an institutionalised schizophrenic who applied a piece of meat to
his head in an attempt to cool himself down; and in a case of Minkowski’s
who devised a rigid programme of self-improvement for himself in order to
achieve spiritual perfection. It is also illustrated by a teacher who forbade
his pupils to read a poem where the sky was supposed to have embraced the
earth, on the grounds that such an event was impossible.
A preliminary analysis of expressions which fall into this category of
perversion or imbalance – whether found in normal language or in the
vocabulary of psychopathology – clearly shows that they are derived from
words used to refer to homo faber, and in particular those who work with
solid materials – wood, steel or stone – but not silk or leather. In
perverseness (or disequilibrium) the primacy of usability [Zuhandenheit in
Heidegger’s philosophical terminology] and its transposition into the mode
of Vorhandenheit in the human being, is affected. The way in which the
world is originally discovered through its practicality and usability is
precisely what is distorted in the Binswangerian mode of perverseness or
disequilibrium.
19
The mode of perverseness, as well as ignoring the bounds of sense with
respect to usability, further oversteps the limits of the natural attitude to
anything. It treats the ‘nature of a thing’, with respect to how anyone might
use it, with complete disdain, and violates the boundaries of what we regard
as ‘good taste’: in both aspects there is a shift towards a subjective
transcendence, and away from an objective transcendence. It is bad taste,
for example, to give your sick daughter a coffin as a present, even if the act
was not ill-intentioned. It is pushing the limits of the theme of Christmas
presents, or presents in general, into the realm of the ludicrous. In his wish
to start communicating with his daughter the father ends up shutting the door
on this more firmly than ever before: his notion of a Christmas present is
actually an object which is useful, but quite inappropriate to the situation.
Likewise, the schizophrenic who tries to cool down his head with a piece of
meat ignores an entire set of connotations which meat evokes, and singles
out the simple notion of himself as a body which is too hot and which needs
cooling off, setting aside what is commonly taken for the uses of meat.
Taking matters to their extremes is also illustrated in the case of the teacher
who reduced the conduct of life to the technique of living. In all these cases,
20
the common denominator is a narrowing down of some complex matter to a
unique theme, which then takes on absolute proportions and brooks no
limits. Perverseness, in this way, has the effect of enlarging the scope of
what any thematic issue can accommodate in terms of an experiential fact,
but at the expense of losing the profundity of experience itself. The upshot
of this is a similar disproportion in the human being’s way of living as
occurs in the mode Binswanger named exaggeration or presumptuousness,
although its direction is inverse vis-à-vis the latter, as it is rather an objective
blockage in the smooth flow of our life [unlike the subjective insouciance
towards such objective obstacles which characterises exaggeration].
Manneristic behaviour and its basis in natural being
[N.B. Binswanger’s Manieriertheit, Tatossian’s translation of this as
maniérisme, and our translation as manneristic behaviour, are in accord].
Binswanger’s work on manneristic behaviour is undoubtedly the richest of
his studies on autism, even if some of it strays into complex aesthetic issues.
Overall, it contains his most revelatory insights into the nature of
schizophrenia. In French, the word maniérisme has connotations derived
from main [hand], which include guinder [to make starchy or stilted] or se
21
guinder [to become stilted], and guinder itself meant originally to hoist a
sail. Manneristic behaviour is an act of self-elevation, but its nautical
association, in the above, suffuses it with a sense of technicality and
instrumentality. Manneristic behaviour is therefore an action which results
in elevating something, but thanks to someone else, and is therefore an
unnatural development, with the implication that the process is somehow
orchestrated. All these considerations lend the term manneristic behaviour a
sense of intentionality, but one which displaces the centre of this away from
an integrated voluntariness to some peripheral region. Any conscious
intention has the flavour of emanating from a technical source. This is why
Binswanger refuses to see the entity in simple terms of voluntary or
involuntary behaviour, as Reboul-Lachoux would have it, or to invoke any
conventional psychological dysfunction as its root cause.
There is a similarity between certain sorts of artistic work and manneristic
behaviour, particularly those of the classical period. This similarity revolves
around the tendency in both to exaggerate certain naturalistic ways of life, to
crystallise some general trait of public life. But the manneristic behaviour
itself, as compared with artistic trends in this respect, is more to do with a
particular direction that ensues [unlike certain artistic styles which capture
22
diverse aspects of the human being]. Manneristic behaviour is solely that
mode of the human being which is inauthentic [here Tatossian emphasises
Binswanger’s reliance on Heideggers’ Being and Time]. The mode of living
which manneristic behaviour epitomizes is that mode which is in the realm
of thinking alone, and which veils, masks, and erects a carapace over,
anything which smacks of a natural way of living. Jűrg Zűnd, for example,
who is a paradigmatic case of the manneristic behaviour under scrutiny here,
was adept at donning three masks – that of his working-class upbringing
which he abhorred, that of his quarrelling parents, and that of his affluent
and upper middle-class grandfather. To put it more correctly, manneristic
behaviour is not a range of potential human existences seen through a mask,
but one existence only, lived in a mask, with its dire effects on self-concept,
its natural illusions, and its jealously protected visions. Jűrg Zűnd could see
no alternative in his forced need to conserve such a way of life but to seek
voluntary retreat in a psychiatric asylum.
If manneristic behaviour is a way of living which necessarily involves
donning masks in this way, rather than the subject compromised in this way
becoming accommodated to whatever they lack, this is because the subject is
completely constrained in this respect. It is not a position of putting on a
23
good impression for others, but, in this way, rather dealing with their own
internal situation, wracked as they are by angst, doubt and despair. The
disproportion which is manifest in their situation vis-à-vis the normal human
being is somehow situated in a region of the human being which is neither
overly subjective, nor overly wrapped up in the demands of merely living,
and perhaps differs from the accommodation that the normal person must
make to these two sides of his or her person. The schizophrenic’s rejection
of the compromise that a normal person makes in such circumstances is
central to the nature of this condition. Perhaps the difference between the
autistic schizophrenic and the sane is not that the former succeeds better in
distancing himself or herself from the everyday, public domain of the natural
life than does the sane [in the latter’s spiritual or mental ventures], but that
the schizophrenic simply fails to adapt to the last. With respect to the other
two modes of disproportion – extravagance and perverseness – manneristic
behaviour is the closest to the core dissociation of schizophrenia, because its
spatial manifestations, more so than in the other two, follow more closely
the presumed dissolution in the nature of a human being that constitutes
schizophrenia.
The three forms of a lack of engagement with life:
24
common traits and inherence in the human being
The three forms of failed integration into life do not exclude one another. In
the case of Ilse, for example, all three co-existed: her infliction of a severe
burn to her arm to show her father ‘what love can do to you’ was an example
of extravagance/presumptuousness, because it attests to her having gone
beyond the bounds of the usual psychological means of expressing this; it
was further perverse, because it ruined the supposed purpose of the act to
initiate communication with her father; and it was manneristic, because the
act had the hallmark of martyrdom, which she would have known from
history and literature. The three modes are therefore similar in kind, and it is
difficult sometimes to separate them in conventional language. Their
common characteristics are an immobilisation of the flow of life; a dubious,
if not dilapidated, achievement of ones ends; and a blockage of authentic
movement of life and its correlated degeneration into inauthenticity. With
respect to how these compare with the inauthentic varieties and modes of
living which the sane also manifest and pursue, the morbid nature of the
three sorts of failure discussed hitherto is bound up with a disruption of the
natural way of experiencing the world, the self and things themselves.
Perverseness, for example, reduces any situation to a general thematic, to an
idea, to a concept, or to a definition, which then becomes an absolutely
25
binding theme, which, in turn, no longer imposes any natural boundaries on
what behaviour or notion it can determine, hence substituting a subjective
transcendence for an objective one. Manneristic behaviour, for example
ends up as an artificial version of what is intended, indeed, in Jűrg Zűnd’s
case, whose aim was not to get himself noticed, he achieved the complete
opposite – getting himself constantly noticed. In extravagance, for example,
the artificiality and lack of boundaries are evident in the flight of fancy that
is manifest.
The nature of the affective trouble in melancholia
Introduction
The experience of melancholia, ours as well as that of the patient, is, above
all, that of suffering, which accounts for its unique status as a psychosis, and
characterises the flavour of the disturbed affectivity which underlies this.
But this core issue is shrouded in obscurity, despite the richness of terms in a
variety of languages which have been used to describe it. Before embarking
on a phenomenology of melancholia, therefore, we need to address this very
issue.
26
Normal and melancholic suffering
The difference between suffering undergone by a sane person, or someone in
a reactively deprived state, and melancholic suffering, is not to be found in
anything in a person’s environment nor in some specific event which
precedes such a state, and indeed there have been psychopathologists (e.g.
Schulte 1961) who have regarded the melancholic as the most autistic of
patients. Their suffering, strange to an outsider, is equally strange to the
patients themselves, who, when cured, find it incomprehensible. Tellenbach
(1974), for example, has written:
In non-psychotic sadness the self identifies itself
with the feelings it undergoes: he is his sadness,
and is equally the object of his sadness. Even in
states lacking any object, such as Weltschmerz, the
self is identical with his sadness. In melancholy,
by contrast, the self is so to speak alongside its
sadness.
Tellenbach goes so far as to say that in one sense the melancholic doesn’t
actually suffer, any more than the manic actually feels joy, both situations
being quite unlike the sane person’s suffering or joy. The melancholic
27
suffering is simply not comparable to naturally occurring suffering, not just
because it has no object, but because it is an abnormal, perverted and
deformed sort of suffering.
What sort of life the melancholic does exactly live through at such times is
also problematical, regardless of whether current clinical psychiatry regards
sadness as the defining and determining symptom. To be sure, melancholics
talk about themselves as sad and appear such to others, but what the
melancholic means by sad here is rather a reaction to the actual morbid
situation going on [and is by no means itself primary]. In fact, the notion
that a melancholic can have reactive feelings in this way is doubtful, and it is
better to view any such sadness as the melancholic’s way of expressing to
themselves and others what is actually inexpressible and inexplicable, a sort
of feeling of emptiness, of petrification, of not living at all.
Vital sadness
Scheler, who was much more influential than Husserl in the early stage of
psychiatric phenomenology, distinguished between several sorts of feelings:
sensory ones, localized in the body, such as pain, which were rather
28
perceptions of ones own body; vital feelings, which directly suffused the
body as belonging to me in the generality of its states, feelings such as well-
being or in bad health, along with psychic functions [and other experiences]
such as angst, disgust, appetite, aversion and sympathy; and feelings of
mental and spiritual worth, which were attached to being-human as a person,
feelings which had no need of a body for their realization, feelings such as
sadness, discouragement and beauty. German clinical psychopathology has
long regarded a ‘vital sadness’ as specific to melancholy, and this goes back
to Kurt Schneider’s application of these notions of Scheler’s just mentioned.
The melancholic [according to such a formulation] lives through his sadness
as localized in the head or chest or epigastrium, or experiences it in a variety
of other bodily ways – as a weight on the chest, as a tightening in the throat.
In supposing a ‘vitalization’ of sadness in this way, Schneider considered
that there might be an inhibition of feelings of the mental and spiritual
levels, an inhibition brought about by the intensity of the vital feelings.
[Against Schneider’s formulation] is the fact that a vital sadness is not a
constant feature of melancholy, and that it can be found in schizophrenia and
reactive depression. Glatzel took the view that the apparent privileged
position of a ‘vital sadness’ in melancholy was nothing to do with ‘sadness’
but to do with ‘vital’ functions [or dysfunctions of another sort]. He realized
29
that there was a ‘vitalization’ of other aspects of the melancholic’s
experience, as there was in the ‘vital anxiety’ described by Lopez-Ibor.
Melancholy as a problem of temperament or mood [l’humeur]
and not of feelings – masked depressions
Scheler’s levels of emotional life correspond [in one way] to a distinction,
familiar to German-speakers, but not easily translated into French, between
Stimmung [humeur, mood or temperament] and Gefűhl [sentiment, feeling].
For Glatzel this distinction is indispensable for understanding melancholy,
which, according to him, lies in the sphere of humeur, and is one of the
dysthymies [Verstimmungen, mood or temperamental anomaly], whereas
sadness is a feeling, and, at most, contingent on this.
Whereas feelings have a temporal sense, with a beginning, a development,
and an end, humeur implies a relative stability. Furthermore, feelings have a
direction, an affective movement, and are in response to something or
someone; humeur, on the other hand, has an element of passivity, is a state,
at a remove from a subject’s will. Such a psychic state is pervasive and
cannot be unique from moment to moment – unlike feelings which can be
multiple and simultaneous – and is tied up with a general experience of the
30
body as my own agent, an experience which can be refreshing or exhausting,
light or heavy. Humeur is further bound up with the vital sphere of the
human, and pervades it completely. This is what gives it its depth, whereas
feelings, however intense, are not profound in this sense. Nevertheless, this
depth to humeur is not something attached to the individual as a person, as it
is rather an ‘anhistorical’ process, which sets in with little in the way of
direct links to that person’s actions and reactions which make up their
biographical self. This can be contrasted with a feeling such as revenge,
which is wide open to psychological exploration in terms of something that
happened in the past.
Glatzel relies on these sorts of distinctions between humeur and sentiment to
elaborate the essential nature of melancholy. He argues that the
melancholic, whether sad or not [see p. ], is anyway party to a whole set
of problems to do with mood and temperament. The very localization of this
dysthymia to the body [and not the mind] supports this thesis, in his view.
In fact, the very existence of formes frustes, or masked varieties of
depression, or ‘depression without depression’, as it has been called, further
31
attests to the correctness of Glatzel’s views. In fact Glatzel goes further, and
says that melancholy not only does not require the presence of sadness – a
feeling – for it to be valid in some way, but even does not require the
presence of a particular mood either. [The nature of melancholy lies
elsewhere] in the same way as the existence of epileptic equivalents
scotched the notion that a grand mal seizure was the essential characteristic
of epilepsy.
Mood (temperament), syntony, and emotional
contact according to Minkowski
The very word ‘humeur’ is vague in French, and a poor translation of the
German Stimmung. [Minkowski’s attempt to tackle the linguistic and
psychopathological issues involved led him to propose that in both
schizophrenia and melancholy there was a disturbance in affective contact or
syntony – he regarded these as synonymous – and that in schizophrenia the
disturbance was in some way qualitatively different from that in
melancholia, a difference, however, which he did not elaborate further].
The melancholic’s incapability of feeling sad
32
and the melancholic’s total incapability
The nucleus of the way in which the melancholic lives his or her life is not
[according to our above considerations] based on sadness, whether vitalized
or not, but emanates from a mood disorder, or is some sort of disturbance of
affective contact. This altered state is tied up also with a change in the
temporality of the human being, attested to by what the melancholic lacks
most of all – mobility, the very core of what it is to be alive. Whereas
sadness, like all feelings, has a point of birth, a growth, a set duration, and
then disappears, a melancholic ‘sadness’ has no movement. It sits there with
a permanence that won’t budge. Furthermore, in melancholia, the self,
although knowing [in a certain way] that there is the possibility of being
liberated from the ‘sadness’, actually stands back as a spectator of the
dysthymic state that is unravelling. The suffering undergone is not,
however, merely in the incapacity to enter into a relationship with this
dysthymia, but the incapacity at issue is tied up with an incapacity for
actually feeling sadness. Schulte, for example, views this very incapability
of feeling sadness as the kernel of melancholia itself:
Someone who can still be sad is not truly
33
melancholic, and one can gauge the termination
of the latter’s illness, or its impending resolution,
by the first stirrings of an ability to feel sad.
A melancholic subject, for example, on hearing of his son’s suicide, said that
he experienced no distress, all the while being in a state of atrocious
unhappiness, whereas, after a month of treatment, he cried and felt sad, a
point in time which coincided with his being cured.
Clinical psychiatry has certainly recognized that there can be an ‘affective
anaesthesia’, a feeling of the absence of feelings, but this has been regarded
as somewhat marginal to, or as a particular sort of, melancholia. In fact it is
rather a central feature of melancholia, even though a similar state occurs in
schizophrenia, organic conditions, and even neurosis. In melancholia this
anaesthesia reaches its most developed form, and, unlike these other
conditions, is experienced by the melancholic in the most tortured way.
34
This incapacity is moreover something which overwhelms the person much
more so than sadness or any other feeling. It is pervasive and taints all sorts
of actions – eating, drinking, sleeping, working, making love. This is why
an explanation of affective anaesthesia, as promoted by Kurt Schneider – an
inhibition of joy and sadness through an intensity of vital feelings – is too
simplistic. The melancholic incapacity at stake here certainly lies in an
inhibition of some sort, but it is not a selective inhibition of this or that
function, but rather something which affects the very nature of what it is to
be human. Straus (1960) noted that joy and sadness are wrapped up with
time, and thought that it was the blocked future of a depressive which
underlay their failure to experience these emotions.
The melancholia’s body as a carrier of life
[corps-porteur]
The notion of the body as a [preconscious] carrier of what it is to be alive, as
opposed to the body as an appearance [to others and ourselves], is contained
in Scheler’s formulation of levels of experience – the living body being the
vital level at which the body is experienced, and bodily appearance being an
35
objectified [mental] version of this. In Zutt’s (1963) concept of melancholia,
the bodily experience at the level of its vital mode loses whatever it is that
makes this experience what it is, and the body is then rendered strange to the
subject. In melancholia, therefore, there is an alteration in the normal shift
between the body as an acknowledged supplier of life and the body as a
burden, towards the body being constantly experienced as a burden. In
melancholia the affective experience of this emerges as a sense of weight
which the body conveys, and this is more central to the condition than any
sadness. This sense of weight can be considered in a literal and
metaphorical sense, as it pervades the entire experience of the melancholic’s
world and self, both of which are treated with undue gravity.
Zutt sees the body as living vehicle and the body as appearance as
complementary, and further links the two, respectively, as the sites of
involuntary behaviour and voluntary action. In the former mode, it is the
shared constituents of living that are supported – nourishment, quenching of
thirst, sexuality, likes and dislikes. On the basis of the general tone to all
36
this, a human being chooses individual instances – this or that food or drink
or sexual partner.
This pre-individuated generality of the body as vehicle of life – which is
quite distinct from any post-individuated generality of, for example, drink as
drink [essence] – is wrapped up with the mood [l’humeur, Stimmung] which
we are originally in as a preconscious mode – Heidegger. This [accentuated]
preconscious generality is what stamps melancholia with its commonality
across individuals, unlike schizophrenia which is quite different from
individual to individual. As Binswanger (1960) says:
everyone has his or her schizophrenia
[according to who they are] but mania or
melancholia are the same the world over.
Zutt’s [and other’s] insistence that the body is simultaneously a carrier of
life and a worldly appearance [respectively, Leib and Kőrper], [and that the
former aspect of the body is not attenuated in melancholia] leads us to the
conclusion that any notion one attributes to the melancholic, such as lack of
trust [l’atrophie de la confiance], might well have to be seen in a double
37
light as well. The development of a paranoid attitude in melancholia could
be based either on some disorder in pre-individuated human functioning or
as the post-individuated variety [comparable in the discussion of bodily
modes to Leib and Kőrper]. Here it would appear that the melancholic’s
pre-individual disorder is the root cause of their [not uncommon] paranoid
ideas and delusions, whereas the post-individuated mode – the world of
appearances – is not the issue. Despite this formulation, one has also to note
that the melancholic’s difficulty in communicating with others is above all a
problem with respect to the other as an individual. As Celleri et al. (1972)
noted:
the depressive has not so much lost the
possibility of being at one, in general, with
another person, but has rather lost the knack of
being at one with this particular other person.
This makes any psychotherapeutic relationship quite difficult. Unlike the
schizophrenic, where a common sense of what’s what between the
schizophrenic and the sane is completely lost, in the case of melancholia this
very common sense is preserved, if not accentuated according to Tellenbach
38
certainly with respect to the predisposing personality to the condition. The
same conservation of common sense can be seen in mania, something which
accounts for the manic’s witticisms being quite on target (Blankenburg
1969).
The weight of the past and the melancholic’s sense of guilt
The immobilisation of lived time and the blocking of the future are in
complete contrast to the automatic liquidation of the past which a normal
person enjoys, this latter being achieved through an orientation to the future
rather than through a laborious annulment of the past item by item.
According to von Gebsattel (1954):
For the depressive, time is no longer the milieu whereby
he or she can unfurl their potentialities, but rather the
inverse. It has become the milieu which restricts them and
forces them into a decline. The future is menacing and
disquieting and what is to become of them quite
problematical, along with which there is a pervasive sense
of foreboding and impending catastrophe. The depressive
gives up on the future as a realm which he or she can do
anything about in the sense of changing it, and they then
39
search for salvation in a vain attempt to change the past.
In the melancholic’s experience the past cannot be dissipated, but lies
heavily and over-determining. But it is simplistic to see the problem as one
in which the past replaces the future and present.
The melancholic’s past is, to be sure, not the same as that of a normal
person’s. But it is rather that the melancholic has a specific problem in
recollecting the original situational context of a remembered event, whereas
the monotonous and stereotyped revival of such memories continues to
plague him or her, shorn of any archaeological inscription as having
occurred in the distant past. Perhaps a better way of looking at things [better
than how von Gebsattel saw matters] is to say that the melancholic, and the
manic for that matter, tend to live in an inauthentic present, in which [like
scientific time] there are merely successive moments, neither articulated nor
possessed of their own momentum. If this is so, then it would be true to say
that the melancholic’s temporality is outside the parameter of true lived
duration, and is not a temporality at all, but pure chronology.
40
The melancholic’s sense of the weight of the past and their sense of guilt are
undoubtedly linked. What was a trivial peccadillo looms large because it
was never got over and remained a latent sore liable to retrieval.
But this is not the whole story. The melancholic feels guilty because he or
she feels generally in debt to something. Some melancholics refer to
themselves as guilty of something or other, but all feel in debt somehow for
not being able to get anything going, for not being able to become whatever
they want to become. This fact makes the hoary problem of whether the
melancholic’s guilt is primary, or secondary to something else, worth
reformulating. In Jaspers’ opinion, all melancholic delusions of guilt were
understandable in terms of the subject’s affective state, and were therefore
secondary to this One of his successors, Weitbrecht (1966), admitted,
however, that, alongside this secondary sense of guilt, there was a primary
and psychologically inexplicable form. Tellenbach (1974), on the other
hand, maintained that the melancholic’s sense of guilt was always primary
and incomprehensible, the real reason for its primacy in this respect being
that it is an anomalous and monstrous sort of guilt, which emanates from a
completely endogenous region of the human being, and which escapes all
41
laws of psychology. The correct view of the sense of guilt in melancholia is
inseparable from a view of melancholia itself which places the sufferer of
such a condition in this respect in an ontological region completely outside
the normal, and, with it, the normal parameters of time. Being guilty, for a
melancholic, simply does not follow the normal rules of what guilt makes
the normal do or feel, because it is something that precedes any such
matters, and it is for this reason that the past is surveyed for evidence for this
new and morbid state of affairs.
The same anomalous source to their guilt, in an ‘endogenous’ zone, accounts
for their apparent overly moral conscience. It is, in fact, a caricature of a
normal moral conscience, a morbid moral conscience, no less, and one
deprived of any possibility that it could be redeemed by repentance in the
future, as would any normal conscience. The melancholic is actually
‘hypersensitive to values’, values which are supra-individual and universal,
such as those to do with the body, the relationship to other people, including
God, but quite blind to others.
The melancholic’s complaint according to Maldiney
42
We now come to the admirable account of Maldiney’s, employing all the
resources of Husserlian phenomenology but also incorporating Heidegger’s
existential analysis. What the melancholic has lost, according to Maldiney,
is not primarily any object, because the critical fault is situated in a pre-
objective level – that which Straus identified as the realm of feeling, and
which others have considered as the region of empathic communication. As
this level is anterior to the world of objective things, one cannot say that the
site of the core fracture is that of objectivization, but rather that the problem
with the melancholic is existence itself, and [in the context in which
Maldiney discusses this] this means Heidegger’s notion of a realm where
entities are only utensils – good for something – and are situated in an
‘environing world’, or, alternatively, in Husserl’s view, take their place in
what he refers to as the Lebenswelt [the world of concern to a living entity].
Maldiney pins his colours quite explicitly to the mast here, with respect to
what the melancholic psychosis essentially is, by invoking some disturbance
in Husserl’s notion of a Lebenswelt.
The melancholic’s complaint is expressed by a ‘subject’ , the selfdom of
which has no longer any objective correlate at all, and is further ‘a self
which has lost something’. [All this is quite paradoxical]. The melancholic
43
is he or she who complains that something has happened to their self, who
then appeals to that self to provide some clue to what has happened, but
receives nothing in reply. The melancholic’s complaint is not just a
particular way of expressing some unease, but illustrates the ultimate way
that any existing, living entity can express itself. Overall, the peculiarity of
what the depressive is bemoaning is quite striking, and has something to do
with a basic mistake of taking the context of something to be its form, or,
better, the exercising of an act which has no thematic content or in which the
theme is a red herring, all of which leads to a morass of interchangeability of
inappropriate issues.
The relevant act or state is nevertheless a function, that which converts the
Dasein [of Heidegger, the core of the human being] into representations [and
whatever concerns this Dasein]. Maldiney regards this process as at work in
all forms of psychosis. What Maldiney regards as the particular fault in all
this which gives rise to a melancholia is that the space between one sort of
self and another is treated as a game. The melancholic’s complaint of this or
that boils down to a ludic activity, which nevertheless has the effect of
suppressing objectivization.
44
There is a linguistic peculiarity in how the melancholic expresses the
complaint too. The characteristic way of putting the complaint is as follows:
If I hadn’t done such and such, or if I had done such and such, then I
wouldn’t be in this situation now. This does not correspond to any of the
recognized linguistic sorts of utterances – factual, performative, prescriptive.
These are predicated on some substantial state of affairs in the world,
whereas the melancholic’s is not – it is predicated on precisely nothing that
does correspond to anything in the world. In effect, it is a proposition which
expresses something from, but does nothing to clarify the situation of, the
melancholic who speaks it. It has a function of expressing a grievance, a cry
of suffering, what Wittgenstein referred to as part of what it is like to be in
pain. For all this, the melancholic’s complaint is impersonal; it is the act of
an anonymous self who gives the impression [as in cases Maldiney
mentions] of things happening – arriving, departing – devoid of any
individuated belonging to the events as they unfold.
One of his cases – Cécile Műnch – feels guilty of what she knows not what,
feels a victim of an anonymous power, and is aware of some destiny
accorded to her, but cannot properly understand what is going on, because
45
she deems herself to have no self anyway which could act as a vehicle for
this destiny, and, instead, only senses an emptiness.
Maldiney shows that the melancholic is trapped between two limiting
situations – a past event which he or she rails against, and the present which
does not open properly to the future; the result is a never-ending repetition,
because time stands still, or does not actually arrive. The temporality of the
melancholic is not like the normal sort which moves ahead smoothly with
the present determining the future, but one in which the past, in advance,
casts it despairing stamp on the present.
The melancholic is, in short, someone who is alienated from themselves, for
the reasons that they cannot breach the [morbid] limits they are constrained
by [a past that is never over and a future that never comes], because they are
preoccupied with the selves within them that have been rendered alien by all
this, and because they cannot communicate with others not so affected.
The notion of ‘Endon’ : endogenicity as endocosmogenicity
In his book on melancholia, Tellenbach (1974) is not trying to bring the
established findings of anthropological phenomenology to bear on the
condition, but to establish its pathogenesis independently of any
46
psychological or biological thesis. In fact, Tellenbach is only following
clinical psychopathology in this respect, as it too recognises the lack of
clear-cut somatic aetiology and admits the psychological
incomprehensibility of melancholia, which is why the condition is classed as
an endogenous psychosis. For Tellenbach, neither psychodynamic
mechanisms – in particular psychoanalytic ones – nor any nycthemeral
disturbance of 24 hour rhythm, can do justice to the condition. According to
Tellenbach, the only way to approach melancholia is by means of a
phenomenology which allows for a global modification of the core state of a
human being.
Clinical psychopathology, however, has given the term ‘endogenous’ a
negative value, in contrast with the positive one attached to somatogenic. In
order to restore an authentic positive value to the realm he is pinpointing,
Tellenbach’s task is to investigate the characteristics of the manifestations of
the ‘Endon’, which he regards as a third aetiological field, alongside – or,
better, anterior to – the somatic and psychic fields. In the normal person, as
in the sick, these manifestations have in common a global nature, which
applies to any phenomenon, that is to say that each trait of the ‘Endon’ refers
to the ‘Endon’ as a whole, giving rise to a synoptic approach. In fact they
47
are not only responsible for the psychic personality as a whole, as
Minkowski surmised, but underlie human corporeality as well The field of
influence of the ‘Endon’ is transsubjective and metapsychological, and
trans-objective and metasomatological, all at the same time.
Among the manifestations of the ‘Endon’ are the phenomenal rhythms of
life: sleep and waking; the female reproductive cycle; the particular
phenomena belonging to movement, the slowing or acceleration of which
occurs in normal life as well as in endogenous psychoses; and the
phenomena of maturation, including pathological varieties which account,
for example, for the onset of hebephrenia around puberty and for the
involutional psychoses in old age. Another feature of the ‘Endon’ is the
reversibility of any pathological forms, certainly in principle, although this is
less evident in schizophrenia than in cyclothymia.
In terms of its links with original modes of being human, the phenomena of
the ‘Endon’ stand outside any individual’s will, and, in fact, suffuse any
human event with their own flavour. In short, the ‘Endon’ is best conceived
of as the Greek notion of Nature – physis – which encompasses the self and
the world and is no more impersonal than is biology and no more personal
48
than existence itself. The ‘Endon’ is situated before either of them, and
founds them, but is also in place after them, because they structure it. As an
intermediary between mechanism and meaning it is closer to the core of the
human being than to mechanism, but closer to life than meaning, and is a
mediate term between necessity and freedom.
In the second edition of his book (Tellenbach 1974), he realigns the ‘Endon’
with the existential categories enunciated by Heidegger, but he eliminates
from his, Tellenbach’s, notion the following Heideggerian categories – care;
being-towards-death; and anything to do with world-formation, such as
historicity, spirituality, language, moral conscience, ipseity, choice or
decision. He retains in his notion the sense of the human being as a thrown
object, but this is taken to be an ontic entity derived from Heidegger’s
ontological formulation. Further, Tellenbach also retains the sense of the
‘Endon’s’ being a receptive entity, sensitive to the feelings of whatever
situation it is in. The ‘Endon’, in the light of all this, is at root an
‘endocosmogenicity’, in both the Greek sense of physis and in Goethe’s
sense. The ‘Endon’ shows itself to be, in effect, a correlation, not of some
causative source, but of a resonance with the world, as wakefulness is with
daytime, as sleep is with nighttime, as hunger is with the nourishing world,
49
and as sexual desire is with the world in its erotic mode. These meaningful
contents to which the ‘Endon’ opens the gate are roughly similar to what
Kunz refers to as the ‘contents of vital significance’, which he, Kunz,
opposes to the intentional contents which require the intervention of
language.
This world which the ‘Endon’ opens out on to is both a human world and the
world of nature, but, in the latter case, it is not populated by things but by
tools – in Heidegger’s sense. Because tools are not yet things, the
Zuhandenheit (the term Heidegger uses to describe a pre-thingly
environment of ready-to-hand tools] is not yet Vorhandenheit [Heidegger’s
term for a genuine world of things deemed by humans already there whether
needed or not]. And because this Zuhandenheit to Vorhandenheit transition
has not yet occurred, the ‘endogenicity’ at issue in Tellenbach’s work cannot
be confused with somatogenesis or psychogenesis, as the somatic and
psychic apparatuses do not appear until after the transformtion from tools to
things. For this reason, the ‘Endon’ is neither psychologically
comprehensible nor somatically explicable, even if somatic and psychic
mechanisms sometimes crop up in objective manifestations of the ‘Endon’,
such as erotica.
50
Pathogenesis of melancholy according to Tellenbach
It is in precisely this region – the region of the ‘Endon’ – which knows
nothing about the distinction between self and other, or between me and the
world – where the fundamental happenings which give rise to melancholia
occur. In this region it is indeed Nature that is involved, but not the ‘Nature’
that science investigates; furthermore, it is a region where human life and
world first interact.
Towards a phenomenological anthropology of delusion
Anthropological phenomenology, Daseinsanalysis, and psychology
Although Jaspers maintained that he was pursuing a non-prejudicial account
of psychopathological facts, it is not difficult to uncover in his work the very
suppositions which are the infantile faults made by all psychologists, that the
human being is composed of subject and object, psyche and soma, and self
and world.
It is the refusal to acknowledge such distinctions which gave birth to the
psychiatric phenomenology of the 1920s, a movement which was explicitly
51
counter to Jaspers and his dogmatic insistence of an incomprehensibility to
the psychoses. This birth is marked by an anthropological approach, evident
in the very titles of the works of the early contributors: Psychology of the
human world (Straus 1960, a collection of papers from 1928 onwards)
Prolegomena to a medical anthropology (von Gebsattel 1954, with papers
from 1928 onwards); and On the path towards an anthropological
psychiatry (Zutt 1963, with papers from 1929 onwards), evoking some
untitled remarks of Minkowski in his treatises (Minkowski 1927, 1933).
Storch, too, can be included here, on account of his contemporary and
similarly entitled work, Problems of human existence in schizophrenia
(Storch 1965, a collection of early papers). The position of Binswanger, as
we saw (p. ), was more nuanced: the first volume of his collected
works is entitled Phenomenological anthropology (1947 ), but even at
that time [articles dating back to the 1920s] he was working towards his
Daseinsanalyse, in which he was already distancing himself from
anthropological psychiatry, and was, moreover, looking for a positive way of
formulating matters, as compared with this anthropological approach, which
was to a large extent merely a negative reaction to the mistaken basis of
psychology.
52
Minkowski’s (1933) principle of a two-way
interpretation of psychopathology
Minkowski (1933) pointed out that one could interpret delusion in two ways:
1) by focusing on ideo-affective aspects within a psychological framework;
and 2) by investigating the very spatio-temporal structure to the experience,
an exercise which gave an anthropological dimension to any research.
Within the first framework, we achieve an understanding of the patient, and
set up an ideational rapport and a sympathetic bond. By taking the second
path, however, we come face to face with the very elements of the
syndrome, and, in effect, come up against a barrier which shows us that our
own way of reasoning cannot get a handle on the delusions of the patient,
and precisely because these are mere secondary expression of a mental life
which is quite different from our own. And, furthermore, this difference
resides in some transformation on the part of the patient of the way the
patient’s self is situated in relationship to space and time. In short the
delusions we see in melancholia chiefly concern a morbid process in the
realm of temporality, whilst a similar morbid derangement affecting
53
spatiality gives rise to delusion itself, what de Clérambault (1942) referred to
as mental automatism.
Minkowski’s principe du double aspect shows clearly that the
incomprehensibility of delusion disappears when one moves from the
psychological domain of ideo-affective concerns to the structural or
anthropological level of temporal and spatial considerations. But although
Minkowski establishes in this way that the patient with a mental illness is
qualitatively different from a normal person, the level implicated by
Minkowski where such a qualitative difference originates – involving spatio-
temporal structures – is not sufficiently general to accommodate the sort of
qualitative differences at issue, and one has to say that Minkowski’s
achievement in pointing out in a negative fashion what is altered or lost is
not the ultimate aim of a phenomenological anthropology.
Comprehensive anthropology of
Zutt and Kulenkampff
54
Under the title of comprehensive anthropology, a term specially chosen by
Zutt and his student Kulenkampff to distinguish what they were doing, as
opposed to what Binswanger was doing in his Daseinsanalyse, these two
psychopathologists published a number of works which illustrate the fertility
of an anthropological approach, but also demonstrate the difficulty in
maintaining a clear distinction between this and a psychological approach.
Little known in France, but eminently accessible on account of its forceful
clinical insights put in the context of traditional nosology, comprehensive
anthropology, as these authors have dubbed their work, largely relies on
notions of the body developed by Sartre and Merleau-Ponty. The chief
account is in Zutt’s ( 1958) article on endogenous and organic psychoses,
with a focus on the paranoid syndrome, and this is a topic which
Kulenkampff also studied.
The paranoid syndrome and an aesthetic-physiognomonic disorder
of the body in its mode as an appearing thing
55
For Zutt, to understand a phenomenon in an anthropological way is to see its
basis in the entire region of what it is to be a human being. The paranoid
syndrome, for example, is to be seen as arising from the aesthetic-
physiognomonic region of the human being, and not from its affective
domain. Zutt considers that an aesthetic alteration can take two forms: 1) ‘a
destructive modification in our capacity to create appearances [of ourselves],
and to remain constant in them, along with our capacity to dissimulate and
disguise what we are’ – this, according to him, being at the root of
schizophrenic autism; and 2) the paranoid syndrome viewed in a similar
way, but in respect of the physiognomies [of people and objects]
encountered, rather than how we ourselves are viewed. Concerning this
second sort of disorder, he writes that the same person can completely ignore
any potential meaning offered to us in an encounter with someone else, as,
for example, when passing through the street, or can register some functional
role of the other person – recognizing them as a postman, policeman or
garage mechanic – without treating them as having a direct reference to
oneself. The normal person thus avoids the impossible task of deciphering
every nuance of what the world potentially offers up. This person,
moreover, retains a trust in what goes on around, in the sense that there are
no malign intentions among those familiar to him. Not so the paranoid. He
56
or she cannot consign those around him to either strangers or those familiar
to him, and cannot rely on the familiar being non-malign.
The realm in which these perturbations take place is that of the body-as-
thing. The patient lets himself or herself be subjugated by the gaze of
another person, another person, moreover, who, despite being individualised,
is ‘the other as universal’. This subjugation takes place in both the visual
and the auditory modalities. The latter fact underlies the frequent
occurrence of auditory-verbal hallucination in schizophrenia, which result
from the fact that not only is the paranoid person at the mercy of whoever
looks at him or her, but also of whatever is being said about them.
The body-as-thing realm where this is going on is a spatially laid out realm,
unlike the living body or body as agent, which is a circumscribed entity
within the boundaries of its cutaneous sensation. Kulenkampff, invoking
Sartre’s notion of a self that has a sense of always being observed, and one,
moreover, whose own observations are always being themselves observed
by another, claims that the deluded person is he or she in which such goings-
on [otherwise normal, and constitutive of a self, in the case of Sartre’s view
57
of what constitutes a normal human] [somehow achieve an extreme form
and] break through the barriers of the person, penetrating their thoughts,
taking possession of him, and knowing everything about him, even to the
extent of being a conduit for the other’s thoughts themselves.
What protects any human being from succumbing to the processes, just
discussed, is what Kulenkampff refers to, following some comments by
Straus, as the capacity to take a stand [Stand, stance] against these
vicissitudes, a capacity which involves resisting them with the living body,
and holding them at a distance, a prerequisite of human freedom. What the
normal human being does under these circumstances is to hold its distance,
to close up to the raw influence of the myriad of physiognomic potentialities
in their environment, and transform them into concepts. What Straus
referred to as a wild space – a space of pre-reflexive communication with
the world – is rendered an aesthetic space, which, in turn, is converted into
geographic or anatomical space.
In respect to its demerits, this sort of approach – comprehensive
anthropology [as we have presented it] – is constantly in danger of merely
translating clinico-diagnostic concepts into another terminology, obscuring,
58
in this way, its actual nature as yet another psychological analysis. As
Blankenburg pointed out, the notions it brings up are rather chapter titles for
a phenomenological analysis of something which is promised but never
delivered.
‘Autonomisation’ of the possibilities of being human
Jaspers and his successors made delusional perception into a pathognomonic
sign of true delusion, whereas a classic study by Matussek showed that
similar perceptions were not confined to the delusional and that, anyway,
perception itself was not an all or nothing fact, but rather a compromise
between a variety of takes on whatever was being perceived.
Blankenburg (1965b) proposed the notion of a differential phenomenology,
a view which tried to take into account in what way the sane person and the
schizophrenic differed in reaching such compromises or eidetic finality in
their perception. He thought he could illustrate his point by comparing what
a schizophrenic ‘saw’ in a painting with what an artist such as Rilke ‘saw’ in
a work of art.
59
The two experiences are superficially similar. The patient, confronted by a
reproduction of a picture, almost certainly one of Gaugin’s, was fascinated
by its blueness, and exclaimed it to be an augury of the soul, which
henceforth would dominate his life. Rilke, on the other hand, in his sonnet
entitled, Archaic torso of Apollo, evokes his experience of contemplating a
statue in the Louvre, which also seemed to say to him, You must change
your life. In both cases, the observer is subjected to a passive experience;
and in both there is an element of influence by a worldly, artistic object;
and, in both, the usual self of the observer is replaced in the experience by an
appeal to another sort of self, to another agenda, and to another
transcendental organization.
In the case of the schizophrenic, however, the self-transformation is
irreversible and totally passive, something quite unique to a delusional state,
in which, moreover, the objective transcendence is swept away by the new
subjective transcendence now in force. In the case of the poet, the
transformation is not given as an event merely submitted to, but rather as a
task to be entered into, and integrated into his life, assimilated with
everything else he has experienced, and then communicated, with due
respect to the rules of intersubjectivity, as a poem. What the schizophrenic
60
lacks is precisely the dialectic unity and dynamic between receptivity and
spontaneity which is conserved in the poet. What keeps the schizophrenic
and the poet apart is not the actual delusional perception, which both share,
but the lack of autonomisation in the latter, which is prevented from
happening by the dialectical union which is conserved.
Dialectical equilibrium between truth and non-truth,
authenticity and inauthenticity
It is Heidegger, above all, who underlined the dialectical relationship
between truth and non-truth, and, in Being and Time, between authenticity
and inauthenticity.
It was Storch who then first tried to formulate delusion as a form of
inauthentic existence, and, indeed, he was the first to apply the corpus of
Being and Time [only published in 1927] to psychiatry. Several other
psychiatrists, including Binswanger, attempted the same feat subsequently.
What Storch drew from Being and Time was the notion that delusion was a
mode of illusional life, as opposed to a genuine life, and that the reason the
61
deluded succumbed to this lay in biographical incidents in their past,
particularly the subject’s relationship to their mother.
This way of conceptualising delusion, which underlay his enthusiasm for
psychotherapy for the condition, of which he was a pioneer, is common to
Binswanger, Zutt and Kulenkampff, as well as Boss and Laing. But none of
these writers properly tackles the issue of delusion, or madness in general, as
a dialectic disequilibrium between authenticity and inauthenticity, but rather
focuses on the deluded or schizophrenic as exemplifying pure negativity, in
respect of an authentic life, or, at best, as some deviation in this line.
In fact, to regard delusion as an inauthentic way of being human does not do
justice to what Heidegger said of the normal human being. Heidegger
regarded an authentic way of comporting oneself as a very exceptional
achievement on the part of a human being anyway, and something that even
then was achieved ephemerally. An inauthentic existence was in fact the
norm for a normal human being, in the form of an everyday, humdrum
grind. So, an inauthentic existence is equally in view in everyday life, as it
is in delusion, and [if delusion is to be formulated in such terms] there must
be two sorts of inauthenticity in play here, one of the everyday type, and one
62
pertaining to madness, which Kisker (1970) designated, respectively as
primary and secondary, and which Blankenburg (1971) termed
asymptomatic and symptomatic. What is at stake here is to determine why
the deluded is no longer capable of an everyday life, i.e. the very difference
between the sane person’s non-truthful way of living or its inauthenticity
with respect to a truthful or authentic way of living, and that of the deluded
person: why, in short, the dialectical equilibrium between these two
disappears in the case of the deluded, but not in the case of the sane.
Being and time as a school of experience
Despite difficulties in applying Being and Time to psychopathology –
regardless of which, Binswanger, Storch, Kuhn, Häfner, Straus, von
Gebsattel, Zutt, Kulenkampff, von Baeyer, and Tellenbach, all made it their
bible – whilst acknowledging these, Blankenburg estimates that this book is
the source of a way forward for psychopathology which transforms the
subject, and leaves way behind any sort of psychological analysis, including
psychoanalysis, and any sort of comprehensive anthropology, as we have
seen.
63
For Blankenburg the critical novelty contained in Being and Time [for the
purposes of illuminating psychopathology] is the deliberate ambiguity in the
word ‘Being’, which is both a verb, and noun with a sense of movement.
This gives the whole subject a sense that what is at stake in the development
of a delusion is a fluidity in the very notion of what a human being can be,
and that one of these versions could be a delusional state.
In the first place, there is the notion of intentionality [which is situated, in
Heidegger’s work, quite differently from how it is in Husserl’s, in a pre-
conscious realm]. In the second place, there is the issue of the multiplicity
of ways of being that a human being has in a nascent state, one of which,
which every normal person carries within, is the potential to be deluded.
This pre-delusional propensity, which we all carry, already contains the
germ towards autonomisation, discussed below (p. ), and is the reason why
the delusional way of life is understandable [up to a point]. What the
philosopher [meaning Heidegger] elaborates ontologically, in terms of the
way its core nature can present as this or that way of living, is encountered
in the deluded person as an actual ontical reality. And, whereas, in the sane,
these polarised ontological structures [intending something from a mental
64
point of view and passively receiving the raw world at face value] maintain
themselves in a dialectical unity, admittedly with some oscillation and
hiccoughs, this unity in the deluded is rent asunder, with the result that an
alternative rigidity sets in, freezing what are in fact ontological possibilities
into ontic certainty, and condemning transcendental potential into empirical
facts.
[The core notion of Binswanger] is to the effect that although the world that
the deluded person invents and resides in is an intentional world, what
makes it delusional is some hiatus in the smooth workings of the pre-
intentional world. This hiatus is precisely, according to Binswanger’s
interpretation of Being and Time, a modification of the core human being’s
relationship to its being in this very world. It is for this reason, contrary to
what Jaspers thought, that there is no valid comparison at a scientific level
between the deluded world and the sane world [for the reason that the
common denominator has been removed in the perturbations of the core
human being]. The world that anyone encounters is not a ‘what’ but a ‘how’
[how some primordial potential determines what comes into being]. The
deluded world is obviously a different sort of world from that of the sane,
but both are products of the same original potential. For this reason,
65
contrary to what Descartes thought, there is no absolute world to which all
human beings belong, precisely because, according to Heidegger, there is
scope for a variety of ‘hows’, i.e. how the primordial potential makes
whatever come about. What distinguishes the sane human’s world from that
of the deluded is not, or is not essentially, any concordance with any
supposed external reality On the contrary, the sane human’s world is not
more true vis-à-vis the deluded in this respect, because truth and reality in
this case are confounded in both scenarios.
The critical task of Binswanger’s Daseinsanalysis of delusion is to show that
the deluded also live in a world, and then to describe what sort of world it is.
Any such description of any worth, however, is not fundamentally geared to
merely describing this world in respect to its what, but to address the issue of
how any such world comes about, to ponder on how an autonomisation of
the extant possibilities determined by the essence of what it is to be human
result in a delusional mode of living.
The problem of limits in delusion:
the case of Franz Weber
66
In the case of delusional spatialization, one encounters the problem of limits,
particularly evident in the case of Franz Weber reported by Kuhn (1952).
This patient, previously a draughtsman, passed his entire time in the asylum,
where he lived for fifteen years, sketching out a plan for a town where
human culture would find a safe haven while war was being waged all round
it. Common to several versions of this town was the notion of limits: there
were material limits in the form of walls and guards, and spiritual limits in
the form of ritual processions which periodically took place around the
town. In the centre of the town he envisaged a number of diverse
constructions, hastily sketched, and sometimes merely indicated by lists of
words, such as silk works, art schools, chemist, nation, continent, world.
The patient explained that by doing all this he was circumscribing
knowledge, which, although not actually of use at the moment, would come
into its own when the war had destroyed everything outside the town.
The whole impression conveyed by this delusional town, according to Kuhn,
is of someone wanting to preserve the world. But whereas, in our world,
beings of various sorts present themselves in a living relationship, in the
form of handy items – objects that are good for this or that, tools, and stand
in this way for the beings as well – in the world of Franz Weber everything
67
is more or less a thing, completely isolated in itself, and lacking any mutual
links. The patient, however, feels obliged to bring them all together, to
prepare an inventory of them, for the sole purpose of not seeing this
phantom of a world dissipate, and he therefore piles up in the interior of his
town all those beings with which he has actually no living relationship. The
overall sense of this delusional state is therefore the ‘transformation of the
tool into the thing’, [in Heidegger’s terminology] the switch from handy tool
to permanent thing [Umschlag von zuhandenen Zeug in vorhandenen
Seiendes].
At the end of his analysis Kuhn puts forward a comparison between the
overall attitude to things of his patient and so-called scientific activity. And
indeed both come under [what Heidegger referred to as] Vorhandenheit – a
mode of being where things simply subsist as if real – as opposed to
Zuhandenheit – the mode of usefulness. The former orientation is precisely
that of a manipulation of the world and the body, making out the latter to be
a corpse, the objectivity of which is what is meant as soma. Deluded
subjects such as Franz Weber, and scientists too, do indeed limit what they
are concerned about out of all the universe to what is a simple, subsistent
thing.
68
The case of Achtzig
The region of the human being in which the delusional consciousness
resides, along with the sense of its infallibility, is well illuminated by
Blankenburg’s (1958) study of the case of Friedrich Achtzig, a man of 76,
with a paranoid delusional system. He had had a short-lived mystical-
megalomanic episode at the age of 28, followed by 35 years of somewhat
precarious family life, and had now been a psychiatric in-patient for 10
years. He thought himself to have a divine mission, and was concerned with
the entire universe, of which he deemed himself virtually the emperor, and
was engaged in preparation for the forthcoming struggle between Good and
Evil. At night, part of himself would be travelling all over the place, and
during the day he would be inspecting his invisible houses in the town, or
busying himself with ‘hyperimmortals’, beings from on high, and what he
referred to as the 5th Reich. Achtzig did not live in a world of goods or
useful entities, but rather in a magico-mythical world, which was suffused
with the sacred. It revealed to him directly the possibilities of being, and he
was guided by it in everything he said and did. The transcendental and
69
ontological were for him as close and familiar as the empirical and ontic are
to us. In fact, he experienced these latter two with a sense of distance,
exactly as we would experience the former two, and, for example, was quite
proud of himself for knowing how to use a tram. Whatever comes naturally
to us was for him something he could only deal with from the outside,
whereas when it came to the totality of beings in the world he felt quite at
home. Numbers, which for us are second nature, he took to possess a
mysterious and overly significant force, as evident in the nine realms which
he was forever distinguishing. The equilibrium between subjective and
objective transcendence was profoundly modified in his case. Thus Achtzig,
when recounting some historical anecdote, which he liked to do, paid no
heed to the detail, which he was not interested in, but steeped himself in
whatever essential matter and universal import he could draw out of it.
Achtzig’s notion of space as an ontic entity accorded remarkably with how
Heidegger formulated it ontologically. Furthermore, it was not really any
fixed delusions or set of delusions that he presented, but rather delusional
activity or ‘deluding’ [délirer, wähnen] that was going on. What was
constant was the eidetic source of all this, allowing him to summon up
possible worlds.
70
Autonomisation and metamorphosis of the transcendental
organization : the case of O.S.
Another case of Blankenburg’s (1965a) illustrates how his work as a whole
is a definite step forward [in phenomenology] as, unlike other
psychopathologists we have considered, Blankenburg manages to explicate
the transition from natural to delusional experience without recourse to any
psychologisation whatsoever. The transition is not from one sort of psychic
functioning to another, but between two types of transcendental
organisation. What Blankenburg calls empirico-apriori experience is the
critical shift here, with categorical perception, not sensible perception, being
involved, i.e. a vision of essences. What he means by this is that a
transcendental organization is responsible for the relationship to ones self
and to the world, and for that between self and world. In a normal person,
the last of these is an open mutuality, where self and world, taking up
themes and what is thematized, and questions and answers on all this, are in
a dialectical balance. Not so in the deluded, where certain world themes
themselves have a tendency to monopolise the attitude of the self, and then
71
further determine what that self can not but focus on – hence ‘empirico-
apriori’, meaning the empirical takes on the role of apriori.
O.S. illustrates this. He was a 35 year-old railwayman, shy and reserved,
and ill at ease with the ‘distinguished’ people in the local ecological society
of which he was a member. A few years ago he had married a girl ten years
younger. A short while before his admission he had found a watch, but, too
busy, he had not handed it in straight away. But he had then started
worrying about the matter, especially after seeing a reference to the watch in
the lost and found column of his newspaper. Believing himself spied on by
the police, he became distrustful of his friends, asked them if they knew
anything of what was going on, discovered allusions to the watch in various
places, and wanted to give the watch to a friend as a gift, but he refused. He
heard voices talking about the watch, accusing him of having a bomb as
well. He buried the watch after having broken it, by which time he had
begun to fear a plot against him involving the police and his wife. While
hospitalised, which he thought had been set up by the police, he went
through a period of complete clarity about everything that had happened, but
he then relapsed, and he had two further delusional phases before he
stabilised.
72
What the case shows is a series of steps in how the theme of autonomisation
develops, in this instance with the focus on the watch.
The first step here was when O.S, still in possession of the watch, looked
through the newspapers for any announcement of the loss. At this point he
was already not acting like someone genuinely and naturally concerned with
the legality of the situation, as, otherwise, he would have kept it – i.e. acted
as a criminal – or handed it in – i.e. acted as a good citizen – both within the
normal system. Instead he chose to re-present the situation in his own way,
creating his own judicial world in the process.
The next step was the transition from sphere of action to sphere of
experience. The critical event for O.S. here was when he read in a
newspaper that it is morally wrong to keep an object that one has found for
more than three days. What is happening here is that the event is no longer a
spur to action of some sort, but is thematized into a way of grasping world
events in general. [Scheler, by the way, refers to this as the objective
become subjective, which is how in childhood, at any rate, knowledge and
ways of knowing grow]. The watch business becomes a cognitive scheme
73
interpreting everything else that is going on, a sort of cancerous growth in
the cognitive apparatus which brooks no opposition to the theme which it
foists on the human being. Despite all this, the subject, at this stage, feels
himself or herself an innocent observer of incredible goings-on.
The next step is the decisive one. The innocence the subject feels is now
pushed to its limits by what he is in the course of experiencing – friends
shunning him – and he begins to draw back, and stop talking about the
matter. The preoccupations which he had – with the watch – which were
hypotheses are now theses, and this is because there is a transformation of
the transcendental organisation which now renders all experience in the
service of the autonomised theme. It – the experience – may take the form
of hallucination or illusions, or a delusional atmosphere, or a delusional
insight, but what renders it delusional is [paradoxically] that the new rogue
scheme does not commandeer all aspects of the perceived world. It is this
very residue of normality which allows the deluded person to continually
question and be amazed about the events unfolding before him.
Overall, the autonomization of some delusional theme – in this case an event
with a watch – is best understood as a progressive loss in the ‘transparency’
74
of the particular thematical issue involved. In a sane person any such theme
– i.e. a preoccupation with an event such as a picked-up watch – can be
compared to the blind person’s cane which functions as part of him, and is
an organ of perception of sorts. A thematic preoccupation is similarly a way
of guiding thoughts and actions, which is nevertheless transparent, because it
allows the subject to take things as they come, whether for or against or
neutral to the project in view. Where the deluded subject differs in this
respect is that the very theme is not transparent, but opaque, and, instead of
opening out this or that avenue to solving some problem, closes the very
gates to any such solution. Moreover, the theme which is supposed to be
directing the subject’s actions then becomes an object in itself [generating
the paradoxical situation that an objective event becomes more subjectively
influential in the deluded subject’s perceptual representation of other events,
but also more objectivized than any similar but non-delusional
preoccupation that a normal person might be engaged in]. This objectivity
further obstructs [further to the inappropriate subjectivization of what after
all was a trivial event] any balanced view as to what’s what about matters
quite tangential to a theme of watches and found objects, etc. The overall
upshot is that the new thematic autocracy no longer reflects or represents the
actual situation in the world [ne raconte plus le monde] but only its, the
75
autocratic theme’s, own indulgent scenarios [ses propres histories], to do
with suspicions and persecutions.
Binswanger’s Wahn book and the move to the
phenomenology of constitutive genesis
Wahn (Binswanger 1965), as well as his earlier book Melancholie und
Manie (Binswanger 1960), belongs to the phase of his ‘return to Husserl’,
and more precisely to the genetic phenomenology of the later Husserl, with
an emphasis on Husserl’s notion of a Lebenswelt, a pre-intentional rapport
with the world. Binswanger claims that in Wahn and Melancholie und
Manie he does not abandon his Daseinsanalyse, based as it was on
Heidegger’s Being and time, but goes on to say that psychiatric
phenomenology cannot do without either. What the later Husserl allows,
however, is not a description of delusional experience, but merely the
possibility of responding to the question as to why and how this particular
sort of experience occurs.
In his introduction to Wahn, Binswanger discusses the two approaches to
psychopathology, the Heideggerian and the Husserlian, and concludes that
what he is doing in espousing a Husserlian approach is actually making what
76
he previously did of a Heideggerian sort in his Daseinsanalyse more
scientific. What he further claims, however, is that whereas his
Daseinsanalyse was an attempt to show that the mad person replaced what
was ontological by what is ontic, the emphasis on Husserl shows that what
the mad person is doing is completely the opposite – it is that he or she is
really replacing the ontic by the ontological.
What is just as striking is that he uses one of the same five cases on which
his Daseinsanalysis was based – Suzanne Urban – to argue for this new and
inverted position. What he now sees is that a case such as this is delusional,
not because she is disposed emotionally to this state, but because she is
captivated by beings themselves, i.e. escapes the lures of the Greek physis
[animality] only to be taken over by what he refers to as the ‘terrific’, the
pure strangeness of what beings are, and this shift [on the part of the deluded
no less than on the part of Binswanger’s volte-face] is accounted for by the
new situation’s being a consequence of ‘subjective transcendence’ and not
‘objective transcendence’ i.e. it is to be put down to what the subject intends
and not what the object passively evokes in the human being.
77
He then invokes a further case, the case of Aline (Binswanger 1965) to
illustrate his new position. She was convinced that she had a plaster around
her head which picked up other thoughts and transmitted them to her
and kept her bones in place, which otherwise would be displaced by a
previous ECT. [She had other delusions, which, in contrast with the above],
led Binswanger to conclude that she had a complete lack of sensible
intuitions, or rather a replacement of them by some mechanical device, and
that nothing was left of a normal communicability with other people –
everything was now electrical, and the like. [In view of this Binswanger
seemed to have retreated from the emotional and being-in-the-world and
other such notions with which he had formulated the condition heretofore.]
In a further case (Binswanger 1965), of the celebrated dramatist Strindberg,
Binswanger analysed some of what Strindberg wrote of his experiences, and
what he, Strindberg, concluded to be their nature: thoughts without images,
concepts without a sensible representation, considering himself to be
perceiving ‘everywhere intentions, orders and punishments’; and
furthermore his sense of living in the presence of someone else, but not
78
someone with any corporeal presence but rather of someone without any
appearance – an appresentation without presence, impersonal and invisible.
Strindberg’s delusional state was therefore much more complex than the
mechanical toings and froings of Aline, or Suzanne Urban’s experience of
slander. He had persecutory elements, certainly, but also a religious theme,
and also several subthemes of a scientific nature, to do with what he thought
he had discovered.
In view of all this, particularly Strindberg’s delusional motifs of a religious
and scientific nature, Binswanger was right to veer towards Husserl and see
in this philosopher’s emphasis on logic that the deluded state was something
to do with a logical anomaly [as opposed to any emotional anomaly, which
he had laboured under an apprehension about with his focus on Heidegger’s
early philosophy]. Even more, Strindberg’s situation is rather that he,
Strindberg, is not even captivated by other beings, as in the case of Aline,
and certainly not in the throes of guilt like Suzanne Urban, but is living in
another realm completely apart from these – and is quite clearly into a logic
of superior power – outside anything at all to do with the core of the human
being.
79
References
Binswanger, L. (1947). Ausgewählte Vorträge und Aufsätze. Francke,
Berne.
Binswanger, L. (1956). Drei Formen missglűckten Daseins. Verstiegenheit,
Verschrobenheit, Manieriertheit. Trans. in part 1987 in The clinical
roots of the schizophrenie concept (ed. J. Cutting and M. Shepherd),
pp 83-8 . Cambridge University Press.
Binswanger, L. (1957) Schizophrenie. Neske, Pfullingen.
Binswanger, L. (1960). Melancholie und Manie. Neske, Pfullingen.
Binswanger, L. (1965). Wahn. Neske, Pfullingen.
Blankenburg, W. (1958). Daseinsanalytische Studie űber einem Fall
paranoider Schizophrenie. Schweizer Archiv fűr Neurologie und
Psychiatrie, 81, 9-105.
80
Blankenburg, W. (1965 a). Die Verselbstständigung eines Themas zum
Wahn. Jahrbuch fűr Psychologie, Psychotherapie und medizinische
Anthropologie, 13, 137-64.
Blankenburg, W. (1965 b). Zur Differentialphänomenologie der
Wahnwahrnehmung. Nervenarzt, 36, 285-98.
Blankenburg, W. (1969). Ansätze zu einer Psychopathologie des ‘common
sense’. Confinia Psychiatrire, 12, 144-63.
Blankenburg, W. (1971). Der Verlust der natűrlichen
Selbstverständlichkeit. Enke, Stuttgart.
Boss, M. (1957). Psychoanalyse und Daseinsanalytik. Huber, Berne.
Callieri, B., Castellani, A, and Vincenis, G, de (1972). Lineamenti di
une psicopatologie fenomenologica. Il Pensiero Scientifico, Rome.
Cutting, J. and Shepherd, M. (1987). The clinical roots of the schizophrenia
concept. Cambridge University Press.
81
De Clérambault, G.G. (1942). Les psychoses passionelles. Trans. 1987 in
The clinical roots of the schizophrenia concept. (ed. J. Cutting and M.
Shepherd), pp 182-5. Cambridge University Press.
Glatzel, J. (1973). Endogene Depression. Thieme, Stuttgart.
Hafner, H. (1963). Prozess und Entwicklung als Grundbegriffe der
Psychologie. Fortschritte der Neurologie und Psychiatrie, 31,
393-438.
Heidegger, M. (1927). Sein und Zeit. Trans. 1962 as Being and Time. Basil
Blackwell, Oxford.
Husserl, E. (1913). Ideen I. Trans. 1941 as Ideas. Macmillan, New York.
Husserl, E. (1954). Die Krisis der europaischen Wissenschaften und die
transzendentale Phänomenologie. Trans. 1970 as The crisis of
European sciences and transcendental phenomenology. Northwestern
Universities Press, Evanston.
82
Jaspers, K. (1913). Allgemeine Psychopathologie. 7th edn. trans. 1963 as
General psychopathology. Manchester University Press.
Kisker, K.P. (1970). Dialogik der Verrűcktheit. Nijhoff, La Haye.
Kuhn, R. (1952). Daseinsanalytische Studie űber die Bedeutung von
Grenzen im Wahn. Monatsschrift fűr die Psychiatrie und Neurologie,
124, 354-83.
Kulenkampff, C. (1956). Erblicken und Erblickt-werden. Nervenarzt, 27,
2-12.
Maldiney, H. (1976). Psychose et présence. Revue de Métaphysique et
Morale, 81, 513-65.
Minkowski, E. (1927). La schizophrénie. Trans. in part in The clinical
roots of the schizophrenia concept (eds. J. Cutting and M. Shepherd),
pp 188-212. Cambridge University Press.
83
Minkowski, E. (1933). Le temps vécu. Trans. 1970 as Lived time.
Northwestern University Press, Evanston.
Scheler, M. (1913-1916). Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die materiale
Wertethik. Trans. 1973 as Formalism in ethics and non-formal ethics
of values. Northwestern University Press, Evanston.
Schneider, K. (1920). Die Schichtung des emotionalen Lebens und der
Aufbau der Depressionszustande. Zeitschrift fűr die gesamte
Neurologie und Psychiatrie, 59, 218-6.
Schulte, W. (1961). Nicht-traurig-sein-Kőnnen im Kern melancholischer
Erlebens. Nervenarzt, 32, 314-20.
Storch, A. (1965). Wege zur Welt und Existenz der Geisteskranken.
Hippocrates, Stuttgart.
Straus, E. (1960). Psychologie der menschlichen Welt. Gesammelte
Schriften. Springer, Berlin.
84
Szilasi, W. (1959). Einfűhrung in die Phänomenologie Edmund Husserls.
Niemeyer, Tűbingen.
Tellenbach, H. (1974). Melancholie. 2nd edn. Springer, Berlin.
Tellenbach, H. (1975). Die Begrundung psychiatrischer Erfahrung und
psychiatrischer Methoden in philosophischen Konzeptionen von
Wesen des Menschen. In Neue Anthropologie (ed. G. Gadamer
and P. Vogler), pp 138-81. Thieme, Stuttgart.
Von Baeyer, W. and Griffith, R. (1966). Conditio humana. Springer,
Berlin.
Von Gebsattel, V.E. (1954). Prolegomena einer medizinischen
Anthropologia. Springer, Berlin.
Weitbrecht, H.J. (1966). Die heutige Diskussion űber das Wesen der
endogenenen Psychosen. Fortschritte der Neurologie und
Psychiatric, 34, 161-75.
85
Wyrsch, J. (1949). La personne du schizophrène. P.U.F, Paris.
Zutt, J. (1963). Auf dem Weg zu einer anthropologischen Psychiatrie.
Springer, Berlin.
Zutt, J, and Kulenkampff, C. (1958). Das paranoide Syndrom in
anthropologischer Sicht. Springer, Berlin.
Copyright of this book returned to the author after it went out of print.
The author has died and we have been unable to contact proxies. We
trust the author would have approved the educational use of this
translation of his work.
Maudsley Philosophy Group
Viel mehr als nur Dokumente.
Entdecken, was Scribd alles zu bieten hat, inklusive Bücher und Hörbücher von großen Verlagen.
Jederzeit kündbar.