net/publication/235325095
CITATIONS READS
37 582
1 author:
Gerard Steen
University of Amsterdam
126 PUBLICATIONS 2,394 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
NWO Visitor Grant 'Resistance: Risk and Responsibility' (ResRisRes) View project
All content following this page was uploaded by Gerard Steen on 14 January 2015.
Abstract
Recent interest in the nature of deliberate metaphor has demonstrated the need for a three-
dimensional model of metaphor. Metaphor is not just a matter of language and thought, but also
of communication. How can this starting point be connected with a discourse-psychological
framework for metaphor in which it is assumed that people have to represent metaphor as part
of a number of complementary mental models for discourse? And how can this discourse-
analytical approach be formalized in the five-step method for metaphor analysis going from
language to thought: Can this method be adjusted to cater to the formal analysis of metaphor in
communication as well, so that a distinction can be made between deliberate and non-deliberate
metaphor in the five-step method? These are the questions addressed in this article.
Das jüngste Interesse an der bewusst eingesetzten, gezielten Metapher hat die Notwendigkeit
eines dreidimensionalen Metaphernmodells verdeutlicht. Metaphern sind nicht nur eine Ange-
legenheit von Sprache und Kognition, sondern auch für die Kommunikation. Dieser Beitrag
möchte folgende, sich aus diesen Voraussetzungen ergebene Fragen beantworten: Wie lässt sich
dieser Standpunkt verbinden mit einem diskurs-psychologischen Ansatz, in dem vorausgesetzt
wird, dass man sich die Metapher als einen Teilbereich komplementärer, im Diskurs aktivierter
mentaler Modelle vorstellen soll? Und wie kann dieser diskursanalytische Ansatz in einem fünf-
schrittigen Modell, das die sprachliche und kognitive Ebene umschließt, formalisiert werden?
Kann dieses Modell auch die kommunikativen Dimensionen erfassen, so dass klar zwischen ge-
zielter und ‚ungezielter’ Metaphernverwendung unterschieden werden kann?
1. Introduction
Some metaphors are used deliberately as metaphors, whereas most metaphors
are not. When Shakespeare asks, ‘Shall I compare thee to a summer’s day?’, he is
entertaining the thought whether or not he will set up a metaphorical comparison
between his beloved addressee and a summer’s day. In other words, he is attend-
ing to metaphor as metaphor and is about to make a decision about his intentions
for his next move: ‘Thou art more lovely and more temperate’.
It is true, of course, that we are not talking about the real Shakespeare but about
his persona in the sonnet cycle. Yet this is a well-known example that can easily
83
metaphorik.de 21/2011
stand for what can happen in regular language use. Examples of deliberate meta-
phor from real life may be found in the language of politicians, instructors, sports
commentators, and so on (Charteris-Black, 2004; Cameron, 2003; Beger, 2011).
Deliberate metaphors differ from non-deliberate metaphors in that they involve
mandatory attention to the fact that they are metaphorical. This is not meant to
imply that addressees have to be able to label a metaphor as a metaphor for it to
count as deliberate, though. That is a metalinguistic skill that is irrelevant. In my
view, a metaphor is deliberate when addressees must pay attention to the source
domain as an independent conceptual domain (or space or category) that they are
instructed to use to think about the target of the metaphor.
Deliberate metaphors are constructed in such a way that the sender invites or
sometimes even instructs the addressee to in fact set up a cross-domain mapping
in their mental representation of the discourse in order to view one thing in terms
of something else. Consider famous Dutch football coach Rinus Michels who said
´Football is war´. His utterance was intended as an invitation for his audience to
pay attention to football from the independent standpoint of war, and to draw
relevant conclusions (implicatures) from that figurative comparison. Deliberate
metaphors are perspective changers.
This is not what happens with non-deliberate metaphor. For instance when peo-
ple talk about arguments in terms of war or life in terms of a journey, they do not
necessarily have to attend to the difference as well as relation between the two
respective domains that may be distinguished in semantic and conceptual struc-
tures by cognitive linguists and other metaphor analysts. An utterance like
´Lakoff attacked Glucksberg´ is typically meant to be understood as an utterance
involving just one conceptual domain, the target domain of academic debate.
Neither the sender nor the addressee is supposed to pay any attention to any is-
sues that are related to physical fighting and war as they are representing this ut-
terance as part of the meaning of the discourse. Even if they continue to talk
about argument in terms of war, this does not necessarily mean that they activate
their knowledge about war in order to think and talk about debates. They may
just employ polysemous words that are conventionally used to talk about de-
bates; these may in the past have been metaphorically derived from the domain
84
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
of war, but it is quite possible that at present they may have lost that connection
in people’s individual minds.
The possibility that a lot of metaphor may be processed non-metaphorically con-
stitutes a paradox (Steen 2008). To some it has raised the question whether ‘La-
koff attacked Glucksberg’ can even count as metaphorical. I think it does, for it is
still possible that the source domain of fighting or war is activated in the proc-
esses preceding the representation of the sentence in working memory, as has
been vociferously contended by cognitive linguists and as may be supported by a
range of experimental studies (Gibbs 2011a and c). If we abide by the conceptual
definition of metaphor as a cross-domain mapping, linguistic expressions such as
‘Lakoff attacked Glucksberg’ have to be kept on board as potentially metaphori-
cal, since they may evoke some form of mapping across conceptual domains.
However, the processes leading up to the product of metaphor comprehension in
working memory (or attention) are a separate issue that are largely immaterial to
the question of whether their product counts as a deliberate metaphor or not—I
will argue here the latter issue turns on attending to the source domain as part of
the represented meaning of the utterance.
The distinction between deliberate and non-deliberate metaphor is controversial.
In a recent exchange, an attempt was made by Gibbs (2011a), Steen (2011a), Deig-
nan (2011), Müller (2011) and Gibbs (2011b) to clarify what it means to call a me-
taphor deliberate or non-deliberate. As a result of that exchange I now hold that
deliberate metaphor is not necessarily the same as conscious metaphor (Steen
2011a): I propose that deliberate metaphor gets represented as metaphor in atten-
tion, and that it thereby affords conscious metaphorical cognition, but that con-
scious metaphorical cognition does not necessarily have to occur (Steen in press).
Also, deliberate metaphor should not be conflated with novel metaphor, non-
deliberate metaphor being conflated with conventional metaphor: conventional
metaphor can also be used deliberately, as happens when newspaper headlines
use conventional metaphors deliberately for the purpose of punning and humor
and drawing the attention of the reader. At the same time, though, there still re-
main many questions about deliberate metaphor, for instance the possible asym-
metry between production and reception: a metaphor may be deliberately pro-
duced as a metaphor but not received as one, or, the other way around, a meta-
85
metaphorik.de 21/2011
phor may have been produced non-deliberately as a metaphor but still be re-
ceived as a cross-domain comparison by the interlocutor or audience. Careful
theoretical and empirical work will have to elaborate how the notion of deliberate
metaphor can be conceived of in these contexts.
Deliberate metaphor therefore has two kinds of values: firstly, it is a special kind
of metaphor use which has its particular values to language users, in that it
draws their attention to the perspective of the source domain; and secondly, it is a
special kind of phenomenon which has its particular values to practitioners of the
academic study of metaphor, in that it reveals that metaphor is not just a matter
of language and thought but also of communication. In this paper I would like to
try and demonstrate both kinds of values. I will begin with the empirical and
theoretical issues that have to do with deliberate metaphor as a specific part of
discourse: I argue that deliberate versus non-deliberate metaphor is an issue of
communication, which is an independent dimension of metaphor in discourse
next to the ones of metaphor in thought and metaphor in language (Steen 2008
and 2011b). Then I will continue with a theoretical exploration of the way in
which metaphor can be analyzed by means of a five-step method for analysis I
proposed some time ago (Steen 1999a; Steen 2009; Dorst 2011; Krennmayr 2011): I
will reinterpret and adjust the five-step method for the purpose of catering to the
distinction between non-deliberate versus deliberate metaphor, and tie this back
to the three dimensions of metaphor that can be distinguished in discourse. My
main claim is that deliberate metaphor has been unduly ignored and that it raises
fundamental and new questions about structures, functions and processes of fig-
uration in discourse, but also about the ways these have been studied.
86
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
87
metaphorik.de 21/2011
The surface text captures the linguistic dimension, the text base and situation
model, the conceptual dimension, and the context model the communicative di-
mension of metaphor. Empirical research has shown that language users need to
construct at least parts of these distinct types of mental representations during
language use processes to be successful in their communicative behavior (Mac-
namara and Magliano 2009; Graesser and Millis 2011).
Metaphor can be connected to this multi-level approach to the psychology of dis-
course processing in two ways. I have collected behavioral data which show that
aspects of metaphor processing can be usefully interpreted with reference to the
distinct mental models for discourse processing (Steen 1994; Steen 2004 and Steen
2006). For instance, I asked participants to rate metaphors from Bob Dylan’s song
‘Hurricane’ on a number of scales for affective value, and found that the same
metaphors received different scores on these scales when presented as linguistic
expressions versus depictions of a situation versus messages between interlocu-
tors (Steen 2004). I believe that these three types of presentation are the three ba-
sic dimensions of all metaphor use (Steen 1994; Steen 1999b and Steen 2008). In
this particular empirical study, they were meant to be associated with the psy-
chological representation of metaphor in a surface text, a situation model, and a
context model, respectively. It hence seems possible to experimentally distinguish
between the various complementary roles metaphors can play during discourse
processing.
The second way in which metaphor can be connected to the multi-level approach
to discourse processing is formal instead of behavioral. I developed a formal
framework for metaphor analysis which includes five separate analytical steps
for the distinct representation formats of metaphor in the multi-level representa-
tion of metaphor in discourse (Steen 1999a; Steen 2009). This approach can show
how one metaphorical utterance can be analyzed as a potential part of the surface
text, the text base, the situation model, and the context model. The latter aspect,
metaphor as part of the context model, is a recently developed interpretation of
the five-step method, which I will illustrate below, and is closely related to the
value of deliberate metaphor.
88
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
Before we can demonstrate the five-step method, however, let us first examine
the more general connection between metaphor and discourse, involving the
three dimensions of language, thought and communication, and do so by looking
at deliberate metaphor. Consider the following data from Beger (2011). It is an ex-
cerpt from a university lecture on the nature of aggression as treated by a hy-
draulic model developed by Konrad Lorenz. Potentially deliberate metaphors
have been identified by Beger and presented in italic and bold print:
“But think about this tank of water as the reservoir within your soul, that
aggressive impulses are dripping into. Little hassles and frustrations of
day-today life keep adding new bits of aggressive impulses to who you are.
And as this tank fills up, the pressure of the weight of these impulses be-
comes stronger and stronger and they push on this plug that keeps it bot-
tled up. Now, you don’t behave aggressively, until all this stuff kind of ex-
plodes and comes shooting out of you. And the weight – and there’s two
different factors here. One of the factors in this model as to whether you
become aggressive or not, is the weight of the water in the tank – or the
amount of aggression that’s piling up. Because as that gets deeper and dee-
per, and heavier and heavier, there is more pressure for it to come out. But
at the other end, there are stimuli out there in the world that you might be
exposed to – aggression-eliciting stimuli, aggressive models, and what
have you, that will be pulling on the plug from the other end. So, if you got
a situation where there is a lot of aggression in there, and just the right
things pulling on the plug from the other end, according to the hydraulic
model, you’re setting the stage for these aggressive urges to come pouring
out.”
All of these utterances have to be represented by readers or listeners as part of
their developing surface text, text base, situation model and context model. Im-
pressionistically, this would lead to a representation of each utterance as, respec-
tively, a lexico-grammatical structure, a proposition, a depiction of the referents
in some state of affairs, and a representation of the position of the utterance in the
on-going discourse between the sender and the addressee in some concrete situa-
tion. These postulated mental representations can be formally modeled by dis-
89
metaphorik.de 21/2011
90
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
present purposes, these differences of detail do not affect the substance of my ar-
gument. What is important to point out, though, is that surface text and text base
show that, in discourse, language and thought are connected but not identical.
For instance, the relative pronoun ‘that’ in the surface text is represented by the
recoverable concept RESERVOIR in the text base in order to display the true con-
ceptual structure of the discourse in the text base: there is a distinction between
linguistic and conceptual structures.
Moving from the text base to the situation model involves the transition from ac-
tivated concepts to the referents they designate in the projected text world, which
is another way of looking at metaphor in thought than that which occurs for the
text base. We shall later see that, precisely for metaphor, activated concepts and
designated referents do not display a one-on-one relation either, just as with lin-
guistic and conceptual structures in surface text and text base. In order to make
this differentiation clearly visible, my impressionistic account of the first sentence
and its referential representation in the situation model would be something like
this:
‘the addressee has to think about a tank of water as a reservoir within the
soul, and aggressive impulses drip into that reservoir’
This may be paraphrased more felicitously and more elaborately, but that would
already involve some form of enrichment. The present formulation is intended to
capture the entities, relationships and attributes that must figure in the situation
model if the addressee has successfully processed the first sentence. These are the
elements of discourse that the addressee must attend to in working memory and
these are the elements of discourse that are part of the referential representation
of the first sentence.
The distinction between surface text, text base and situation model can be seen as
a reflection at the level of discourse analysis of the generally accepted semiotic
distinction between symbol, concept, and referent. The referential representation
of discourse in a situation model has received a lot of attention in discourse psy-
chology. By comparison, the context model has remained somewhat in the back-
ground, its theoretical and empirical development remaining sketchy (Van Dijk
2008). Effects of constructing a context model have been concerned with, for in-
91
metaphorik.de 21/2011
92
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
93
metaphorik.de 21/2011
Table 1
Five-step analysis of ‘Lakoff attacked Glucksberg’
Steps Analysis
possible inferences:
ARGUMENTS < WEAPONS
Table 1 offers an overview of this five-step analysis of the metaphor ‘Lakoff at-
tacked Glucksberg’. Step 1 involves the identification of any metaphor-related
words in a stretch of text. In our case, the word attack is seen as a potential ex-
pression of an underlying metaphorical mapping; what the mapping is, does not
94
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
95
metaphorik.de 21/2011
and presupposed concepts for target and source, respectively. Note that when the
open slots in the frames are filled out, in step 4, they are functionally equivalent
to the source and target mental spaces used in Blending Theory (Fauconnier and
Turner 1998); nothing depends on their formulation as propositions in the pre-
sent approach, these are just convenient and maximally precise and explicit forms
of notation (Kintsch, 1998).
As soon as the open comparison has been generated by step 3, its completion by
the insertion of new concepts in each of the two frames in step 4 is a natural con-
sequence. The idea is that there is an academic context in which Lakoff does
something to Glucksberg which may be compared with attacking, and conven-
tionally this will be interpreted as strongly criticizing; this gives us an interpreta-
tion for the open slot F. This is even the conventionally metaphorical meaning of
the verb to attack in the dictionary (on the systematic use of dictionaries for this
analysis, see Krennmayr 2008). Conversely, the action of attacking entails two
open slots a and b and these can be filled by an attacker and an attacked. Filling
out the open slots in the two propositions is therefore not highly problematic, in
this instance. And again, representing this analogy in a propositional format is
not meant to suggest any a priori preference for propositions over other forms of
representation, including, for instance, image-schemas and so on—these are em-
pirical issues for behavioral research.
Step 5 then turns the analogy produced in step 4 into a differently ordered map-
ping according to the format popularized by cognitive linguists. It takes each of
the correspondences projected by the analogy of step 4 as separate entities and
lines them up as a list of entailments. This also enables the explication of other
possible entailments that are implied by the analogy, such as the presumable cor-
respondence between words or arguments on the one hand and weapons or for
instance fists on the other. The fact that these have not been explicitly given in the
text, however, changes the status of this part of the analysis.
Table 1 labels the five steps with the appropriate cognitive-scientific terms. It uses
‘metaphor-related’ for reasons that have been explained in Steen et al. (2010) and
to which we will return to below. And it shows how the most likely label of the
cross-domain mapping found in the present utterance would be CRITICISM IS
96
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
97
metaphorik.de 21/2011
98
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
Table 2
Five-step analysis of ‘think about the water tank as a reservoir within the soul …’
Steps Analysis
Text But think about this tank of water as the reservoir within your
soul, that aggressive impulses are dripping into
1. Identification of About this tank of water as …reservoir within … that … drip-
metaphor-related ping into
words
2. Identification of P1 (BUTt S0 S1)
metaphor-related P2 (THINK-ABOUTt ADDRESSEEt TANKs)
propositions P3 (ASt TANKs RESERVOIRs,t)
P4 (OFs TANKs WATERs)
P5 (WITHINs RESERVOIRs,t SOULt)
P6 (DRIP-INTOs IMPULSESt RESERVOIRs,t)
P7 (MODt IMPULSESt AGGRESSIVEt)
3. Identification of SIM (THINK-ABOUT TARGET AS-SOURCE) { F, a, y
open metaphorical [F (IMPULSES[AGGRESSIVE], ‘RESERVOIR’[WITHIN-SOUL])]t
comparison [DRIP-INTO (x, TANK-AS-RESERVOIR[WITHIN-y]])]s}
4. Identification of SIM (THINK-ABOUT TARGET AS-SOURCE)
analogical struc- { [ADD-TO (IMPULSES[AGGRESSIVE], ‘RESERVOIR’[WITHIN-SOUL])]t
ture [DRIP-INTO (WATER, TANK-AS-RESERVOIR[WITHIN-ECOSYSTEM])]s}
5. Identification of TARGET < SOURCE DOMAIN
cross-domain ADD-TO < DRIP-INTO
mapping IMPULSES[AGGRESSIVE] < WATER
‘RESERVOIR’[WITHIN-SOUL] < TANK-AS-RESERVOIR[WITHIN-
ECOSYSTEM]
99
metaphorik.de 21/2011
(A similar point can be made about impulse, which I am going to ignore for the
sake of simplicity too.)
There is, however, another interpretation of reservoir, which is equally plausible
and which would preserve its concrete meaning while simultaneously utilizing
the abstract meaning. It would make reservoir ambiguous between a synonym for
tank on the one hand and an abstract metaphorical interpretation or replacement
of tank for some property of the soul on the other. Such double uses of words in
metaphorical contexts have been labeled as ‘bridge terms’ by Kittay (1987). This
interpretation can be motivated by discourse-analytical considerations in which
the professor has to move from the prior introduction of the source domain ele-
ment of the water tank as a local topic in its own right to its use as a means to
think about the true topic of the lecture, aggression: the double, ambiguous use of
reservoir as both a kind of natural container for water as well as an abstract con-
tainer for emotions embodies a natural transition between the two discourse top-
ics. This can be transparently shown in the five-step analysis (see Table 2). The
fact that the same utterance can be given more than one interpretation is of
course a given in discourse analysis and should not be seen as an issue for the
five-step method, as long as it can represent both options and spell out what their
implications are; since my present argument is not concerned with these issues, I
will leave the comparison between the two alternative interpretations aside.
100
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
101
metaphorik.de 21/2011
to elements of the source domain, both in steps 3 and 4, which should be visible
in addressees’ construction of the situation model.
This is where the difference between deliberate and non-deliberate begins to af-
fect the five-step method and reveals new opportunities for its use. We have just
taken steps 3 and 4 as a representation of the situation model and argued that, for
deliberate metaphor, the situation model should contain source domain elements
or even a complete source domain proposition, next to the target domain propo-
sition which reflects the topic of the metaphor in terms of the encompassing dis-
course. To be concrete, the situation model for the water tank sentence should
comprise a referential picture of the soul having some abstract reservoir in which
aggressive impulses accumulate, this picture being seen as at least partly analo-
gous to something dripping into a water tank which acts as a natural reservoir.
With non-deliberate metaphor, this is different. When addressees derive ‘Lakoff
criticized Glucksberg’ in step 4 (assuming that this is what they do), they can rep-
resent what they need. They do not need to represent the source domain ele-
ments or complete proposition, ‘the attacker attacked the attackee’, as another,
analogous part of their developing situation model. Indeed, it has been the claim
of cognitive linguistics that people typically do not attend to the cross-domain
mapping in attention; instead, they construct the mapping before then, in order to
arrive at the intended target domain meaning which would be in their attention,
in the form of the referential representation ‘Lakoff criticized Glucksberg’.
For non-deliberate metaphors, therefore, we might have to indicate that it is only
the top proposition in step 4, the target domain proposition, which gets repre-
sented in people’s situation models. The bottom proposition, representing the
source domain analogue, might somehow play a part in the processes leading up
to the product of comprehension in working memory, but presumably does not
end up there itself. It should not be part of the situation model for non-deliberate
metaphors. For deliberate metaphors, the source domain proposition should at
least partly be included in the situation model. These are testable claims which
we are currently undertaking to investigate in our lab.
102
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
103
metaphorik.de 21/2011
model might read something like ‘the sender is informing the addressee that La-
koff criticized Glucksberg in order to add this event to a developing account’, for
instance one in which the sender himself is either praising or criticizing Lakoff.
In other words, I am suggesting that there may be a close and differential connec-
tion between the output of step 4 for non-deliberate versus deliberate metaphors
on the one hand and the content of the context model on the other hand: if ele-
ments of the source domain are represented as such and hence presumably at-
tended to in the situation model, as is the case with deliberate metaphor, then
they constitute a case of discourse incongruity which can be represented as such
in the context model as well; if elements of the source domain are not represented
as such and hence presumably not attended to in the situation model, as is the
case with non-deliberate metaphor, then they do not constitute a case of dis-
course incongruity and do not get represented as such in the context model ei-
ther. The function of such an analysis would be to explain why some metaphors
raise questions as to their use and point, whereas others do not. If the context
model displays a representation like the one for the water tank above, this affords
a platform for wondering about the rhetorical aim of the sender as well as the
means and success of his action. If the context model only say something like ‘the
sender is informing the addressee that Lakoff criticized Glucksberg in order to
add this event to a developing account’, then there is no ground in the context
model for continuing with paying any sort of attention to what technically and
perhaps subconsciously is a metaphor. Again, my think aloud data for under-
standing metaphor in literary versus journalistic text processing (Steen 1994)
clearly showed signs of the possibility of these processes, but in just one out of
about five to six cases of metaphor—these may have been the deliberate ones,
and we are now preparing to address this issue head-on.
In sum, the five-step method may be closely aligned with the various mental rep-
resentations that people are assumed to make during discourse processing. The
discovery of deliberate metaphor as an important manifestation of the communi-
cative dimension of metaphor in discourse pointed out that the context model
might be more important for the five step method than originally realized. In-
deed, it now looks as if the content of the context model may be partly dependent
on the representation of metaphor in step 4, which captures the situation model.
104
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
This became particularly clear when we looked at the difference between non-
deliberate versus deliberate metaphor, which revealed that the crucial issue there
may have to do with the presence or absence of the source domain in the situa-
tion model (step 4). If the source domain is part of what is attended to in the situ-
ation model, as is the case for deliberate metaphor, then it may give rise to a con-
text model for metaphor that pays attention to metaphor as metaphor, since there
is some form of discourse incongruity in the situation model; if the source do-
main is not part of the situation model, as is the case for non-deliberate metaphor,
then there is no ground for this to occur.
105
metaphorik.de 21/2011
deliberate, but we might even want to treat this as a post-hoc effect on the part of
the recipient, which would make this proposal compatible with some of the ar-
guments advanced by Gibbs (2011a; Gibbs 2011 b). How all of this might work
for production would be a rather different affair, and how this would be affected
by using different media of communication (speech versus writing) would have
to be examined as well. These are challenges that are more general for all meta-
phor research.
The second suggestion would be to take more seriously the possibility that many
metaphors are so conventionalized that they may not give rise to activation of
source domain concepts or cross-domain mappings. Thus, even though step 1
would show that attack in ‘Lakoff attacked Glucksberg’ is linguistically meta-
phorical (Steen et al. 2010), this might still be argued to lead to fast lexical disam-
biguation and immediate activation of the appropriate target domain concept
ATTACK in the sense of ‘criticize’ by the addressee. If that were to happen, the text
base would not show any source domain concepts that would require incongru-
ity resolution by triggering step 3, for it would simply say ATTACK* LAKOFF
GLUCKSBERG, the star indicating that we are dealing with the metaphorical con-
cept ‘attack’ (Glucksberg and Haught 2006). Instead, we would immediately pro-
ceed to step 4, which would only have a target domain representation of the sen-
tence, in the form of ‘Lakoff attacked* Glucksberg’, and there would be no issue
about the presence or absence of source domain concepts and referents.
Even if lexical disambiguation would allow for the activation of both concrete
and abstract versions of the concept ATTACK in the text base, this might still allow
for a process of suppression of the irrelevant source domain concepts that is fast
enough to prevent the start of any sort of mapping. The potential conceptual in-
congruity between source and target domain concepts might then be gone before
it can trigger a resolution process. This could happen with most conventional me-
taphors that are not revitalized as metaphors in deliberate use (Giora 2003, Giora
2008).
Note that this implies that the representation of ATTACK as a source domain con-
cept in Table 1 above represents just one possibility. It was chosen in order to re-
flect the assumptions of cognitive linguistics, in order to spell out the conse-
106
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
References
Beger, Anke (2011): “Deliberate metaphors? An exploration of the choice and
functions of metaphors in US-American college lectures”, in: metaphorik.de
20, 39-60.
Bowdle, Brian F., & Gentner, Dedre (2005): “The career of metaphor”, in: Psycho-
logical Review, 112(1), 193-216.
Butler, Chris (2003): Structure and function: A guide to three major structural-
functional theories. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Cameron, Lynne (2003): Metaphor in educational discourse. London and New York:
Continuum.
Charteris-Black, Jonathan (2004): Corpus approaches to critical metaphor analysis.
London: Palgrave MacMillan.
Charteris-Black, Jonathan/ Musolff, Andreas (2003): “'Battered Hero' or 'Innocent
Victim'? A comparative study of metaphors for euro trading in British and
German financial reporting”, in: English for Specific Purposes, 22, 153-176.
Deignan, Alice (2011): “Deliberateness is not unique to metaphor: A response to
Gibbs”, in: Metaphor and the Social World 1(1), 67-69.
Dorst, Aletta G. (2011): “Personification in discourse: linguistic forms, conceptual
structures and communicative functions”, in: Language and Literature 20(2),
113-135.
Fauconnier, Gilles/Turner, Mark (1998): “Conceptual integration networks”, in:
Cognitive Science 22, 133-187.
107
metaphorik.de 21/2011
108
Steen, The value of deliberate metaphor
109
metaphorik.de 21/2011
110