Sie sind auf Seite 1von 19

ARCHIVES AHDlMA66(J999) 189-224

'"
D'HISTOIRE DOCTRINALE ET LmERAIRE
DU
MOYEN AGE
Tome 66 - ANNEE 1999

SOMMAlRE THEDISTINCTION BETWEEN NATURE ANDWILL


IN DUNSSCOTUS
In memoriam Andre Yernet (1910-1999) .. 7

ETUDES DOCfRlNALES ET LlTI'ERAIRES par Tobias HOFFMANN


Marc GEOFFROY. L'almohadisme theologique d'Averroes (Ibn Ruffd)........... 9-47 Universitat Bonn, Philosophisches Seminar,
Lehr- undForschungsbereichII, Am Hof 1, 0-53113 Bonn
James R. GINTHER. A scholastic idea of the Church: Robert Grosseteste's
Exposition ofPsalm 86 49-72
Jose Ricardo PIERPAULI. Die praktische Yemunft als vis ordinativa. Albert
Resume
und Thomas im Vergleich 73-87
Dans la pensee de Duns Scot, la repartition des puissances actives entre
Guido ALLINEY. «De centro in circumferentia ». Metafore spaziali del
volonte et nature devient un des fondements de son systeme. Elle differencie une
rapporto tempo-etemita in Tomasso d'Aquino , ,......... 89-120
causalite libre et auto-determinante d'une causalite naturelle et necessaire. Get
Jakob H. J. SCHNEIDER. The Eternity of the World. Thomas Aquinas and article essaie de montrer dans quelle mesure cette distinction fonde en grande
Boethius ofDacia 121-141 partie la psychologle, la doctrine morale, la metaphysique et la theologie de Duns
Michael SWEENEY. Soul as Substance and Method in Aquinas' Scot.
Anthropological Writings 143-187
Tobias HOFFMANN. The Distinction between Nature and Will in Duns Abstract
Scotus...................................................................................................... 189-224 In the thought ofDuns Scotus, the distinction ofactive potencies into will and
Giorgio PlNI. Duns Scotus' Commentary on the Topics: New light on his nature takes on a fundamental systematic significance. It distinguishes free and
philosophical teaching............................................................................ 225-243 self-determining causality from natural and necessary causality. The purpose of
this article is to show to what extent this distinction underlies large parts ofDuns
TEXTES Scotus' psychology, ethics, metaphysics and theology.
Ludwig HODL. «Non est malitia in voluntate... », Die magistrate
Zusammenfassung
Entscheidung der PariserTheoiogen von 1285/1286 in der Diskussion Die Unterscheidung der aktiven Wirkvermiigen in Wille und Natur bekommt
des Johannes de Polliaco, Quodl. I, q. /0. Untersuchung und Edition.. 245-297 im Denken von Duns Scotus erstmals eine fundamentale systematische
Chris SCHABEL. Landulphus Caracciolo and a Sequax on Divine Bedeutung. Sie unterscheidetfreie, selbstbestimmende Kausalitdt von naturhaft-
Foreknowledge 299-343 notwendiger Kausaliuit. Dieser Artikel untersucht, inwiefern diese Unterschei-
dung weiten Teilen der scotischen Psychologic, Morallehre, Metaphysik und
Theologie zugrundeliegt.
Ouvrage publie avec le concours
du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique [Mots-des: JeanDunsScot,puissances de l' arne, volonte, natureet necessite]
PARIS
LmRAIR1E PHILOSOPHIQUE J. YRIN
6, PU\CE DE LA SORBONNE, y'
1999
190 TOBIASHOFFMANN THEDISTINCTION BETWEEN NATURE ANDWILLINDUNSSCOTUS 191

I t is generally accepted that the distinction between nature and will is crucial to
the thought of John Duns Scotus'. Until now, there has been no systematic
analysis of the role of this distinction in the work of the Subtle Doctors. In this
more emphasis on 'will' than on 'nature', it is because Duns Scotus usually
analyses this distinction in the contextofbroader discussions about the will.
The distinction between nature and will allows Scotus to characterize what he
article, my goal is to show that this distinction underlies much of Duns Scotus' considers the essential feature ofthe will : the will, being a free agent 7 , determines
psychology, ethics, metaphysics and theology. Scotus is not the first thinker who its acts by its own control, while all natural agents are determined in their action to
opposes will and nature 3, but the distinction was made more sharply in his work a specific effect, from extrinsic circumstancess, Scotus takes the will's freedom
than in any of his predecessors, and no one before him attributed such a (in contrast to natural action) to be the fundamental distinction of active potencies:
fundamental role to the distinction - a characteristic that Scotus shares with the «The will is per se never an active principle that acts naturally. To be naturally
thought ofImmanuel Kanr', active and to be freely active represents a primary division of 'active principle' »9.
Two brief preliminaries: first, in referring to Scotus' distinction between By virtue of its capacity for self-determination, the will has the unique
'nature' 5 and 'will' , I am referring in shorthand to his distinction between natural characteristic of being able to determine the intensity of its activity 10, whereas
active potencies and free active potencies 6 ; second, if this paper seems to place nature always acts according to the full extent of its power!'. Scotus further
affirms that the will is «an agent that is essentially different from anything else in
the universe» 12.
(I) A. B. Wolter lists this distinction among several characteristic and innovative features ofthe The article will proceed in five sections: section one takes up the classic
thought of Duns Scotus, cf. his dictionary article «John Duns Scotus », in R. AUDl (ed.), The
Cambridge Dictionary ofPhilosophy, Cambridge-New York, Cambridge University Press, 1995,
sources for Scotus' will/nature distinction, namely Aristotle and Augustine; it
212b-213a. suggests as well that the work of Henry of Ghent is an important inspiration for
(2) The essentials of the will/natnre distinction are clearly exposed by L. D. ROBERTS,
«Indeterminism in Duns Scotus' doctrine of human freedom», Modem Schoolman, 51 (1973),
1-16. Yet, this article does not show the implications of this distinction throughout Scotus' thought, menschliche Erkenntnisvermogen als Vol/zug von Spontaneitat und Rezeptivitat, Kevelaer, Butzon
and its textual basis is limited. und Bercker, 1998 (Veroffentlichungen der Johannes-Duns-Scotus-Akademie fur Pranziskanische
(3) Among others, Bonaventure and Thomas Aquinas already use this distinction, but it is less Geistlichkeit und Spiritualitat 7), 20-36.
fundamental in their thought than it is in Scotus. Cf. among other texts BONAVENTURE, In Sent. I d. 2 (7) In the texts presented in this article, Scorus takes the freedom of the will for granted. In his
a. un. q.4 fund. 2, Opera omnia. Quaracchi, 1882ff., I, 56b; THOMAS AQUINAS, S. c. Gent. II c.48 view, the will's freedom is manifestaposteriori, from experience, QQ. Metaph. IX q. 15 n, 30, OPh.
a.I, Leon. (Editio Leonina, Rome, I882ff.) XIIl, 376b-377a; S. theol.lq.19 a.4, Leon. IV, 237a- IV,682-683; Ord. IV d.49 suppl. q.9-lOn.lO, Vivo XXI, 333b. He also undertakes a proof of the
238b;lq.63 a.S.Leon. V, 130a-131b;Iq.82a.I,Leon. V,293ab;lq. 83 aLLeon. V, 307a-308b. freedom of the will with reference to there being contingency; yet, this is only a shift ofthe problem,
Thomas also uses the distinction between ratio and natura, as, for example, inS. theol. I-II q, I a. 2 in since then he has to prove that there is in fact contingency. Cf. n. 139.
corp., Leon. VI, 9ab. As to Henry of Ghent see below, section one. (8)Cf. Rep. III d.33 q. un. n.lO, Vivo XXIII, 514b: «nam quia voluntas habet actum et
(4) The opposition between nature and will or between nature and freedom is considered to be a determinationemactus in potestate sua, ideo potestse libere determinare ad bonum, vel ad malum.
basic distinction by KANT, Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, Kant's gesammelteSchriften, recte vel non recte.... sed non sic est determinaturn agens naturale, quod sic est determinatumex se
Prussian Academy of Sciences, Berlin, 1902-1923, IV, 387.412.428.446.455-456. For this and ad unum, quod non potest se determinare ad oppositum, et ideo licet determinetur ex se formaliter
other parallels between the thought of Scotus and Kant, A. SCBMlDT, «Scotns und Kant: Rationale per formam naturaliter inclinantem ad unum, tamen aliunde determinamr effective ... Sed voluntas
Anti-Rationalisten », Theologieund Glaube, 89 (1999), 180-218. ex se detenninatur effective». Cf. also QQ. Metaph. IX q.15 n. 22, OPh.IV, 680-681; n.43, OPh.
(5) The term 'nature' stands on the one hand for the essence ofa thing, and in this sense also the IV, 587.
will is a nature; in a more narrow sense it indicates the wayan active potency elicits its acts, namely (9)« Voluntas, per se loquendo, nunquam est principium activum naturaliter, quia esse
in a determinate way, as opposed to the self-determination ofthe will. Cf. Ord. (Ordinatio) prol, p. 1 natnraliter activum et esse libere activum sunt primae differentiae principii activi, et voluntas, unde
q. un. n. 73, Vat. (Editio Vaticana, ed. C. BALle et al., Rome, 1950ff.) I, 44-45. Cf. Rep. (Reportatioy voluntas est principium activum libere », Quodl. q, 16 n. IS, Vivo XXVI, 199a. For the English text,
I Ad. 10 q. 3, Oxford, Merton 59, fol. 68v : « ... natura accipitur uno modo communiter pro essentia see F. ALLUNTI8--A. B. WOLTER, God and Creatures: The Quodlibetal Questions, Princeton,
rei, et sic unumquodque sicut habet entitatem, ita et naturam.... Alia modo accipitur natura pro University Press, 1975,384. Cf. Ord.I d.lOq.un. n.44, Vat.IV, 358; QQ. Metaph. IXq.15 n.23,
principio naturali ut est vis quaedam productiva ct sirnilis ex simili, et hoc vi productionis suae, et OPh. IV, 681.
isto modo producitur Filius in divinis natura vel naturaliter, qua ex vi productionis suae procedit ut (10) Lect. (Lectura) I d.I p.2 q.2 n.98, Vat. XVI, 94: « ... quidquid agit necessario, agit
simms ex simili in natura». Cf. Quodl. q.16 n.13, Vivo (Editio Wadding-Vives, Paris 1891-1895) secundum ultimum suae potentiae ; si igitur voluntas necessario ferretur in ultimum finem in
XXVI,197b. universali, igitur secundum ultimum suae potentiae, et per consequens non aliquando remissius et
(6) Scotus distinguishes between potency as a mode of being and as a principle of being, aliquando intensius ferretur in illud, sed semper uniformiter, quod falsum est », Cf. Ord. I d. 1 p. 1
QQ. Metaph. (Quaestiones super libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelisy IX q.I-2 n.14, OPh. (Opera q.1 n.22, Vat. II, 16; Ord.1 d.l p.2 q. 2 n, 133 (deleted text), Vat. II, 88-89. Cf. also W.HOERES,
philosophica, ed, G.l.ETZKORN et al., St.Bonaventure, 1997ff.) IV, 512. Potency as a mode of Der Wille als reine Yollkommenheit nach Duns Scotus, Munich, Anton Pustet, 1962 (Salzburger
being can be understood in different ways: I. as what is opposed to the impossible, 2. in opposition Studien zur Philosophie 1),240.
to necessity, 3. in opposition to the act, QQ. Metaph. IX q. 1-2 n. 21, OPh. IV, 515. As a principle of (11) Ord. Ld, 8 p. 2q. un. n. 286, Vat. IV, 315: «causa necessario agens agit secundumultimum
being, potency is divided into active potencies and passive potencies, QQ. Metaph. IX q. 3-4 n. 29, potentiae suae, quia sicut non est in potestate eius agerc et non agere, ita nee intense agere et
OPh. IV, 548. A passive potency is something that can receive a determining fonn, whereas an remisse».Cf.Ord.ld. J p. 2q. 2n. 95. Vat.H, 72; Lect. Hd. 12q. un.n.16, Vat. XIX, 74.
active potency has some sort of efficient causality, QQ. Metaph. IX q. 3-4 n. 29-30, OPh. IV, 548- (12)« Voluntas estagens alterins rationis a toto quod est in universo". Leet. II d. 25 q. nn. n. 93,
549. Cf. G. PIzzO, Intellectus und memoria nach der Lehre des Johannes Duns Scotus: Das Vat.XIX,261.
192 TOBIAS HOFFMANN THEDISTINCTION BETWEEN NATUREANDW1LLlN DUNSSCOTUS 193

Scotus' teaching on this issue; section two outlines Scorns' sharp contrast very explicit 15. Scotus bases his argument on his reading of the second book of
between will as self-determined and nature as determined, with special emphasis Aristotle's Physics and the ninth book of the Metaphysics. The Subtle Doctor
on psychological implications 13; section three discusses the influence of this discusses the passage where Aristotle is analyzing the relationship between
distinction for Scotus' ethics, referring specifically to his distinction between the chance (to «mOI.la.tOV) and intention (f1 tUXTl) in relation to thefour causes:
will's affection for what is just in itself (affectio iustitiaey as opposed to the Of things that come to be, some come to be for the sake of something [evEKll
affection for what is of the subject's own interest (affectio commodi) ; section four 'tou], others not. Again, some of the former class are in accordance with
analyses Scotus' view of God's activity ad extra, i.e. towards creatures, intention, others not... Things that are for the sake of something include
emphasizing Scotus' account of contingency; finally, section five discusses how whatever may be done as a result of thought [f:l.1ti:J otavoioo;] or of nature [uno
the will/nature distinction affects Scotus' account of God's activity ad intra, i. e. CPUO'EOl~]l6 .
the Trinitarian productions, namely the distinction between the way in which the
Here, Scotus interprets Aristotle as claiming that intellect and nature are
Son is naturally generated by the Father and the way in which the Holy Spirit
essentially different active principles 17. According to Scotus, Aristotle reduces
proceeds freely from the Father and the Son.
intentional causality and chance causality, both of which are considered as
accidental causes, to intellect and nature, respectively, as being their per se
causes 18. Thereafter, Aristotle's distinction between intellect and nature is
I.DUNsSCOTUS'SOURCES transformed by Scotns into a distinction between will and nature :
When it is argued, with reference to the Philosopher in the second book of the
It is not my purpose to discuss the thinkers Scotus refers to as authorities as to Physics that nature and intellect are two distinct productive principles, I say that
their own account of active potencies, nor am I here concerned with the legitimacy the Philosopher has said little about the will, as it is distinct from the intellect, but
of Scotus' interpretation. What shall be shown is how Scotus himselfconsiders his usually he unites the intellect and will in the notion of the active principle; that is
position to be prepared by eminent thinkers, namely Aristotle and Augustine, and why in Book II of the Physics where he distinguished these active principles,
moreoverin which way Scotus' thought seems to be preparedby Henry of Ghent. namely intellect and nature, the intellect is not to be understood in so far as it is
distinct from the will, but as it cooperates with the will. When the intellect acts in
this way, the intellect and the will constitute the same principle with respect to
Aristotle
artificial things 19.
In Scotus' discussion of the distinction between nature and will, Aristotle
According to Scotus, a more obvious example of Aristotle's distinction
appears in two different ways. In one way, Scotus is rather concerned with the
between these two essentially different active principles is his distinction between
argument of authority; he wants to prove that this distinction is already present in
Aristotle's teaching. In a second way, Scotus tries to interpret Aristotle as a basis
for his own thought This second use of Aristotle is unseparable from Scotus' own
account of the will as it is opposed to nature; for this reason we shall reserve its (15) The context of most of the following references to Aristotle is Scotus' doctrine of the
discussion to section two. Trinity. where he argues that there are only two essentially different Trinitarian productions: a
Duns Seotus repeatedly argues that the main features of the distinction natural one and a free one. For more details see section five. Here, Scotus responds to objections that
between will and nature can be found in Aristotle 14, although this might not be Aristotle does not distinguish between nature and will, but rather between nature and intellect
(Physics II) and between rational and irrational active potencies (Metaphysics IX). Cf. Ord. I d.2
p. 2q. 1-4n,216-217. Vat. II,257-258 ;Lect.ld. 2 p. 2q. 1-4n. 160-161, Vat. XVI. 165-166.
(l6)ARIST .• Physics II. 5, 196b17-22. The English text is taken from The Complete Works of
Aristotle, ed. by I. BARNES, Princeton, NI. University Press, 1984, vol. 1,335.
(13) Scorns' ontological explanation of the possibility of self-motion as a basis for his (17) Ord. I d. 2 p. 2 q, 1-4 n. 216, Vat. Il, 257; see also Quodl. q. 16 n. 13, Vivo XXVI, 19Th-
conception of the self-determining will (cf. QQ. Metaph. IX q. 14, OPh,IV, 625-673) - a challenge 198a.
to Aristotelian and Thomistic principles - will not be discussed in this article. Cf. R. EFFLER, John (18) Quodl., ibid... cf. also QQ. Metaph. IX q. 15 n. 23, OPh. IV, 681. This interpretation seems
Duns Scotus and the principle Omne quod movetur ab alia rnovetur, St. Bonaventure, NY, to bejustified, ARlST.• Physics, II, 6, 19ThI -22.
Franciscan Institute, 1962 (Franciscan Institute Publications, Philosophy series 15); P. KING. (19) «Cum arguitur de natura et intellectu quod sunt duo principia productiva distincta per
«Duns Scotus on the Reality of Self-Change », in M. L. GILL-I. G. LENNOX (ed.), Self-motion from Philosophum Il Physicorum, respondeo quod Philosophus parum locutus est de voluntate ut
Aristotle to Newton. Princeton, University Press, 1994, 227-290; HOERES, Der Wille als reine distinguitur contra intellectum, sed communiter in ratione principii activi coniunxit intellectum ad
Vollkommenheit.269-274. voluntatem: et ideo in II Physicorum, ubi distinguit isla principia activa, naturam scilicet et
(14) Lect. I d.2 p.2 q. 1-4 n.225-226, Vat.XVI. 196-198; Ord. I d.2 p.2 q.l-4 n.345-351, intellectum, intellectus non debet intelligi ut distinguitur contra voluntatem sed ut concurrit cum
Vat.II, 332-335; QQ. Metaph. IX q.15 n.23, OPh. IV, 681; n.35-41, OPh. IV, 684-686; Quodl. voluntate, constituendo idem principium respectu artificialium», Ord.I d.2 p.2 q.I-4 n.345,
q.16n.13. Viv.XXVI, 197b-198a. Vat. II, 332. When no other source is mentioned. the translations are my own.
194 TOBIASHOFFMANN THEDISTINCTION BETWEEN NATUREANDWILLIN DUNSSCOTUS 195

irrational and rational potencies in the ninth book of the Metaphysics 20. There, the cause opposite things, it cannot determine itself to opposite effects. The sun acts
key difference between irrational and rational potencies is that the latter can always by natural necessity, and which one of the opposite effects is produced
produce contrary effects, whereas irrational potencies are determined to only one depends on the matter on which it acts 30. As a consequence, self-determination is,
effect-", Thus, for example, heat can only heat, whereas medicine can produce according to Scotus, reserved to the will>',
either a cure or sickness 22.
Augustine
... whenthe agentand thepatientmeetin the wayappropriate to the potentiality
in question, the one must act and the other be acted on, but with the former More profoundly than Aristotle, Augustine perceived the philosophical (and
kindthisis notnecessary. Forthenon-rational potentialities areall productive of theological) problems associated with the will. Augustine develops a more
one effect each, but the rational produce contrary effects, so that they would explicit notion of the will and its free activity than Aristotle. Thus, it is no surprise
producecontrary effects at the same time; but this is impossible. That which that Scotus repeatedly quotes Augustine when discussing the freedom of the will :
decides, then, mustbe something else; I meanby this,desire [ope~t<;] or choice « Nothing is in our power as much as the will itself» 32. The originality with which
[ltpoatpeGt<;] 23.
Augustine treats the peculiar nature of the will can be attributed to Augustine's
Duns Scotus appropriates these Aristotelian distinctions, inserting them into novel concern with the degree to which humans are culpable for their sins, and
his own doctrine of the distinction of the active potencies 24. Scorns accomplishes why God, while first cause of all being, cannot be held responsible for human sin.
this - as mentioned earlier - by acknowledging that the intellect can be considered Scotus draws upon Augustine's On Free Will as an authority for his distinction
in two different ways: first, with respect to its own activity and nature; second, between free active principles and natural active principles:
with respect to the activity and nature of other potencies which influence the
I thinkyouremember wewerefairly satisfied in thefirstdiscussion that the mind
intellect. Whereas in the first sense, the intellect is a natural active potency 25, in the becomes the slave of passion only through its own will. ... The movement,
second sense (i. e. in connection with the will) it is not a natural, but a free active therefore, must be due to itself, by which it turns its will to enjoyment of the
potency-e. In fact, as a nature, the intellect is not able to determine itself in an creaturefromenjoyment of the Creator, If thismovement is calledculpableand
opposite way, this means that, by itself, it is not able to accomplish the choice todoubtthisis, in youropinion, absurd- it is certainly notnatural,but voluntary
Aristotle demands ofit in the above quotation 27; inasmuch as the intellect acts in a [non estutiquenaturalis, seduoluntariusv>.
natural way, it acts under the same circumstances in like manner 28. Even if we
admit that the intellect has the possibility of opposite effects, this does not yet
imply the self-possession of the intellect. For the sun (an irrational potency), too,
produces opposite effects: it can either liquefy a solid material (e. g. it can melt potentia eius est irrationalis ». Cf. Add. magn. (Additiones magnaet, ed. C. BALle in Les
ice) or solidify a liquid material (e. g. harden mud) 29. Yet, even though the SUfI can commentaires de Jean Duns Scot sur les quatre livres des Sentences, Leuven 1927 (Bibliotheque de
la Revue d'histoire ecclesiastique 1), 264-301, especially 267. The Additlones magnae contain
fragments of Scotus' teachings; they arereported byWilliam of Alnwick, a student of Scotus, The
(20)« ... oij)"ov on Kat 'tCiiv O'Uvaltll(i)V ui l1£v e<:lovw:t &",010t ai oe l111ti':r. M10'U », degree ofauthenticity isofcourse less than for texts redacted byScotus himself; nevertheless they
ARIST., Metaph. IX, 2, I 046b1-2. Cf. P. SCAPIN, «Necessite et liberte d' apres Aristote erJean Duns areofacertain value, since they are asource which testifies Scotus' late teaching.
Scot », Diotima, 8 (1980), 120-127. - Scorns discusses this text extensively in his QQ. Metaph. IX (30)Scotus expresses this idea particularly clearly in Ord. IVd.12q. 3n.19, Vivo XVII, 594b-
q.15, OPh. IV,675-699. Atthis point ofmy article I intend toshow how Scotus transforms what he 595a: « ... agens ex electione potest diversirnode agere, non tanturn diversitate quadam
canfind inAristotle tohisown purposes. Insection two, when dealing with Scotus' account ofthe disparationis, sed contradictionis, sicut potest non tantum hoc agere et illud, sedhoc agere et ilIud
will as self-determining potency, his interpretation of Aristotle's distinction of rational and non agere. Agens autem naturale, quod est illimitaturn simpliciter, vel aliqualiter secundum
irrational potencies inQQ. Metaph. IXq. 15will bediscussed more closely. perfectionem activam potest ad disparata agere, sednon ad contradictoria, quia quodlibet iIlorum
(21)ARIST., Metaph. IX,2, 1046b4-5. agit inmateria disposita, ethocnecessaria. Non ergo sequitur, non agit secundum electionem, ergo
(22) Ibid., I046b6-7. nondiversas forrnas in diversis passis. Sed sequitur, ergo non indifferenter agn, velnonagit ex se
(23)ARrST., Metaph. IX, 5, 1048a6-11. For the English text, see The Complete Works of formam illam, quam potest agere in tali passo. Exemplum de sole ... qui licet habeat
Aristotle. vol. II, 1654-1655. Cf. DUNSSCOTUS, Quodl. q. 16n. 13, Viv. XXVI, 198a. indeterminationem quamdam addisparata causanda indiversis passis, nonesttamen indeterminatus
(24) Cf. H. MaHLE, Ethik als scientia practica nach Johannes Duns Scotus : Eine philosophi- contradictorie ad agendum, immo necessario agit in quodlibet passivum quidquid potest in iIlud
sche Grundlegung, MUnster, Aschendorff, 1995 (Beitrage zur Geschichte der Philosophie und agere ».
Theologie desMittelalters, NeueFolge 44), 158-161. (31) Ord. I d.2 p. 2 q. 1-4n. 350, Vat. 11,334. This point will bedeepened in section two ofthis
(25) Oro. I d. 2p.2q.1-4n. 346, Vat. II, 333. article.
(26) Ord. Id. 2 p. 2q.1-4n. 351, Val. II, 335. (32)"Quapropter nihil tam in nostra potesrate quam ipsa voluntas est», Retractationes I, 9,3,
(27)Ord. Id.2p.2q. 1-4n. 350, Vat. II, 334. CCSL57, 25. cr. Lect. I d. 1 p.2 q. 2 n.96,Vat. XVI, 93; Leet. n d.25 q. un. n.15,Vat. XIX, 232;
(28)Ord. Id.2p.2q.I-4n.348, Val. II, 334. Quodl. q.16n.4,Vivo XXVI, 184b.
(29) Ord. I d.2 p.2 q.l-4 n.349, Vat. II, 334; QQ. Metaph. IXq.15 n.5, OPh. IV, 676: «Sol (33) De libero arbitrio Ill, 1,8-9, CCSL 29,275, The English textistaken from St.AUGUSTINE,
potest inopposites effectus inistis inferioribus: dissolvit enim glaciem et constringit lutum; tamen The Problem of Free Choice, translated by D. M. PONTtFEX, Westminster, MD, Newman Press-
196 TOBIASHOFFNIANN THE DISTINCTIONBETWEENNATUREANDWILL INDliNS SCOTUS 197

Like Scotus, Augustine thinks that the natural activity of active principles creatures) is natural, that that God acts always with utmost intensityw. In
entails necessity, and where there is necessity there can be no sin 34. Henry's Summa, this discussion of God's activity follows shortly after Henry
It is to Augustine's City ofGod which Scotus turns to support his view that the distinguishes natural and rational potencies, where he defines rational potencies as
will is free, that is, it is not determined to particular activity by causes outside of those commanded by the will 40 • In the light of that distinction, Henry argues that
itself. In Book XII, Augustine asks how it is that two different persons, in God's aetivity is determined not naturally, but according to the requirements of
apparently the same situation, make different choices : reason and the disposition of the will 41.
Whereas in this text Henry discusses the will in conjunction with the intellect,
Let us suppose that two persons in the same mental and physical state see the
beauty of a single body, and that the sight of it drives one of them to seek illicit and distinguishes both will and intellect from nature, elsewhere, namely in his
enjoyment while the other maintains steadfastly the chastity of his will. Now discussion of the doctrine of the Trinity, Henry appeals only to the will as the
what do we think is the reason that the will to do evil is produced in one but not in opposite of nature 42 • There, Henry asks ifthe active spiration ofthe Father and the
the other? ... Accordingly, even if they study the matter ever so carefully, those Son proceeds solely by will, or also by nature.
who are curious to know what thing created the individual will of one ofthem evil Henry responds that «nature and will are the two principle categories of
are at a loss for an idea.... Now if anyone says that the one who yielded was production... to which all the other categories of production have to be
himself responsible for making his will evil, although he was certainly good referred» 43. On this occasion, Henry distinguishes four senses of the term 'nature'
before the evil will, let him put the question why he did this ... It will then be in God: first, nature as the divine essence; second, nature as a naturally active
discovered that the evil will derives not from the fact that he is a natural creature, principle; in a third sense as any power in God, even if free (this sense applies to
but from the fact that he is a natural being created out of nothing 35.
the will); and finally nature as the necessity of an act 44. If 'nature' refers to a
Though major intention in this text is not to argue for the self- natural active principle, then the act ofthe generation of the Son is natural, but not
determination of the will, the Subtle Doctor finds here a confirmation of his the act of the spiration of the Holy Spirit. The latter is produced by the will, that is
conviction that the will is not a natural active principle, because the will does not to say, the Holy Spirit proceeds freely ". As we shall see, Henry's distinction
always actin the same way, even under the same circumstances 36. between those productions in God which are produced by nature and those
produeed by will shall be incorporated into Duns Scotus' treatment of the Trinity.
Henry ofGhent For Henry, the basis for distinguishing the will from nature as two distinct
active potencies is the will's capacity for self-motion 46. Henry's emphasis that the
It is easy to be misled with regard to Scotus' intellectual debt to Henry of
Ghent. For Scotus rarely explicitly cites Henry as an authority, but rather criticizes
Henry's views. However, with respect to the distinction between will and nature (39) «Et est vera ct necessaria consequentia, quia omnis virtus naturalis naturaliter motiva, in
as the two fundamental active principles, it is very likely that Henry's work has a corpore iam existens, movet de necessitate mobile suum secundum totum suum vigorem », Summa
a. 35 q. 6 ad 2, Opera omnia XXVIII, 67.
direct influence on Scotus. For not only is this distinction important for Henry's
(40)« ... potentia agens duplex est. quaedam scilicet naturalis, er per impetum naturae,
work generally, it is also a fundamental distinction in those specific areas of quaedam rarionalis, et perimperium voluntatis ", Summa a. 35 q, 6 ad 1, Opera omnia XXVIII, 63.
Henry's teaching which are foundational for Duns Scotus' treatment, namely, the (41) Summa a. 35q. 6 ad 3, OperaomniaXXVIll, 68-69.
self-motion of the will and the procession of the Holy Spirit by the will ofGod 37. (42) Summa a. 60q.1.
(43)« ... natura et voluntas sunt duae rationes principales emanandi sive producendi tam in
For example, Henry asks if the active potency of God is infinite. Henry's
divinis quam in creaturis, ad quas omnes aliae quae sunt habent reduci », Summa a. 60 q. I in corp.,
response to the objections against the affirmative answer to this question 38 is that ed, BADtuS, Paris, 1520 (reprint: St. Bonaventure, NY, The Franciscan Institute, 1953) II, I 53vN.
they only have force if one assumes that God's activity ad extra (i. e. towards (44) Summa a. 60q.l in corp., II, 154vT: «Sciendurn est quod natura in divinis quadrupliciter
dicitur. Uno modo appellatur natura ipsa divina essentia, in qua tres personae consisrunt, et dicitur
pure essentialiter. Secundo modo dicitur natura principiumactivum naturale, et sic natura est vis
productiva similis ex sirnill ... Tertio modo dicitur natura quaelibet vis naturaliter exsistens in
London, Longmans, Green and Co., 1955, 140-141. Cf. DUNS SCOTUS, Quodl. q.16 n.L Vivo natura primo modo, etiam etsi sit libera illa vis; et sic voluntas in Deo dicitur natura, quia scilicet est
XXVI,180ab. naturalis potentia, exsistens naturaliterin divinanatura. Quarto modo dicitur natura incommurabilis
(34) De libero arbitriolil; 1,4, CCSL29, 274; IIIA8, 167, CCSL29, 304. necessitas circa aliquern actum »,
(35) De civitate Dei XII, 6, CCSL 48, 361. The English text is taken from St. AUGUSTINE. The (45)Suntmil a. 60 q.l in corp., II, l54vT: «Secundo modo dicitur natura principium activum
City of God Against the Pagans, translated by Ph, LEVINE, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University naturale».154vV: «Loquendo vero de secundo modo naturae: dico simpliciter quod natura
Press-London, William Heinemann Ltd, 1966 (Loeb Classical Library 414), IV, 29. solummodo est principium eliciendi actus generationis filii, et nullo modo communis spirationis
(36)Leet. Il d. 25 q, un. n. 12, Vat. XIX, 231-232. cum voluntate.... Ad acturn autem spirandi, ordinem habet non ut est natura naturaliter agens, sed ut
(37) Cf. Quodl. IX q. 5 (self-motion of the will) and Summa a. 60 (procession of the Holy Spirit). est libera liberaliter agens ».
(38)Summa a.35 q.6 arg.2 and arg.3, Opera omnia XXVIlI, ed. G.A.WILSON, Leuven, (46) The self motion of the will is the subject of a detailed discussion in Quodl. IX q. 5, Opera
University Press, 1994,43. omnia XIII, ed, R. MACKEN. Leuven, University Press, 1983,99-139.
198 TOBIASHOFFMANN THE DISTINCTIONBETWEENNATUREANDWILLIN DUNSSCOTUS 199

will is not in any way like a nature can be seen in his concluding notes to the II.THE SELF-DE1ERMINAnON OF THE WILL
discussion offreedom of the will and self-motion:
... if the will were naturally moved by something else, it would be determined to TheSelfDeterminationoftheWill versusthe DeterminationofNature 54
its act without any freedom, and it could not pull back from it .... One must say,
When examining Scotus' treatment of notions like necessity, contingency and
then, without qualification that the will is moved to its act of willing by nothing
freedom of will, it is important to note that he analyses them with regard to
else, but by itselfalone 47.
different modes ofcausation. The consideration ofthe effects of different types of
Henry also seems to influence Scotus with regard to the relationship between agents is secondary. Thus, with respect to will, Scotus says that « ... the primary
the will and the intellect Specifically, Henry asks whether the will and intellect distinction of active potencies stems from the radically different way in which
have the same degree of freedonr", To answer this question, Henry appeals to they elicit their respective operations» 55.
Aristotle's distinction between rational active potencies and natural active Negatively, the will is characterized by its non-natural activity:
potencies-". Henry claims that freedom is an attribute of active potencies, but not
... there is only a twofold generic wayan operation proper to a potency can be
of passive potencies so. Now in a most proper sense it is the will that is an active
elicited. For either the potency of itself is determined to act, so that so far as itself
potency: « ... it is very strange to say that the will is a passive power and still is is concerned, it cannot fail to act when not impeded from without; or it is not of
free, just as it would be strange to say that something is an active natural power and itself so determined, but can perform either this act or its opposite, or can either
still is free» 51. Henry argues again that the distinction between the will and nature act or not act at alL A potency of the first sort is commonly called 'nature',
is that the will, and not nature, can determine itself to different possibilities 52 . For whereas one of the second sort is called 'will'. Hence, the primary division of
Henry, the intellect can, in a sense, even be considered a passive potency, because active potencies is into nature and will 56 •
it cannot control freely its own activity 53.
Thus, the will is characterized by indetermination. This indetermination
In this section, we have already anticipated some of Scotus' ideas on the will
applies not only with respect to contrary effects (in the same way irrational beings
and its opposition to nature in as much as they appear in the use he makes of the
as e. g. the sun have been shown to be indeterminate), but also with respect to
authorities. In the next section we will analyze the distinction between will and
contrary acts and to contrary objects 57. Nature, on the other hand, is determined to
nature directly in Scotus' own thought.
one effect 58. Thus, there are two questions which arise: first, if the will is
undetermined, how can it choose anything at all? second, why does the will
(47)« ... Si voluntas rnoveretur ab alio natural iter, determinaretur ad actum absque omni choose one possibility rather than the other?
Iibertate, nee posset resilire ab ipso ... simpliciter ergo dicendurn quod voluntas in acturn volendi a Duns Scotus answers the first question with a distinction between two sorts of
nullo alio, sed a se ipsa sola movetur», Quodl. IX q. 5 in corp .. Opera omnia Xlll, 130. The English
translation is taken from HENRY OF GHENT, Quodlibetal Questions on Free Will, translated by indetermination. On the one hand, indetermination can be seen as a deficiency, as
R. J. TESKE, Milwaukee, WI, Marquette University Press 1993,58. Cf. Quodl. IX q. 5 in corp., Opera is the case with a passive potency which lacks its determining form. Scotus refers
omniaXllI, 131-132 : « Quam propter libertatem voluntatis, qua debet esse domina suorum actuurn,
impossibile estponi quod ab aliquo naturali activo, ut est natura ut est receptibilis volitionis, alio a se
procedat de potentia in actum : hoc enirn omnino repugnat liberrati, sicut dictum est, et non minus (54) F.INCIARTE. « Natura ad unum - ratio ad opposita, Zur Transformation des Arisrotelismus
ageretur appetitus voluntatis, quam ille qui est sensibilis, Unde et Spiritus sanctus, si a Patre et Filio bei Duns Scotus », in J. P. BECKMANN et al. (ed.), Philosophic im Mittelalter : Entwicklungslinien
procederet ut a naturali activo, ut natura est, et modo naturae, non diceretur procedere modo und Paradigmen, Hamburg, Meiner, 1987 (Festschrift W. Kluxen), 259-273, especially 262-266;
voluntatis et libertatis sive liberalitaris, sed quia procedit ab agente ut est liberum voluntate ... H. MaHLE, Ethikals scientia practica, 161-166.
diciturprocedere opere voluntatis ». (55)« ... prima distinctio potentiae activae est secundum diversum modum eliciendi operatic-
(48)Quod. XIV q.5, ed. BADIUS. Paris, 1518 (reprint Leuven, Bibliotheque S.J., 1961) Il, nem», QQ. Metaph. IX q.15 n.21, OPh.IV, 680. The English text is taken from A.B.WOLTER.
563vT: "utrum ... intellectus et voluntas ambo sint aeque liberi, supponendo quod ambo sint Scotus on Will and Morality, Washington D. C., The Catholic University of America Press, 1986,
liberi ». 151.Fromnowon Ireferto this bookasABW. Cf. n. 9.
(49) Quodl. XIV q. 5 argo2, rr, 564rX. (56) «Iste autem modus eliciendi operationem propriam non potest esse in genere nisi duplex.
(50) Quodl. XIV q. 5 in corp., II, 574rY; cr. ibid., ad 2, Il, 566rD. Aut enim potentia ex se est detenninata ad agendum, ita quod, quantum est ex se, non potest non
(51) « Unde multum mirabile est dicere quod voluntas est virtus passiva, libere ramen, sicut agere quando non impeditur ab cxtrinseco. Aut non est ex se determinata, sed potest agere hunc
mirabile esset dicere quod aliquid esset vis activa naruralis, libere tamen », Quodl. XIV q. 5 ad 2, II, actum vel oppositum actum: agere etiam vel non agere. Prima potentia communiter dicitur 'natura' ,
566rD. For the English text see HENRY OF GHENT, Quodlibetal Questions on Free Wili, 86. secunda dicitur 'voluntas'. Unde prima divisio principiorum activorum est in naturam et
(52) Ibid. : "Ex quo provenit quod contingens aequaliter potest inveniri a voluntate fieri pro voluntatem»,EnglishtextABW,151.
altera parte, non sic auternab agente naturali ». (57) Leet. I d.39 q.I-5 n.45, Vat-XVII, 493. Cf. QQ.Metaph. IX q. 15 n.22-23, OPh. IV,
(53) Ibid. : «Licet ergo intellectus aeque rationalis sit quam voluntas aut etiam magis, cum 680-681.
tarnen non sit activa potentia, nisi prius passiva, nec etiam activa quoad exercitium actus etiam in (58) QQ. Metaph. IX q.15 n.24, OPh. IV, 681: «natura est tantum unius (hoc est, ...
iudicando quod est opus quod magis libere agit, nisi secundum complacentiam voluntatis secundum determinate ex se est istius vel illorum), voluntas autem est oppositorum (id est, ex se indeterminate
praedicta, ideo non tam libere valet ad opposita ut voluntas », huius actionis vel non actionis) »,
200 TOBIASHOFFMANN THEDISTINCTION BETWEEN NATUREANDWILLINDUNSSCOTUS 201

to such a case as indeterminatio insufficientiae and indeterminatio contradictio- The Intellect as Natural Agent
nis'", On the other hand, indetermination can express a perfection, such as when a
Its capacity to self-determination also distinguishes the will from the
potency produces contrary effects on its own (indeterminatio superabundantis
intellect. In principle, both the will and the intellect are open to opposite effects 66.
sufficientiae, indeterminatio illimuationisy», In the former case the activity of a
However, while the will always acts freelys", the intellect by itself acts in a
potency depends on external circumstances, and as soon as the deficiency is
determinate way. The intellect is unable to choose between opposite possibilities
remedied, the potency is determined to one specific effect. On that account, these
on its own, but rather is determined by things exterior to itself. Its primary
are natural agentsv'. The latter case, that is, indetermination as a perfection,
determinant is the object of knowledge, though it may also be the will 68• Thus, on
applies only to the will which does not act according to nature as described above,
its own, the intellect acts as a nature 69.
but freely. The will determines itself with respect to contrary (velle and nolle) or
The example of the intellect being determined from the outside shows again -
contradictory (velie and non velle) possibilities to act 62•
we mentioned before the case of the sun - that the possibility of something
According to Scotus, there is no answer to the second question: «There is no
producing opposite effects is not mutually exclusive with its being determined 70.
other cause to be found except that the will is will» 63. The proposition "the will
Unlike the will, a natural agent does not have its activity in its own power;
wills" is a contingent and at the same time immediate proposition. With regard to
«inasmuch as it is not hindered, it cannot produce opposite effects in the same
contingent propositions in general, some are first and immediate, and it is to these
matter which is disposed in the same way» 71. Observing that irrational potencies
which all other contingent propositions have to be traced back 64 • This shows the
have the capacity to produce opposites, we must thus note that for Scotus the term
fundamental difference between free active potencies and natural active
'rational' cannot merely mean the capacity to produce opposites, but the capacity
potencies: whereas the activity of natural active potencies can always be
to self-determination,
explained by reference to prior causes, the one offree active potencies cannot 65.
Having shown that the intellect is to be considered a natural agent, Scotus can
now relate his distinction between will and nature with the Aristotelian distinction
between rational and irrational agents 72. If, according to Aristotle, to be 'rational'
(59) QQ. Metaph. IXq.15 n.31. OPh. IV, 683; Add. magn., ed. BALlC, 275. Cf. also Ord. Id. 7
q.1 n. 20, Vat. IV, 1l4-1l5;Leet. Id. 7 q.un, n. 26, Vat.XVI,481·482.
(60)Add. magn.,ed. BALlC,275 ; Lect. lId. 25 q. un.n. 92, Vat. XIX, 260·261.
(61) Ibid.
(62) Cf. Add. magn., ed. BALlC,276; Leel. lId. 25 q. un.n, 93, Vat. XIX, 261. quia nee iIla effectio sed defectio », CCSL48, 362. - Aristotle holds the opposite view, i. e. that the
(63)« Quare voluntas illud volet ? Nulla erit alia causa nisi quia est voluntas », QQ. Metaph. IX will is moved by earlier causes, namely by the object of desire (opentlCov), De anima III, 10.
q. 15n.29, OPh. IV,682. EnglishtextABW, 153. Cf. also Ord. Id. 8 p. 2q. un n. 299, Vat. IV, 325; 433blO·18.
Leel.ld.S p.2q. un. n.279, Vat. XVII, 105; Ord. II d. 1 q, 2 n.91, Vat. VII, 47-48; Lect. lId. 1 q.2 (66)As to the intellect, cf. ARIST.,Metaph.IX, 2, 1046h4·6; DUNS Scows, QQ. Metaph. IX
n. 89, Vat. XVIII, 29; Rep. I A d. IOq. 3, Oxford, Merton 59, fol. 68r-68v : « Sicut quamlibet formam q.15n.41,OPh.IV,686.
activam consequitur immediate quod sit principiurn agendi, ita immediate consequitur earn modus (67) Scotus explicitly claims thai the will always acts freely: «Voluntas autem semper habet
agendi, et ideo sicut non est aliqua causa quaerenda quare talis forma agit vel potest agere vel quare suum modumcausandi proprium, scilicet libere », Quodl. q. 16 n. 14, VivoXXVI, 198b. Therefore, a
calor est calefactivus et quare calidum calefacit, nisi quia sunt tales formae, ita non est aliqua causa will cannot be forced from the outside to a specific act: «eontradictio enim est voluntatem
quaerenda quare habent talem modum agendi, ur calefacere per modum naturae er huiusmodi, nisi simpliciter cogi ad actum volendi»,Ord. IV d.29q. un.n. 6, Viv.XIX,218a(ABW, 174).
quia sunt tales formae. Unde sicut non est medium inter formam et principiumactivum, ita non est (68) QQ. Metaph. IX q.15 n.39, Ol'h, IV, 686; also Ord. II d.42 q.I·4, Vivo XlII, 45Ia-462a;
medium inter modum agendi et principium agendi, et ideo sicut quamlibet entitatem sequitur H. MOHLE, Ethik als scientia practica. 198-202.
immediate modus essendi eius proprius, ita quamlibet formam activam sequitur immediate modus (69) QQ. Metaph. IX q. 15 n. 36, OPh. IV, 684; «Et sic intellectuscadit sub natura. Est enirn ex
eius agendi proprius. Non est ergo aliqua causa quare voluntas vult, nisi quia voluntas est voluntas, se deterrninatus ad intelligendum, et non habet in potestate sua intelligerc et non intelligere, sive
nee quare hoc vel hoc vult necessario et contingenter, necessario et libere, nisi quia est talis et talis circa complexa, ubi potest habere contraries aetas, non habet etiam ilIos in potestate sua: assentire
voluntas ». et dissentire ».
(64)Cf. QQ. Metaph. q. 15n.28,OPh. IV,682;Ord. prol. p.3q.1·3n.I69, ve.r, 113; Rep. IA (70)« ... Determinatio non tollit 'posse in opposita' », QQ. Metaph. IX q.15 n.62, OPh.
d. 10 q. 3, Oxford, Merton 59, fol. 68v: «Sicut in propositionibus necessariis standum est tandem ad IV,694.
aliquam immediate, ita et in contingentibus propositicnibus oportet stare ad immediatam (71) « ... Agens naturale - idem et non impeditum - in eadem passe aequaliter disposito non
contingentem et non necessariam, quia ex necessario non sequitur contingens, sicut ex veto non potest causare opposita (hoc enim est de ratione agentis naturalis; unde II De generatione : "Idem in
sequitur falsum ». quantum idem natum est semper facere idem"; et hoc specialiter intelligitur de agente naturali) »,
(65)Cf. Leel.II d. 25 q. un. n.31, Vat. XIX, 238. Regarding this viewpoint, Duns Scotus seems Lect. II d. 25 q. un. n.36, Vat. XIX, 239. Cf. ARiST., De generatione et corruptione II, 10, 336a27-
to be in accordance with Augustine: «Sed quae tandem esse potent ante voluntatem causa 28. Therefore, if a natural agent acts by itself, it acts uninterruptedly. Cf. Lect. II d. 25 q. un. n. 73,
voluntatis ? Aut enim et ipsa voluntas est et a radice ista voluntatis non recedetur, aut non est Vat, XIX, 254.
voluntas et peccatum nullum habet. Aut igitur voluntas est prima causa peccandi aut nullum (72) A. B. WOLTER, « Duns Scotus on the Will as a Rational Potency», in M. McCORD ADAMS
peccatum est prima causa peccandi. Nee est cui recte inputetur peccanrm nisi peccanti », De libero (ed.), The Philosophical Theology ofJohn Duns Scotus, Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press, 1990,
arbitrio III, 49, 168, CCSL 29, 304. This point comes out more clearly in De civitate Dei XII, 7: 163-180; M.McCoRD·ADAMS, «Duns Scotus on Will as Rational Power», in L. SILEO (ed.), Via
«Nemo igitur quaerat efficientem causam malae voluntatis ; non enim est efficiens sed deficiens, scoti. Methodologia ad mentem Joannis Duns Scoti. Atti del Congresso Scotistico Internazionale
202 TOBIAS HOFFMANN
THE DISTINCTION BETWEENNATUREAND WILLIN DUNSSCOTUS 203

is to have the power to produce opposite effects, then, Scotus argues, it is the will
We could say that in this feature of the intellect lies the basis for objective
rather than the intellect that is properly deemed rational 73:
ethical judgments: one is free to elicit a morally good act, but the criteria of its
If 'rational' is understood to mean 'with reason', then the will is properly judgment is objective and accessible to the intellect 77.
rational, and it has to do with opposites, both as regards its own act and as regards
,the acts it controls. And it has to do with opposites not in the way that a nature, The Cause of the Will's Act: The Will is not determined by the Object of
like the intellect, acts, which has no power to determine itself in any other way. Apprehension 78
But the will acts freely, for it has the power of self-determination. Properly
speaking, however, the intellect is not a potency with regard to external things, If the will self-determines its activity, it follows that it is in some respects
because if it does have to do with opposites, it cannot determine itself, and unless independent of exterior influences. This includes a certain independence with
it is determined, it is unable to do anything extra 74. regard to its object as it is presented by apprehension. Since the object of
apprehension can only exercise a natural influence, the relationship between the
Scours' argument that the intellect is a natural agent should not be understood
free will and the object has to be accounted for in a way that freedom will not be
as derogatory. Rather, it can be seen that therein lies the intellect's true strength:
compromised.
for since the intellect as nature acts according to its utmost power, it is not subject
Scotus compares his views regarding the effective cause of the act of will with
to error in so far as simple concepts of thought are concerned 75. Furthermore, the
his scholastic contemporaries. He attributes to Thomas Aquinas and Godfrey of
intellect as a natural agent cannot fail to perceive the truth of self-evident
Fontaines the view that the act of will is determined by the object of apprehension
principles (propasiiianes per se notae) and the truth of conclusions from these
alone 79. To Henry of Ghent, on the other hand, he attributes the view that the will
principles 76.
alone is the effective cause of its act 80. Scotus grants some truth to both positions
and integrates them into his own view:

... I hold a middle way, claiming that not only the will, but also the object
cooperate to the act of will, so that the act of the will sterns from the will and from
the apprehended object as its effective cause 81.
Roma 9-11 marzo 1993, vol.2, Rome,Edizioni Antonianurn, 1995, 839-854; H.MOHLB, Ethik als In Lectura II d. 25, Scotus' pivotal text on this question, he interprets the will
scientiapractica, 166-173.
and the intellect (i. e. that which presents the object to the will) as both being partial
(73)In this assumption,Scotus seems to be directlydependenton Henry of Ghent, cf. Summa
a.36q.5,OperaomniaXXVllI,122-130.
(74)« Si autem intelligiturrationalis,id est cum ratione, tunc voluntasest proprierationalis.Et
ipsa est oppositorum, tamquoadactum proprium quamquoad actus inferiorum; et non oppositorum
modo naturae, sicut intellectus non patens se deterrninare ad alterum, sed modo Iibero potens se
determinate. Et ideo est potentia, quia ipsa aliquid potest, nam potest se determinate. Intellectus
(77)H.MOHLE, Ethik als scientia practica, 205. Cf. Ord. I d.l p.2 q.2 n.147, va.n, 98:
autem proprie non est potentia respectuextrinsecorum, quia ipse, si est oppositorum, non potest se
« necessitasest in intellectupropterevidentiamobiecti necessariocausantisassensumin intellectu:
determinare ; et nisi determinetur, nihil extra poterit », QQ. Metaph. IX q. 15 n. 41, OPh. IV, 686.
non autem bonitas aliqua obiecti causatnecessario assensum voluntatis, sed voluntas libere assentit
EnglishtextABW,157.
cuilibet bono,et ita libere assentitmaioribono sicut minori ». Cf. Ord. I d. 1 p. 1 q, 1 n. 22,Vat. II, 16.
(75)Cf. Ord. I d.3 p.l q.I-2 n.76, Vat.ID, 52: «causa naturalis agit ad effectum suum
(78) Seethe extensive study of thisquestionin H.MOHLE, Ethik als scientiapractica, 178-198.
secundum ultimum suae porentiae, quando non est irnpedita; igitur ad effectum perfectissimum
quem potest primo producere, primo agit, Omnia concurrentia ad istum actum primum intellectus Cf. also J, SPRUVT,« Duns Scotus's CriticismofHenryof Ghent'sNotion of FreeWill", in E. P. Bas
(ed.), John Duns Scotus: Renewal of Philosophy. Acts of the third Symposiumorganized by the
sunt causae mere naturales,quia praecedunt omnem actum voluntatis, - et non impeditae, ut patet;
Dutch Society for Medieval Philosophy Medium Aevum (May23 and 24, 1996), Amsterdam-
ergo prime producunt perfectissimum conceptum in quam possunt: ille autem non est nisi
Atlanta, Rodopi, 1998 (Elernenta. Schriften zur Philosophie und ihrer Problemgeschichte 72),
conceptus speciei specialissimaeproductae ». Cf. Leer. I d. 3 p, 1q, 1-2n. 71,Vat. XVI, 251.
139-154.
(76) Ord. II d.6 q.2 n.ll, Vivo XII, 355b (ABW, 474): « ... non est in potestate intellectus
(79)Cf. THOMAS AQUINAS, s.c. Gem. III c.26 ad5, Leon. XlV, 73a: «Voluntas enim, in
moderari assensum suum veris, quae apprehendit, nam quantum ostenditur veritas principiorum
quantum huiusmodi, movetur a suo obiecto, quod est bonum apprehensum»: S. theol. I q. 82 a. 4 in
ex terminis vel conclusionurn ex principiis,tantum oportet assentire, propter carentiam libertatis »,
corp., Leon. V, 303a; GODFREY OF FONTAlNES, Quodl. VI q.7 in corp., ed. M.DE WULF-
The necessityofthe assentto the firstprinciples(I. e. the self-evidentprinciples)lieson the one hand
J. HOFFMANS, Philosophes belges III, Leuven, t914, 163: «Voluntas non mover se, sed movetur a
in thenatureof the intellectas a natural agentthat acts to its utmostpower (Ord. I d. 3 p. 1 qA n. 269,
bono apprehenso secundum modum et formam apprehensionis », Aquinas and Godfrey are
Vat.III, 164-165); on the other hand it lies in the nature of these principles themselves: «termini
mentionedexplicitly inAdd. magn., ed. BALle, 267.
principiorumper se notorumtalemhabentidentitatemutalterevidenternecessarioalterumincludat,
(80) HENRY OFGHENT, Quodl. IX q.5 in corp.: « Simpliciterergo dicendum quod voluntas in
et ideo intellectus, componensillos terminos, ex quo apprehenditeos - habet apud se necessariam
actum volendi anulloalio, sed a se ipsa solamovetur », Opera omnia Xlll, 131.Cf.n.47.
causarn conformitatis illius actus componendi ad ipsos terminos quorum est compositio, et etiam
(81) «Ideo renee viam mediarn, quod tam voluntasquam obiectum concurrunt ad causandurn
causam evidentem talis conformitatis, et ideo necessario pater sibi ilia confonnitas cuius causam
actum volendi, ita quod actus volendi est a voluntare et ab obiecto cognito ut a causa effectiva »,
evidentemapprehenditin tenninis»,Ord. Id. 3 p. 1 q. 4n. 230,Vat.III,138-139.
Lect. lId. 25 q. un.n.69, Vat.XIX,253.
204 TOBIAS HOFFMANN THEDISTINCTION BETWEENNATURE ANDWlUIN DUNSSCOTUS 205

causes 82. In causing the act of will, both express their causality according to their assumes that to avoid sin during the beatific vision the will is preserved by a
characterization: the will as a free active potency and the intellect as a natural permanent influence of God 87.
active potency. Of these two partial causes, Duns Scotus considers the will to be
the principal cause 83. The will's freedom is not compromised by the cooperation The Will as a Pure Perfection : Freedom and Necessity
of the intellect as a natural cause, since the will freely chooses regarding the use it
An important element of Scotus' conception of the will follows from his
makes ofthis natural cause 84.
consideration of the divine will, becausein God the will is found as an infinite will.
The will's freedom with respect to its object holds true even with regard to its
Reflections on the infinite will in God presuppose that the will can not only exist as
most perfect object: the ultimate end for humans 85, i. e. the beatific vision of God
a finite will (in creatures), but also as an infinite will (in God), in other words, that
(as its most perfect object) and happiness (beatitudo, as its ultimate end). The will
the nature of the will as such transcends the modes of finite being and of infinity.
remains free to will beatitude and the beatific vision or not to will it. While the will
This leads us to the consideration of Scotus' account ofpure perfections 88.
cannot will against (nolle) happiness, it can fail to elicit an act ofwill for happiness
Literally, the expression 'pure perfection' (perfectio simpliciter) stands for a
(non velle) 86. Furthermore, since the human will is not infinite, it can tum away
perfection in the unqualified sense of the term. With Anselm of Canrerburyw,
from the infinite and highest beatifying good, even while experiencing the beatific
Scornsdefines the pure perfection in the following terms:
vision. Since the stability of the beatific vision, i. e. that the will can not tum away
from God, is not entailed by the interaction of the object and the will, Scotus That is said to be a pure perfection, which is better in everything than that which
is not-it90.

Following Scotus' own thought, this description can be exposed in the


following way:
Whenever two positive perfections are incompatible with one another, if one is a
(82) The Scotistic Commission holds that the discussions of the act of the will found in the text pure perfection, it mustbe better than the other 91.
of Lectura II d.25, Vat. XIX, 229-263 and in the Reportatio II A d.25 are authentic teaching of
Scotus. Cf. the introduction to Vat. XIX, 38*-41 *.The text of the Opus OxonienseII d. 25 contained For instance, for someone to have intelligence or wisdom is better than to lack
in the edition of Wadding-Vives does not belong to Scotus' Ordinatio, Vat. XIX, 37*. In the latter
them. The only condition is that these perfections be compatible with the nature of
text the object of the will is merely considered as causa sinequa non for the will's act, and the author
avoids interpreting it as efficient cause, Op. Ox. II d. 25 q. un. n. 19. Vivo XlTI,21Za. According to that which possesses them: for a dog it is not a perfection to be wise, since wisdom
this text, the will alone is considered the total cause of the will's act (n. 22, VivoXlll, 221b). Thus, is incompatible with a dog' s nature'".
the Scotistic Commission refutes the view of C. Balic : basing his view on a note of the Additiones What is important for our purpose is to consider that, according to Scotus, pure
magnae, where Scotus' student William of Alnwick reports that «aliter dixit Oxonie », ed. BALlC,
272, 282, Balle concluded that Scotus changed his mind about the cause of volition several times.
perfections are compatible with the mode ofinfinity 93• In fact, pure perfections are
Balic thought that, at an early stage (represented by the Lectura-texii, Scotus believed that object
and will are partial causes: by the time Scotus taught in Oxford Balic thought he had changed his
mind to the view described by the Op.Ox., and at the end of his career Scotus was assumed to have
returned to his original position. Balic believed that Scotus' final view was presented in the
Additiones magnae and the Secundae additiones (Add. magn., ed. C. BALlC, 282-284; Sec. add., ed. (87) Ord.lV d. 49 q. 6 n. 15, Vivo XXI, 234a: « ... Simpliciter contingens est. quod non peccet,
C. BALlC,«Une question inedite de J. Duns Scot sur la volonte », Recherchesde theologie anclenne tamen nunquam eveniet, quia causa superior semper praeservat »,
et medievale, 3 (1931], 191-208, especially 202-203). The Scotistic Commission interprets the (88) For an acconnt of the pure perfections in Duns Scotus, A B. WOLTER, The Transcendentals
words of William of Alnwick(aliterdixit Oxonie) as implying not that Scorns presented a different and their Function in the Metaphysics of Duns Scotus, St. Bonaventure, NY, The Franciscan
view in Oxford than he did before (i, e. in Paris), but rather that he should be understood as defending Institute, 1946, 162-175.
a view at variance with that of Henry of Ghent, who appears as Scotus' opponent, Vat. XIX, 39*. In (89) ANSELM OFCA1"TERBURY, Monologlon C. 15, Opera omnia 1, ed. F. S. SCHMm, Seckau
his article" Did Duns Scotus Change his Mind on the Will?» (forthcoming in vol. 28 of Miscellanea (Austriaj.Styria, 1938,28-29.
Mediaevalia), S. Dumont challenges this view. He argues against the editors of Vat. XIX that Balic (90) " Perfecrio simpliciter dicitur, quae in quolibet est melius ipsum quam non ipsum », Pro
was correct in thinking that Scotuschanged his mind on the will, but that this change, contrary to the princ. (Tractatus de primo principia) c. 4 concl. 3, ed. E. ROCHE, St. Bonaventure, NY, Franciscan
opinion of Balle .took place at Paris. not at Oxford. Dumont considers Rep. II A d. 25 to be the latest Institute-Leaven, Nauwelaerts 1949,76. English texiibid.•77.
statement on this issue and he interprets this text as favoring the viewthatthe will is the total cause of (91) WOL'fER. The Transcendental". 164.Cf. DUNS SCOTUS, Pro princ. C. 4 concl. 3, ed, ROCHE,
volition. 78; « Perfectio simpliciter est, quae est simpliciter et absolute melius quocumque incomposslbili: et
(83) Lect. IId.25 q. un.n, 73, Vat. XIX,254. ita exponatur illud 'in quolibet quam non ipsurn' , hoc est, quodlibet quod non est ipsum ».
(84) Lect. lId. 25 q. un, n, 74, Vat. XIX, 255. (92) Pro princ. c.4 concl. 3, ed. ROCHE, 78: «Non melior est in cane sapientia, quia nihil est
(85) MOHLE, Ethikals scientiapractica,389-398. bonitas in ilIocui contradicit »,
(86)" Licet non potest nolle beatitudinem, potest tamen non velie illud », Lect. I d. 1 p.2 q. 2 (93)Cf. Quodl. q.5 n. 9, Vivo XXV, 212a. Compatibility with the mode of infinity is just one of
n.Ll S, Vat. XVI, 100: more extensively Ord. IV d.49 suppl. q, 9-10 n.S, VivoXXI, 332b. For the four features Scotus ascribes to the pure perfections. For a complete account of the features of the
motivation of Scotus' viewon this point, see MOHLE, Ethik als scientia practica, 186-187. pure perfections, see WOLIT:.R, The Transcendentals, 166-169.
206 TOBIASHOFFMANN THE DISTINCTIONBETWEENNATUREANDWILLIN DUNSSCOTUS 207

transcendentals 94, which means that they are not restricted to any genus and that Scotus puts it. this is because contingency can spring from natural agents, and a
they are indifferent to finite and infinite being'", Consequently, they can all be free agent can act necessarily 102.
predicated of God, some exclusively ofhim (such as omnipotence), others of God Scotus himself seems to be somewhat puzzled with his own account of the
and of creatures 96. According to Seems, the will is a pure perfection 97; in fact, the compatibility between necessity and freedom. In an Addition to Quodlibet
wiJ1 is one that applies to God and to creatures. q.16 103 , the question is raised as to in precisely what the essence of freedom
We will now turn our attention to Scorns' account of the will in the mode of consists if the will can act necessarily.In necessary actions it seems neither to have
infinity (which is the divine will). God's will can be active not only contingently a determination to act nor a mastery over its acts 104. Moreover, since both an
(when it respects a finite object), but also necessarily (when it respects the infinite action of a natural agent and a necessary action of the will entail some
object, i. e. his own goodness), because both modes of the will's activity are determination to act, Scotus asks why the will does not act like a nature when it
perfect 98 • As a general rule, it can be said that each of God's productions ad intra acts necessarily 105.
(within the Trinity) is necessary while each causation ad extra (with respect to The answer to the first question is that the freedom of a necessary act of God
creatures) is contingent 99. The latter productions of God shall be discussed in the «consists in the fact that he elicits this act and perseveres in it as something
fourth section, while the former ones will be treated in the fifth and final section of delightful which he has elected, as it were, to do» 106. This reply is of course
the paper. However, before we turn to these subjects, it is necessary to present somewhat deceiving, since it does not respond to the intriguing question of
Scotus' argument as to how an activity of the will which is necessary does not whether the mastery over the action is preserved in necessary acts. The answer to
compromise its freedom. the second question is more persuasive: Scotus remarks that even though
According to Scotus, God necessarily wills his own goodness. Yet, at the same necessity implies determination. there are different degrees ofnecessity. Whereas
time, this act of willing is free lOO• The question why the necessity of this act does
not contradict its freedom cannot be explained by further reasons; this (102)« Non est eadem divisio in principium naturale. et liberum, et in principium necessario
compatibility of freedom and necessity simply derives from the nature of the will activurn, et contingenter, aliquod enim naturale potest contingenter agere, quia potest impediri:
and from the nature of God's goodness mi. Scotus is concerned to maintain a clear igitur pari ratione possibile est aliquod liberum, stante libertate, necessario agere », Quodl. q, 16 n. 9.
distinction between two pairs of contraries: the opposition between necessity and Vivo XXVI. 195a. Cf. Rep. IA d.1O q.S, Oxford. Merton 59. foI.68v: «Sicut ergo natura ex se
determinata ad unum. ita et voluntas ad producendum aliquid necessario vel contingenter, nee israe
contingency is distinct from the opposition between nature and freedom. As differentiae actionis necessitas et contingentia sunt differentiae essentiales principii activi vel
productivi, sed sunt differentiae accidentales non convertibiles cum principio activo naturali, nee
cum principio libero, quia utroque modo potest utrumque principium agere ». Cf. Ord. I d. 1 p. 2 q. 2
(94)« ... Omnes sunt transcendentes qui important perfectionem simpliciter», Ord. I d. 8 p.l n. 131, Vat. II, 88. - The explanation ofcontingency in this quote as a hindrance of natural effects is
q. 3n.156, VatlV,229. in apparent contradiction to Scotus' usual account of contingency (which is the object of section
(95)Ord. I d.8 p.1 q.3 n.114. Vat. IV, 206:« ... Transcendens quodcurnque nullum habet four). In his major texts on contingency, Scotus traces contingency back to a free will, not to some
genus sub quo contineatur ». Cf. Ord. I d.S p.1 q.3 n.113. Vat. IV. 206: «Quaecurnque sunt sort of interaction between natural causes. This apparent contradiction is resolved if we consider
cornmunia Deo et creaturae, sunt talia quae conveniunt enti ut est indifferens ad finiturn et that in this text Scotus is not discussing contingent causation, which is in fact reserved to free will.
infinitum ». nor does he seem here to intend the contingency of being, but he rather seems to have in mind the
(96) Ord. I d. 8 p. 1 q. 3 n, 115, Vat. IV, 207: «Ita enim potest sapientia esse transcend ens, et contingency ofa certain effect to take place or not (e. g. a stone is prevented from falling down if it is
quodcumque aliud, quod est commune Deo er creaturae, licet aliquod tale dicatur de solo Deo, held in a hand). This type of contingency may be explained as referring to the effects of natural
aliquod autem de Deo et aliqua creatura». It is in fact a condition for a pure perfection to be causes, even though, when tracing it back to the first cause of being, we arrive at the disjunction
predicable of God, Ord. I d.26 q. un. n.83, interpolated text, Vat. VI, 41 : « ... Solum ilIud est between necessary or contingent causing. This means that. in the final analysis, the hindrance of
perfectio simpliciter quod potest esse in aliquo infinitum ». natural effects as the cause for this type of contingency has to be itself either necessary (as an effect
(97) All attributes of God are pure perfections, Pro princ. c. 4 concl. 10, ed. ROCHE, 140: «Nihil of natural causation of the first cause) - or contingent (as an effect of free, contingent causation of
est in Primo nisi perfectio simpliciter». InOrd. I d. 2 p. 2 q.1-4n.235. Vat. II. 268, Scotus explicitly the first cause). Cf. section four.
characterizes the will (and the intellect) as pure perfections. Cf. also Pro princ. c.4 concl, 4, (103) F. Alluntis and A. B. Wolter believe that the additions to Scorns' Quodlibet « were added
ed, ROCHE, 86 : «Intelligere, velle, sapientia, arnor sunt perfectiones simpliciter ». by hands other than Scotus.... Some of these seem to be simply earlier versions of parallel passages
(98)« ... Voluntas infinita necessario habet actum circa obiectum infinitum, quia hoc est and probably would have been eventually eliminated had Scotus lived to see the revision of the
perfectionis ; et pari ratione non necessaria habet actum circa obiectum <finitum> (Viv. : infinitum), Quodlibet completed », God and Creatures, XXXIII.
quia hoc esset irnperfectionis », Quodl. q. l6n. 9, VivoXXVI, 194b. (104)« Sed semper est dubium, in quo stat per se ratio libertatis, sive enim dicatur quod libertas
(99) Lect, I d.2 p.2 q.I-4 n.177, Vat. XVI, 172; Ord. I d.2 p.2 q. 1-4 n.239, Vat. II, 272; stat in determinatione ad agendum, sive in dominatione respectu sui actus. per neutrum hie videtur
cf. Ord. proI. p. I q. un. n.4l, Vat. I, 24. possesalvari»,Quodl. q. 16n. 9 (additio), Viv.XXVI.195a.
(100) Quodl. q. 16n. 8, Viv.XXVI, 194a. (105) «Sed quaeritur unde est, quod voluntas, licet necessario agat, non tamen naturaliter agit,
(101)« Non est quaerenda ratio eorum quorum non est ratio ... Ita dico hie, quod sicut ista est cum non possit natura magis esse determinata ad agendum, quam quod sit necessitata ad agere ? »,
immediata et necessaria, voluntas divina vult bonitatem divinam, nee est alia ratio, nisi quia haec est Quodl. q.16 n. 15, VivoXXVI, 199a.
talis voluntas, et ilia talis boniras », Quodl. q.16 n. 8, Vivo XXVl. 194b; ibid. n.16, Vivo XXVl, (106)« Respondeo, quia delectabiliter et eligibiliter elicit actum, et permanet in actum », Quodl.
199b. cr. also above, n. 63. q. 16 n. 10 (additio), Viv, XXVI, 195b. English text ALLUNTIS-WOLTER. God and Creatures, 380.
208 TOBIASHOFFMANN THEDISTINCTIONBETWEENNATUREANDWILL IN DUNS SCOTUS 209

a natural agent is determined by exterior circumstances to produce its effect, the III. THE AFFECTION FOR THE ADVANTAGEOUS VERSUS
will- even when it necessarily wills something - has the capacity to determine THE AFFECTION FOR JUSTICE
itself to its volition 107. Scotus seems to claim that God's will, when it wills
necessarily, determines itself, yet in a determinate way. Though determining Besides the specific notion of the will as a free potency, Scotus also refers to
itself, the infinite and most righteous will cannot fail to will the most perfect the will in a general sense as an appetite Ill. As an appetite, the will has a natural
good lOB. inclination towards its own perfection, although it is entirely free in eliciting its
Yet, even though necessity is not contradictory to the freedom of will, the will act 112.
never elicits its act by natural necessity 109, The only case in which natural In addition to this natural tendency of the will by which a person pursues his or
necessity is compatible with the will's freedom is given when the will freely her own perfection (happiness), the will, being free, also has the capacity to want
accepts a natural necessity. Duns Scotus provides the following example: something independently of the person's own profit and simply because it is a
For instance, if one voluntarily dives off a cliff and, while falling, continues to good in itself. In Scotus' thought, each of the two types of the will's acts is based
will this, hefalls necessarily with the necessity ofnatural gravity and yethe freely on a different affection of the will.
wills that fall. Thus God, though he lives necessarily by a natural life and with a Following Anselm of Canterbury 113, Scotus refers to one of these tendencies
necessity that excludes all freedom, nevertheless freely wants to live such a or biases of the will as «the affection for the advantageous» taffectio commodii,
life llO. i. e. that which promotes one's own perfection, and to the other as «the affection
Having thus exposed the principal implications of the will/nature distinction for justice» (affectio iustitiaet, i, e. the tendency toward something good for its
for the notion ofthe will itself and of the intellect, we can now tum to see how this own sake 114. As Scotus puts it :
distinction affects Scotus' ethics. According to Anselm, two affections may be assigned to the will, namely, the
affection for justice and the affection for the advantageous. He treats of these
extensively in The Fall of the Devil, ch.14, and The Harmony of God's

(Ill) «Dico quod voluntas potest accipi sup propria ratione vel sub generali ratione et notitia,
scilicet pro appetitu », Ord. IIld. 17 q. un. n. 2, Viv.XIV, 653b(ABW, 180).
(112) «Dico quod voluntas naturalis sic. et ut naturalis non est voluntas ut potentia, sed tantum
importat inclinationem potentiae ad tendendum in propriam perfectionern suam», Ord. III d.17
q. un.n.5, Viv.XlV,655a(ABW, 182).
(I 13) ANSELM OFCANTERBURY, De casu diaboli C. t4, Opera omnia I, ed. SCHMITT, Seckau,
1938,258: «Quoniam ergo nec solummodo volendo beatitudinem, nee solummodo volendo quod
{I07)Cf. Quodl. q.16n.16, Viv.XXVI, 199b:« ... Grave est determinaturn ad descensum, non convenit cum ex necessitate sic velit, iustus vel iniustus potest appellari, nee potest nee debet esse
habito necessario actu descendendi ab ipso generanre, sed tantum habito ab ipso principio beams nisi velit et nisi iuste velit : necesse est ut sic faciat deus utramque voluntatem in iIlo
naturaliter determinative ad descendendum. Voluntas autem causata, si necessario vult aliquid, non convenire, ut et beatus et iuste velit, Quatenus addita iustitia sic temperet voluntatem beatitudinis, ut
sic est determinata a causante ad illud velle, sicut grave ad descensum, sed tantum a causante habet et resecet voluntatis excessum et excedendi non amputet potestatem. Ut cum per hoc quia volet
principium deterrninativum sui ad hoc velle ». beatus esse modum possit excedere, per hoc quia iuste volet non velit excedere, et sic iustam habens
(l08)Cf. Ord. Id.lOq. un. n.47-48, Vat.IV, 359; Quodl. q.16n.2, Viv.XXVl, 181ab;Rep. IA beatitudinis voluntatem possit et debeat esse beatus », Cf, De concordia praescientiae et
d.10 q. 2, OXford, Merton 59, foJ.67v: «Sequitur a primo ad ultimum, quod si voluntas infimta praedestinationis et gratiae Dei cum libero arbitrio q, 3 c. II, Opera omnia II, ed, SCHMITT, Rome,
posset esse non recta vel in actu non recto, quod necessario sit in actu volendo recto et circa primum 1940,281 : « ... Instrumentum volendi duas habet aptitudines, quas voeo 'affectiones'. Quarum una
obieetum volibile. Primum autem obiectum volibile quod est summum bonum est sunune et est ad volendum commoditatem, altera advolendum rectitudinem.... Per affectionem quidem quae
necessario volendurn ex ratione finis ». est ad volendum cornmoditatem, semper vult homo beatitudinem et beatus esse. Per illam vero quae
(109) Ord. I d. 1 p. 2 q. 2 n, 80, Vat.Il, 60: «Necessitas naturalis non stat cum libertate. Quod est ad volendumrectitudinem, vult rectitudinem etrectus, id est iustus esse »,
probo : quia natura et voluntas sunt principia activa habentia oppositum modum principiandi; ergo (114) Ord. II d. 6 q. 2 n.Ll , Vivo XII, 356b. This distinction has received attention in several
cum modo principiandi voluntatis non stat modus principiandi naturae ». Here again it is apparent studies: W. HOERES, Der Wille als reine Yollkommenheit, 149-162; A.B. WOLTER. «Native
how the difference between nature and freedom is founded in the different modus principiandi, i. e. Freedom of the Will as a Key to the Ethics of Scotus », in Deus et homo ad men/em l. Duns Scali,
the way a principle elicits its act, and not how some effects are related to another. Cf. also Leer, I d. 10 Rome, Societas internationalis Scotistica 1972 (Studia scholastico-scotistica 5), 359-370;
q. un, n. 17, Vat. XVII, 121 : « ubi est necessitas naturae ibi non est libertas ». N. HARTMANN,« Die Preundschaftsliebe nach Johannes Duns Skotus », wissenschaft una Weisheit,
(110)« Exemplum, si quis voluntarie se praecipitat, et semper in cadendo illud velie continuat, 52 (1989),194-218; 53 (1990), 50-65; I.F. BOLER, «Transcending the Natural: Duns Scotus on the
necessario quidem cadit necessitate gravitatis naturalis, et tamen libere vult ilium casum, ita Deus, Two Affections of the Will», American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 67 (1993), 109-126;
licet necessario vivat vita naturali, et hoc tali necessitate, quae excludit omnem libertatem, tamen Th. WILLIAMS, «How Scotus Separates Morality from Happiness », American Catholic
vult libere se vivere tali vita », Quodl. q. t6 n. 18, Vivo XXVI, 20lab. English text ALLuNTls- Philosophical Quarterly, 69 (1995), 425-445; L. SUKJAE, « Scotus on the Will : The Rational Power
WOLTER, God and Creatures. 387. and the Dual Affections », Vivarium, 36 (1998), 40-54.
210 TOBIASHOFFMANN THEDISTINCTION BETWEENNAWREAND WILLINDUNSSCOWS 211

Foreknowledge, Grace, and Predestination, ch.19. The affection for justice is identifies the affection for justice with «the innate freedom of the will» 121.
nobler than the affection for the advantageous, understanding by 'justice' not Conversely, if a will were to lack the affection for justice, it would have lowered
only acquired or infused justice, but also innate justice, which is the will's itself to the level of a natural agent (i. e. one without free will), as Scotus remarks
congenital liberty by reason of which it is able to will some good not oriented to with reference to the free will ofangels J22:
self. According to the affection for what is advantageous, however, nothing can
be willed save with reference to self. And this we would possess if only an For if one were to think, according to that fictitious situation Anselm postulates
intellectual appetite with no liberty followed upon intellectual knowledge, as in The Fall of the Devil, that there was an angel with an affection for the
sense appetite follows sense cognition 1J5. beneficial, but without an affection for justice (I. e., one that had a purely
intellectual appetite as such and not one that was free), such an angel would be
With his twofold account of the affections of the will, Scotus disassociates unable not to will what is beneficial, and unable not to covet such above all. But
himself from a strict eudaemonism in the Aristotelian sense!", For Scotus, not this would not be imputed to it as sin, because this appetite would be related to
every good is pursued for the sake of happiness 1l7; acts not motivated by the intellect as the visual appetite is now related to sight, necessarily following what
pursuit of one's happiness but rather intended for their own good are based on the is shown to it by that cognitive power, and being inclined to seek the very best
affection for justice. For Scotus, the affection for justice is of utmost importance, revealed by such a power, for it would have nothing to restrain it 123.
for it alone makes unselfish love possible J J8.
In accordance with Anselm, Scotus identifies the two affections as two
According to Scotus, the affection for justice would be inconceivable if the constitutive features ofthe will :
will were a natural active principle rather than a free active principle. For as a
nature, i. e. by the natural inclination alone, a person necessarily pursues the Nevertheless, by distinguishing from the nature of the thing the two primary
highest degree of his or her happiness 119. The will can desire all that is good in characteristics of this twofold affection ... he [i. e. Anselm] makes these aspects
out to be nothing other than the will itself insofar as it is an intellective appetite
itself independently of the pursuit of its own happiness, precisely since it is not
and insofar as it is free. For, as has been said, qua pure intellective appetite, the
naturally ordered solely to its own self-perfection. Thus, while the affection for the
will would be actually inclined to the optimum intelligible (as sight is to what is
advantageous is conceivable also in creatures lacking a free will, the affection for
best visible), whereas qua free, it could restrain itself in eliciting its act from
justice can only be present in those with a free will 120. In fact, Scotus literally following this natural inclination, as to either the substance of the act or its
intensity 124.
(1l5) «In voluntate secundum Anselmum assignantur duae affectiones, scilicet affectio Here we see that Scotus does not - contrary to Thomas Aquinas 125 - conceive
iustitiae et affectio commodi, de quibus tractat De casu diaboli, capitulo 14 er De concordia, 19
diffuse. Nobilior est affectio iustitiae quam commodi, non solum intelligendo de acquisita et infusa, ofthe will simply as an intellectual appetite. If the will were merely an intellectual
sed de innata, quae est ingenita libertas secundum quam potest velle aliquod bonum non ordinatum
ad se. Secundum autem affectionern commodi nihil potest velle nisi in ordine ad se, et hanc haberet
si praecise esset appetitus intellectivus sine libertate sequens cognitionem intellectivam, sicut (121) Cf. n.129.
appetitus sensitivus sequitur cognitionem sensitivam », Ord. ill suppl, d. 26 q. un. n. 17, Vivo XV, (122) An example about the angelic will also allows conclusions about the way the human will
340b-34Ia{ABW, 178). EnglishtextABW, 179. acts, since the will as a pure perfection is not restricted to a specific mode of existence. The essence
(116) BOLER, «Transcending the Natural », 116·122. of the will is univoque in different modes of existence, namely in God, in human beings and in
{I 17) Ord. IV d,49 suppl, q. 9-10 n. IS, Viv. XXI. 382a. angels. cr. Lect. I d.3 p. I q. 1-2 n.33, VaI.XVI, 237: «Anselmus De libero arbitrio cap. I :
(118) Cf. Ord. IV d. 49 q. 5 n, 2-3, VivoXXI, Ina-l73a: « ... Velie etiam est duplex in genere, "Potestas peccandi non est potestas libertatis, alioquin Deus non haberet libertatem" ; sed hoc non
aut propter volitum, sive propter bonum voliti, aut propter volentem vel bonum volentis. Primum sequeretur nisi libertas secundum se univoce conveniret nobis et Deo ».
velle dicitur esse amoris amicitiae; secundum amoris concupiscentiae ... actus amicitiae inest (123)« ... Angelus tantum habens affectionem cornmodi et non iustitiae (hoc est, habens
voluntati, secundum quod habet affectionem iustitiae, quia si solam affectionem commodi haberet, appetitum intellectivurn mere ut appetitum talem, et non ut liberum), talis angelus non posset non
non posset nisi sibi summe commoda velie... Actus autem concupiscentiae inest voluntati velie commoda, nee etiam non-summe velle talia; nee imputaretur sibi ad peccatum, quia ilIe
secundum quod habet affectionem commodi », For more details, see HARTMANN, «Die appetitus se haberet ad suam cognitivam sicut modo appetitus visivus ad visum, in necessario
Freundschaftsliebe », 53 (1990),54. consequendo ostensionem illius cognitivae et inclinationem ad optimum ostensum a tali potentia,
(1l9) Ord. IV d,49 suppl.q, 9-IOn. 2, VivoXXI, 319a:« ... Natura non potest remanere natura, quia non haberet unde se refraenaret », Ord. II d. 6q. 2 n. 8, VivoXII, 353b (ABW, 468), English text
quin inclinetur ad suam perfectionem, quia si tollas ilIam inclinationem, tollis naturam; sed ABW,469.
appetitus naturalis non est nisi inclinatio talis: ergo ut sic necessario appetit beatitudinem, quia illa (124) « ... Distinguendo ex natura rei duas rationes prirnas istarum rationum. ... nihil aliud sunt
est maxima perfectio.... Praeterea, in cuius potestate non est tendere, vel non tendere, in eius ista quam eadem voluntas, in quantum est appetitus intellectivus et in quantum libera, quia, sicut
potestate non est remisse tendere; ergo si voluntas ut natura determinatur necessario ad appetendum dictum est, voluntas inquantum est mere appetitus intellectivus summe inclinaretur actualiter ad
beatitudinem, ergo summe », optimum intelligibile ;.. tamen inquantum libera est, potest refraenare in eliciendo actum ne
(120) Rep. IV d,49 q. 4 n. 5, Vivo XXIV, 637b: « Affectio iustitiae, sive illud quod convenit sequatur istam inclinationem, nee quantum ad substantiarn actus, nee quantum ad intensionem, ad
alicui secundum affectionern iusti tantum, convenit voluntati inquantum liberae, affectio autem quam potentia naturalitcr inclinatur », Ord. II d. 6 q. 2 n. 8, VivoXll, 354a (ABW, 470), English text
commodi est communis ornni appetitui cognoscitivo, non inquantum liber, quia sic non conveniret ABW,471.
non habenti libertatem ». Cf. Ord. lId. 39q. 2n. 5, VivoXIII,415ab{ABW, 202). (125)Cf. S. theol. Iq. 82a. 2arg. 3 and ad 3,Leon. V, 296aand 297ab.
212 TOBIASHOFFMANN THEDISTINCTIONBETWEENNATL'REAND WILLINDUNSSCOWS 213

appetite, it would not be a freely active potency, but a natural active potency, since IV. GoD'SPRODUcnONSADEJITRA: CONTINGENCY
the intellect is a natural agent l 26 . Scotus often identifies the intellectual appetite
with the affection for the advantageous 127. Our topic now leads us to the consideration of the notion of contingency.
This confirms our assumption that for Scotus freedom of the will would be According to Scotus, contingency can only arise from causality that is not
inconceivable if the will only disposed of the affectio commodi128. Instead, the naturally necessitated. As we shall see, Scotus argues that contingency is founded
Subtle Doctor explicitly establishes the relationship between the affectio iustitiae in the free will of God 133.
and the freedom of will : The notion of contingency is critical in Duns Scotus' work, because he
... this affection for what is just, I say, is the liberty innate to the will, since it understands it to show in a particularly clear way how the Graeco-Arabic
represents the first checkrein on this affection ofthe advantageous 129. necessitarian cosmology of those whom Scotus simply calls the 'philosophers'
(i. e. Aristotle, Avicenna and Averroes) is fundamentally incompatible with
The possibility of the affection for justice to overcome the affection for the central Christian theological convictions.
advantageous is based upon the will's capacity to determine the intensity of its One's conception of contingency has a profound influence on one's
acts, in other words, the will's ability to not always act according to what promotes understanding of the relationship between God and creatures. The theological
the person's own good. Actually, in being free not to pursue one's own interest, by issues at stake are the Christian doctrines that God's creation of the world and
virtue of the affectioiustitiae, a person is destined to follow a higher will 130• This God's gift of grace are purely gratuitous. According to Scotus, God's activity ad
dependence upon a higher will must be interpreted as a subordination ofthe will to extrais never necessitated 134, but always arises out of God's free love.
the will ofGod 131.
Without belaboring the significance of the notion of contingency in the work
W. Haeres sees the connection between freedom and the affection for justice of Scotus, I will briefly recount the central issues at stake in Scotus' rejection of
in Scotus as so important that he defmes freedom in terms ofit: necessitarianism 135.
Since the capacity to self-determination owes its criterion and its direction to the Duns Scotus engages in his most detailed debate with the 'philosophers' in his
inner rationality of the will, by which alone freedom becomes possible ... , treatment of God's immutability (Ord. I d. 8 p. 2)136. In arguing that God alone is
freedom can be characterized as the capacity to dojustice to each thing 132. immutable, Scotus is confronted with the view which he attributes to Aristotle
and Avicenna 137 that the immutability of God requires the immutability and
therefore necessity ofall being that is caused by God 138.
(126)Scotus therefore does not use in this context the expression appetitus rationalis, but he
talks of the appetitus intellectualis. The reason for this seems to be that Scotus considered the will,
rather than the intellect, as the rational active potency (cf. n. 74). Cf. WILLIAMS, «How Scotus (133)Yel, God's will is not the only source of contingency. Besides the divine will, also the
separates Morality from Happiness », 428, n. 6. human will is a source of contingency, even though the latter contingency has its ontological
(127)Cf. the text just quoted: Ord.IId. 6q.2n. 8, VivoXlI, 353b (ABW, 468); Ord. II d. 39 q.2 foundation in God's contingent operalion ad extra. Cf. Rep. I A d. 39-40q. 1-3 n. 36, ed. J. R. SODER,
n. 5, Viv.XIII,415ab(ABW.202);Ord.IIId.26suppl.q. un.n.17, Viv.XV,340b(ABW,178). in m., Kontlngenz; und Wissen: Die Lehre von den futura contingentia bei Johannes Duns Sea IUS,
(128) This is also manifest in a similar reflection as the one just quoted: «Si esset angelus Munster, Aschendorff, 1999 (Beitrage zur Geschiehte der Philosophie und Theologie des
creatus habens instrumentum volendi solum affectione commodi, talis non posset non velle Mittelalters, Neue Folge 49),249. Cf. also SOder's comments, ibid., 86-87.
commoda ... Ex quo pater, quod voluntas non est libera, quia est imaterialis nee etiam eius libertas (134) Cf. n.99.
principaliter est ex parte intellectus, quia si tantum esser appetitus intellectivus, qui tantum (135) A thorough analysis of Scotus' account of contingency is given by SODER, Kontingem
afficeretur ad commoda esset imaterialis et haberet intellectum precedentem, non ramen esset und Wissen. Cf. also M. SYloWANOwrCZ, Contingent Causality and the Foundations ofDuns Scotus'
liber», Add. magn., ed. BAlle, 301. Cf. Rep. IIAd. 25 q. un. n, 20. VivoXXIII, 128b; Ord. II d. 39 Metaphysics, Leiden-New York-Cologne, Brill 1996 (Studienund Texte zurGeistesgeschichtedes
q.2n.5, Viv.XIII, 415b; Ord. IV d.49 q.Sn.S, Viv.XXI,173a. Miuelalters 51); L. HONNEFELDER, Scientia transcendens : Die formaie Bestimmung del' Seiendheit
(129) «Ilia igitur affectio iustitiae, quae est prima moderatrix affectionis commodi, ... est und Realitat in del' Metaphysik des Mittelalters und der Neuzeit (Duns Scotus-Suarez-Wolff-Kant-
libertas innata voluntatis », Ord. II d. 6 q. 2n. 8, VivoXlI, 353b (ABW, 470), English lexlABW, 471. Peirce), Hamburg, Meiner, 1990 (paradeigmata 9),56-108. For a description of how Scotus' notion
(130) Ord. II d. 6 q. 2 n. 10, VivoXlI. 355b: «Quia [voluntas] habet aliam regulam in agendo, of contingency influences his conception of metaphysics, ethics and the supernatural order,
quam ilia haberet si ex se sola ageret; tenetur enirn sequi voluntatem superiorem, ex quo in P. SCAPrN, Contingenza e liberta divina ill Giovanni Duns Scoto, Rome, Editrice Miscellanea
moderando iIIam inclinationem naturalem in potestate eius est moderari vel non rnoderari, quia in Francescana, 1964,79-86.
potestateeius est non summeagere in quod potest ». Cf. HOERES, Der Wille als reine Vollkommen- (136) For a more extensive discussion of Scotus' arguments, L. HONNEPELDER, « Die Kritik des
heit,154. Johannes Duns Scotus am kosmologischen Nezessitarismus der Araber. Ansatze zu einem neuen
(l31)Rep. II A d.6 q.2 n.IO, Vivo XXII, 622a; WILLIAMS, «How Scotus separates Morality Preihcitsbcgriff », in J.FRIED (ed.), Die abendlandische Freiheit vom 10. zum 14. Jahrhundert,
from Happiness», 436-437. See also HOERES, Der Wille als reine Yollkommenheu. 154. Sigmaringen 1991,249-263, especially 250-254. Cf. also 10., Scientia transcendens, 74-82.
(132)« Da die Fahigkeit zur Selbstbestimmung ihren MaBstab und ihre Richtung in der inneren (137) Ord. I d. 8 p.2q. un. n.251-255, Vat. IV, 294-297.
Rationalitat des Willens hat, wodurch allererst Freiheit rnoglich wird ..., kann man die Freiheit auch (138) Further places for the discussion ofnecessitarianism are the proofofthe existence of God
als die Fahigkeit bezeichnen, den Dingenjeweils gerecht zu werden », HOERES, Der Wille als reine tLect. I d. 2 p. I; Ord. I d. 2 p. 1; Rep. I A d. 2 q. 1-2; PI'. princ.) and the question concerning God's
Yollkommenheit. 152. knowledge ofcontingents (Lect. I d. 39).
214 TOBIAS HOFFMAN'N THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN NATURE AND WILL IN DUNS SCOTUS 215

The 'philosophers' agree with Scotus on the assumption that there is indeed If the first cause necessarily causes and moves its proximate cause and has a
contingency 139. But Scotus' point of departure from the philosophers is that he necessary relation to it, then that second cause necessarily moves this which it
believes contingency of being can only be adequately accounted for in relation to moves and causes, for a second cause only moves insofar as it is moved by the
the contingent causation of the First Cause l 40 • In fact, Scotus is generally first cause. Therefore, if it is necessarily moved and caused by the first cause, it
necessarily moves something else and so all the way down to the effect to be
considered to be the first to make a sharp distinction between contingent being 141
produced. Thus the whole order of causes is necessary in moving, and
and contingent causation, i, e. between entitative and operative contingency t42. In
consequently these causes can produce no effect contingently. Therefore it is
contrast, the 'philosophers' appeal to a necessarily operating First Cause to necessary that, if there is contingency in things, the first cause move either the
account for contingency, and they explain contingency by the fact that some second cause contingently or the effect contingently, so that contingency
effects might be hindered by interfering causes, due to the complex movements proceeds from the action ofthe first cause. If all things, therefore, were necessary
and interferences in the sublunary world 143. The difficulty with this explanation, in relation to the first cause, nothing would happen contingently t45.
Scotus notes, is that these movements are founded upon the necessary movements
The assumption of a contingently operating First Cause is closely linked to
of the constellations of the celestial bodies, which means that Scotus' opponents
Scotus' notion of contingent being as something «the opposite of which could
are actually claiming that contingency can arise from necessity-w. Scorns'
come to be when in fact it comes to be» 146. Scotus gives an account of how divine
response is that this account does not allow for true contingency of being :
causality is contingent and thus able to produce contingent being in the above
sense. He argues that the First Cause as contingent cause must arise either from the
divine intellect or the divine will, because they are the basis for God's activity ad
(139) Cf. Ord. Id. 8 p. 2q. un. n. 281-282, Vat. IV, 313. Wbile contingency cannot be proved by
extra 147. The intellect cannot be considered the source of contingency, since its
a demonstration by the cause (propter quid), Scotus argues for it with reference to the moral and activity is natural, and hence it cannot freely cause opposite effects 148.
political order, which would be senseless if there were no contingency. Furthermore, he proposes an Instead, as we have discussed, Scotus attributes to the will the capacity to
argument for contingency based on a thought-experiment: someone who denies contingency shall choose contraries 149, and therefore «when it is the cause which elicits an act of
be tortured until he admits that it is non-necessary that he be tortured, Rep. I A d. 39-40 q. 1-3 n. 30,
ed. cit.. 268-269: «Potest igitur probari [sc. contingentia] a posteriori, quia aliter non essent
necessariae virtutes nee praecepta nee merita nee mercedes nee poenae nee honores, et breviter
destrueretur omnis politia, et omnis conversatio humana. Et contra hoc negantes esset procedendum (145)« Si prima causa necessario causat et movet causam sibi proximam, et necessariam habet
cum tormentis et cum igne et huiusmodi, et tamdiu deberent fustigari, quousque fateantur, quod habitudinem ad illarn, igitur illa secunda causa necessario movet hoc quod movet et causat, quia
possunt non tormentari, et ita dicere quod contingenter tormentantur et non necessario, sicut fecit causa secunda non movet nisi in quantum movetur a prima; si igitur necessario movetur et causatur a
Avicenna contra negantes primum principium. Tales enim secundum eum debent vapulari donee prima, necessario movet aliud, et sic semper descendendo ad effectum producendum, - et ita torus
sciant quod nan est idem torqueri et non torqueri, cornburi et non cornburi ». Cf. AVtCENNA, Liber de ordo causarum in movendo erit necessarius, et per consequens nullum effectum contingenter
philosophia prima I c. 8, AvicennaLatinus, ed. S. VAN RIET, Leuven-Leiden, Peeters-Brill 1977.62. possunt producere; igitur oportet quod si sit contingentia in rebus, quod prima causa vel
Even though contingency has its ontological foundation in the free will (so that, a priori, contingenter moveat causam secundam, vel quod contingenter movet effectum, ita quod
contingency could only be proved by insight into the action of the will), the a posteriori proof of contingentia proveniat ex actione primae causae. Si igitur omnia essent necessaria in comparatione
contingency is also used by Scotus to hint at the self-determination of the will; Rep. n A d. 25 q. un. ad primam causam, nihil contingenter proveniret », Lect. I d. 39 q. 1-5 n. 35, Vat. XVII. 489. The
n.20, Viv.XXm.127b-128a. English text is taken from JOHN DUNS SCOTUS, Contingency and Freedom. Lectura I 39, ed. by
(140) Scotus proposes five arguments against the conception of contingency proper to the A. Vos JACZN.. H. VELDHUIS et al., Dordrecht-Boston-London, Kluwer academic publishers, 1994
'philosophers', HONNEFELDER, Scientia transcendens, 78-80. We will present only one of them; in (Synthese Historical Library 42), 90. In a shorter form this argument also appears in Pro princ. c.4
this argument the foundation of contingency in the will as a non-natural agent is especially clear. concl.4, ed.ROCHE, 84; Ord. I d.2 q.I-2 n.80-81. Vat. II, [76-177; QQ. Metaph. IX q. 15 n.28,
(141) According to Scams, contingency is a "disjunctive attribute" of being; every being is OPh. IV. 682.
either contingent or necessary. Cf. Ord. I d. 8 p. 1 q. 3 n. 115, Vat. IV, 207: « Sicut autem passiones (146) « Non dieo hie contingens quodcumque non est necessarium nee sempiternurn, sed cuius
convertibiles sunt transcendentes quia consequuntur ens in quantum non determinatur ad aliquod oppositum posset fieri quando istud fit », Pro princ. c.4 concl. 4, ed. ROCHE, 84, English text ibid.,
genus. ita passiones disiunctae sunt transcendentes, et utrumque membrum illius disiuncti est 85. Cf. Ord. Id. 2 p.l q. 1-2 n. 86, Vat. II, 178. Accordingly, the definition of necessity is as follows;
transcendens quia neutrum determinat suum determinabile ad certum genus: et tamen unum «Illud dicitur necessarium, cuius oppositum includit contradictionem », Quodl. q.16 n.3, Vivo
membrum illius disiuncti formaliter est speciale, non conveniens nisi uni enti, - sieut necesse-esse XXVI, 184a;cf. Ord. IV d.12q.l n. 9, Viv.XVIl,545a.
in ista divisione 'necesse-esse' vel 'possibile-esse', et infinitum in ista divisione 'finitum vel (147) Lect. Id. 39q.I-5n.42. Vat. xvn, 492.
infinitum' , et sic de aliis »; WOLTER, The Transcendentals, 150-152. (148) Lect. I d.39 q.I-5 n.43, Vat.XVII, 492: «Sed ista contingentia non est ex parte
(142)Cf. Pro princ. c.4 concL4, ed, ROCHE, 84; Ord. I d.2 p.l q.I-2 n.86, Vat. II, 178-179. intellectus divini in quantum ostendit aliquid voluntati, quia quidquid cognoscit ante actum
Cf. SODER, Kontingenz und Wissen, 50-56. voluntatis, necessario cognoscit et naturaliter, ita quod non sit ibi contingentia ad opposita »,
(143)ARIST., Physics vm, 6, 259b32-260aI9; Metaph. XII, 6-7, 1072a9-23. The idea that (149) Lect. Id. 39 q. 1-5 n. 43-45, Vat. XVII, 492-493; d. n. 57. The activity of the human will is
contingency is rooted in the sublunary movements is most clearly exposed by THOMAS AQUINAS, In the basis for the insight into the divine will. As a pure perfection, the will has an indifferent essence
Sent. I d. 39 q. 2 a. 2 in corp., ed. P. MANDONNET. voLI, Paris, Lethielleux, 1929, 932. Elsewhere, which Scorus considers to apply univocally to God's will and the will of creatures, d. n. 95. This
Aquinas ascribes to matter the cause of contingency, S. theol. I q. 86 a 3 in corp., Leon. V, 351. allows SCOluS to transfer that which is perfect in the human will to the divine will, cf. Rep. I A d. 39-
(l44)Cf.n.142. 40 q.I-3 n.40, ed. SODER, 250: «Hie dico quod assumendo quae sunt perfectionis in voluntate
216 TOBIASHOFFMANN THE DISTINCTIONBETWEENNATUREAND WILLIN DUNS SCOTUS 217

willing, the will has a contingent relation to the act, so that willing at a [volens in a] causation, whereas to cause necessarily seems to be perfect-". Because any
it can not-will at a [potest nolle in a]» 150. Thus, the contingency of a being (e. g. imperfection is incompatible with the essence of God, Duns Scotus has to show
that of a stone) arises from the so-called synchronic contingency of the causation why it does not entail an imperfection for God to cause contingently, i. e. to create
of the divine will. This means that «the divine will", can will and not-will contingent beings. Scotus' response is that the claim that necessary being is more
something [velle et nolle aliquid] , and likewise can produce or not-produce perfect than contingent being must be qualified. Only if it is non-contradictory for
something in the same moment of eternity and for the same moment of something to be necessary, its necessity is a more perfect condition than its
eternity» 151. Consequently, the actual existence of a contingent being (i, e. of a contingency 156. However, as Scotus argues, it is logically impossible for
creature) cannot be explained by any further reasons, other than by referring to the 'causable being' (ens causabile) to be necessary; consequently it cannot be a
fact that God wills it; and, as we noted earlier, Scotus maintains that no reason can perfect condition of it, nor can it be a more perfect mode of production to produce
be given for why the divine will decides as it does apart from the fact that the divine something into necessary being if this is itself impossible 157. Thus, Scotus has
will is a will 152. shown that it is not incompatible with the perfection of God to cause contingently,
Seotus' conception of contingency thus rests on the view that the First Cause is viz. to cause contingent being.
not a natural agent ad extra, but is a free agent 153, If there is contingency, there Duns Scotus' account of contingency - its explanation with reference to the
must be a free agent; the primary source of contingency must then be rooted in the contingent causation of the First Cause of being rather than to some random
divine will 154 • combination of secondary effects, and consequently the ontological notion of
However, since necessity is generally a more perfect attribute of being than contingency - is highly significant for the metaphysics of the Subtle Doctor.
contingency, it may seem that to cause contingently is an imperfect type of L. Honnefelder articulates the implication of Scotus' notion of contingency for his
metaphysics:
nostra respectu actus et dimittendo quod est imperfectionis in ea, transferendo ea quae sunt Contingency is ... no more as it is for the 'philosophers' ... a consequence of
perfectionis in ea ad divina, statim apparet propositum ». Indifference with respect to the object, materiality, but it is a mode of being in its actual existence, it is no longer a
which is at stake in the following arguments of Scotus, is considered to be a perfection, and therefore category ofPhysics, but a transcategorical attribute of being 158.
it can be ascribed to the will of God, cf. Rep. I A, ibid.: «Voluntas enim nostra indifferens est
contingenter ad actus diversos, quibus mediantibus est ad diversa obiecta et ad plures effectus.
Prima indifferentia est imperfectlonis ; secunda est perfectionis er ideo ponenda in divinis », The Necessity ofthe Intelligibility ofCreatures 159
(150)Leet.ld. 39q. 1-5 n.51, Vat. XVII, 495 :« ... Voluntas ... quando est causa eliciens aetum
volendi contingentem habet habitudinem ad actum, ita quod 'volens in a, potest nolle in a' .», If the world as we can understand it is a contingent world and radically
English text in JOHN DUNSSCOTUS, Contingency and Freedom. 118. In this statement a stands for a
specific moment in time.
dependent for its creation and continued existence upon God's will, then one
(l51) Lect. I d. 39 q.I-5 n.54, Vat. XVII, 497: «Voluntas divina ... potest in eodem instanti might conclude that metaphysics - which, as a science, must be based upon
aeternitatis et pro eodem instanti aeternitatis velle et nolle aliquid, et sic producere aliquid et non
producere », English text in JOHN DUNS SCOTUS, Contingency and Freedom. 126. For a more
detailed account ofScot us ' concept of synchronic contingency, SODER, Kontingenzund Wissen, 92- (155) « In omni differentia entis necessitas est perfectior condicio quam contingentia ; probatio,
107; S.DUMONT, «The Origin of Scotus's Theory of Synchronic Contingency», The Modem quia necessitas est perfectior in ente in se, ergo et in omni differentia entis ; ergo et in ista differentia
Schoolman, 72(1995) 149-167. entis quae est 'causa', necessitas est perfectior contingentia perfectissirna ; ergo causa necessario
(152) Ord. I d. 8 p. 2 q. un. n. 299, Vat. IV, 324-325: «Et si quaeras quare ergo voluntas divina causat », Ord. I d. 8 p. 2 q. un. n. 259, Vat. IV, 300. This objection is not a quote from anyone of the
magis detenninabitur ad unum contradictoriorum quam ad alterum, respondeo : "indisciplinati est philosophers; it is rather an objection Scotus makes to himself, in the spirit of Aristotle and Avicenna.
quaerere omnium causas et demonstrationern" (secundum Philosophum IV Metaphysicaei, (156) Ord. I d. 8 p. 2 q. un. n. 302, Vat. IV, 326 : « ... Dico quod 'necessarium' est perfectior
"principii enim demonstrationis non est determinatio". Immediatum autem est voluntatem velIe condicio in omni entitate (quam 'possibile') cui condicio necessitatis est possibilis ; non est autem
hoc, ita quod non est aliqua causa media inter ista, sicut est immediatum calorem esse calefactivum perfectior in ilia entitate cui non est cornpossibilis, quia contradictio non ponit aliquam perfectionern
(sed hie naturalitas. ibi Iibertas), et ideo huius "quare voluntas voluit" nulla est causa nisi quia ethoc non est ex ratione sui sed ex ratione illius entis cui repugnat, Et ita dico quod necessitas repugnat
voluntas est voluntas, sicut huius "quare calor est calefactivus" nulla est causa nisi quia calor est omni respectui ad posterius, quia ex quo omne posterius est non-necessarium, primum non potest
calor, quia nulla est prior causa ». To be not explainable by further reasons is, as mentioned before, a habere necessariam habitudinem ad aliquod eorum».
typical feature ofthe will. Cf. n. 63. (l57)Ord. I d.8 p.2 q.un. n.305, Vat. IV, 327-328: «Dico quod ens causabile non potest
(153) The fact that God is not naturally active ad extra is shown by Scotus with the following habere istas plures differentias, necessarium et possibile, sed omne ens causabile est tan tum
consideration: A natural activity of God ad extra would imply that God has a natural inclination ad possibile ; et ideo non est perfectionis in causa posse causare istas plures differentias, quia ad
extra, and therefore he would be naturally related to something other than himself; this is impossibile nulla est potentia »,
impossible. Cf. Pro princ. c. 4 concl. 4, ed. ROCHE, 80; Ord. I d. 8 p. 2 q. un. n. 268, Vat. IV, 304-305. (158)« Kontingenz ist ;.. nicht mehr wie bei den 'philosophi' ... Folge der Materialitat,
(l54)Lect.I d.39 q.I-5 n.54, Vat.XVIl, 497. cr. SODER, Kontingenz und Wissen; sondern Modus des Seienden in seiner aktuellen Existenz, nicht mehr Kategorie des Physischen,
HONNEFBLDER, Scientia transcendens, 82-94; E. GtLSON, Jean Duns Scot .. Introduction a ses sondern transkategoriale Bestimmtheit des Seiendseins », HONNEFBLDER, « Die Kritik des Johannes
positions fondamentales, Paris, Librairie philosophique J. Vrin, 1952 (Etudes de philosophie Duns Scotus am kosmologischen Nezessitarisrnus der Araber », 260.
medievale42),153. (159) HONNEFBLDER, Scientia transcendens, 45-56; 94-108.
218 TOBIASHOFFMANN THEDISTINCTION BETWEEN NATUREANDWILLIN DUNSSCOTUS 219

necessary knowledge 160 - is an impossible enterprise. However, even though Scotus emphasizes that the divine idea of a thing (i. e. the intelligible being of the
created being is contingent as to its real existence, Scotus maintains that it is creature) does not proceed freely from the divine will, but necessarily from the
necessary for non-contradictory finite being to be possible 161 and to be divine intellect:
intelligible 162.
... iris to say thatthe instantofeternity in which God knows his own essence can be
While the cause of the actual existence of created beings is the contingent will divided into two signs or instances of nature. In the first one, God knows his
of God 163, the very possibility of their being derives not from God's will, but from essence as the first object, and in the second one he knows ail that is distinct from
God's intellect 164. Besides his own essence, God knows all finite beings that are himself as being naturally constituted by the act of God' s knowledge in a certain
non-contradictory. Prior to God's knowledge of the non-contradictory finite intelligible being. Thus God is, with respectto the things that are distinct from him,
beings 165, they do not have any entity whatsoever. By virtue of the act of the the natural cause oftheir intelligible being, by the act ofhis knowledge. The proof
divine intellect they come to be in a 'known being' (esse cognitum) or 'intelligible ofthis; since the will does not want anything that is not known, the divine intellect
being' (esse intelligibile) 166. This is what Scotus refers to as the divine idea of a knows something according to its intelligible being before the will wills it, because
thing. All non-contradictory and non-necessary beings which are thus ideally the will can only have an act which refers to something known by the intellect But
every cause that precedes the will and that is previous to the will is a natural cause,
present to the divine intellect can come to real existence if God's will sovereignly
and all that precedes the act of will is merely natural; so it follows that God is a
decides to cause their real being 167. Thus, before something comes to contingent
natural causeof all that is distinctfrom him as to its intelligiblebeing 169.
existence through creation, it necessarily already possesses an intelligible notion
in God's intellect - Scotus refers to it as 'objective being' (esse obiectivumi 168. Scotus continues by arguing that human knowledge has its ontological foun-
dation in God's knowledge of possible creatures, namely in the divine ideas 170.
Once it receives real existence and thus becomes accessible to human knowledge,
(160) AR1ST., Analytica Posteriora I, 2, 71b9-12; I, 4, 72b21-74a3. the notion of a thing as it is necessarily in God's intellect, and as it has a necessary
(161) This does not mean that possible being is necessary being, The condition for possibility is
to be non-contradictory and to be non-necessary, Ord. I d. 43 q. un. n. 7, Vat. VI, 354 (cf. n.166). The ideal being (esse intelligibile, esse obiectivumi, is also the basis for human
qualification 'non-necessary' excludes God's own infinite essence from the definition of possible knowledge 171. Thus, whereas its existence is contingent, its inner 'intelligible
beings. structure' is necessary. Since human knowledge is founded in the natural and
(l62)Cf. Lect.I d.2 p.1 q.I-2 n.57, Vat. XVI, 131: e ... Dico quod licet alia entia a Deo necessary knowledge of God (though mediated by knowledge of existing crea-
actualiter sinl conringentia respectu esse actualis, non ramen respectu esse potentialis. Unde illa
quae dicuntur contingentia respectu actualis exsistentiae, respectu potentialis sunt necessaria, ut tures), metaphysics has an objective and necessary ground in the First Being 172.
licet hominem esse sit contingens, tamen ipsum esse 'possibile esse' est necessarium, quia non
includit contradictionem ad esse ». For the necessity of finite non-contradictory being to be
intelligible, see the following remarks. V. GOD'sPRODUCTIONSADINTRA: SOMENOIESONTHETRINITY
(163) Cf. Leet. I d. 39 q. 1-5 n. 62-63, Vat XVII, 500; SODER, Kontingen: und Wissen, 173-176.
(164) Cf. Ord. I d.43 q. un. n. 7, Vat. VI, 354; ibid., n. 14, Vat VI, 358-359; Rep. IA d.43 q. I,
Oxford, Merton 59, fol. 183r: « ... Res anle suam existentiam extra prius sint possibiles: ergo The distinction between will and nature is also fundamental for Duns Scotus'
secundum suum esse possibile prius oportet principiari esse ab aliquo, non ab omnipotentia vel doctrine of the Trinity 173. This distinction is the basis for his explanation for why
potentia activa, ergo ab intellectu ». Cf, also A. B. WOLTI:.R, «Scorns on the Divine Origin of
Possibility», American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 67 (1993), 95-107. For a more detailed
analysis of what follows, HONNEFELDER, Scientia transcendens, 22-31.
(165) The priority is ontological, not chronological. Scotus talks of different 'instants of nature' (169) « ... Dicendum quod iIlud instans aeternitatis in quo Deus intelligit essentiam suam,
to distinguish what is ontolcgically prior or posterior. dividi potest in duo signa vel instantia naturae, in quorum primo intelligit essentiam suam ut primum
(l66)Ord. I d.35 q. un. n.32, Vat. VI, 258; Lect.I d.35 q.un. n.22, Vat XVII, 452. Scotus obiectum, in secundo autem intelligit omnia alia a se ut constituta naturaliter in quodam esse
argues that a finite being, produced into intelligiblebeing by the divine intellect, is possible formally intelligibili per actum intelligendi divinum: et respectu rerum aliarum a se, ut habent esse
by itself and principally by the intellect of God, Ord. I d. 43 q. un. n. 7, Vat. VI, 354: «Possibile ... intelligibile, est Deus causa naturalis per actum suum intelligendi. - Cuius probatio est: quia cum
est illud cui non repugnat esse et quod non potest ex se esse necessario ; lapis, productus in esse voluntas nihil velit nisi cognitum, igitur intellectus divinus prius intelligit aliquid secundum esse
intelligibili per intellectum divinum, habet ista [sc. the two conditions: to be non-contradictory and intelligibile quam velit illud, cum voluntas non possit habere actum nisi respectu cogniti ab
non-necessary] ex se formaliter et per intellectum principiative ; ergo est ex se formaliter possibilis intellectu; sed omnis causa praecedens voluntatem et praevia voluntati est causa naturalis, et affine
et quasi principiative per intellectum divinum ». For more details, L. HONNEFELDER, «Die Lehre quod praecedit actum voluntatis est mere naturale; igitur Deus est causa naturalis aliorum a se
von der doppelten ratitudo entis und ihre Bedeutung fur die Metaphysik des Johannes Duns secundum esse intelligibile », Lect. I d. 3 p. I q.3 n. 191, Vat. XVI, 302. Cf. Ord. I d. 38 q, un. n. 6,
Scotus », in Deus et homo ad mentem I. Duns Scoti, Rome, Societas intemationalis Scotistica, 1972 Vat. VI, 305 ; Quodl. q. 14n. 13, Viv.XXVI,47a
(Studia scholastico-scotistica 5), 661-671; WOLTER, «Scotus on the Divine Origin of Possibility», (170) Lect. Id. 3 p.l q. 3 n. 191-192, Vat. XVI, 302-303;Ord. Id. 3 p. 1q.4n. 262, Vat. III, 160.
American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 67 (1993), 95-107; S. KNULTTILA, Modalities in (171)Cf. n. 168.
Medieval Philosophy, London-New York, Routledge, 1993, 139-149. (172) HONNEFEWER,Scientiatranscendens, 104.
(167)Cf. n.163. (173) For a more extensive discussion of the role of the distinction between will and nature in
(168) Ord.] d. 36q. un.n.47, Vat. VI, 289. the doctrine of the Trinity, F. WETTER, Die Trinitiuslehre des Johannes Duns Scotus, Munster,
220 TOBIASHOFFMANN THEDISTINCTION BETWEEN NATURE ANDWILLINDUNSSCOTUS 221

there must be precisely three persons in the Trinity, that is - assuming that there is the Son) that has its lovable object present 184, namely God's essence as what is
only one ungenerated person 174 - why there are precisely two Trinitarian loved 185. Although both productions are necessary (because it would be
productions. Furthermore, the distinction between will and nature allows him to impossible for God not to know and love his infmite essence), the productions of
distinguish the Son and the Holy Spirit by virtue of their emanations, and therefore the Son and the Holy Spirit remain essentially different, since one is produced by
without needing to refer exclusively to their relations of origin 175. natural generation while the otheris produced by free spiration 186.
Christian doctrine traditionally claims that there are two Trinitarian So far, Scotus has argued that there must be only two essentially different
productions, namely, the generation of the Son and the procession of the Holy Trinitarian productions in God. Scotus' attempt to demonstrate the necessity of
Spirit 176. Scotus attributes the necessity of there being two and only two precisely three divine persons requires him to show that these two productive
Trinitarian processions to the fact that there are two and only two formal active principles do not produce more than one person each.
principles 177. According to Pseudo-Dionysius, each great number is best To show that each of the productive principles (i. e. the will and intellect) only
accounted for by only one thing or by the smallest possible number of things 178. In act to produce one person, Scotus appeals to two features of the Trinitarian
Scotus' view, this Dionysian ptinciple applies also to active principles 179. What productions. First of all, each production fully taxes God's entire (infinite)
Scotus wishes to show is that there are only two essentially different active productive potency in the intellect and in the will. Second, each production is
principles. His argument runs as follows: an active principle produces in either a eternal. If the first condition were not the case, the productive principle could
determinate way or not. If it produces in a determinate way, it is a natural produce more than one person at a time, just as heat can warm up more than one
production; if it does not produce in a determinate way, it is a free production 180. thing. The eternity of production guarantees that there is no production of several
Following the Augustinian tradition, Scotus argues that the Son is generated persons successively, in the way that one person would be annihilated and a
by the memory of the Father. Scotus understands the memory of the Father as «the further person would be produced 187,
intellect to whom the intelligible object [i. e. God's essence] is present» 181. Since Scotus' insights regarding the mode of Trinitarian productions now allow him
the intellect is a natural agent l 82 , the Son is produced naturally (per modum to account for the distinction between the Son and the Holy Spirit. This in tum
naturae) 183. Conversely, the Holy Spirit is produced by the will of the Father (and sheds light on the problem of the constitution of the divine persons. For that which
constitutes the divine person also provides its distinctiveness from the other divine
persons 188. Contrary to the common opinion 189, Scotus argues that the divine
Aschendorff, 1967 (Beitrage zur Geschichte der Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters 41/5),
31-32; 198-200, For the role of the divine will in the Trinitarian productions, H,R.KoSLA, persons are not distinguished solely by their relations oforigin, but also in terms of
« Voluntas est prlncipium producendi amorem infinitum»: La productio e fa complacentia nel- their properties (which he calls therefore 'constitutive properties' : paternitas,
i'autocomunicarione divina secondo il B, Giovanni Duns Scoto, Rome, PAA-Edizioni Antonianum, filiatio, spiratio passiva) 190. An additional reason for the distinctiveness applies
1995,111-163.
between the Son and the Holy Spirit, namely between their emanations: for
(174) Ord. I d. 2 p. 2q.I-4n. 359-370, Vat. II, 338-341.
(11S)The dominating assumption among theologians in the 13'" century was that the only Scotus, generation is essentially different from spiration 191. For whereas
reason for the distinction of the divine persons is that they are constituted by different relations of generation is natural (per modum naturae), spiration is «in the way a will acts»
origin, cf. THOMAS AQUINAS, S. theol. I q. 29 a.4 in corp., Leon, IV, 321b (for references to other (permodum voluntatisi 192.
medieval theologians who held this view see the footnote of the Vatican Edition to Ord. I d. 26 q. un.
n. IS, Vat. VI, 4). Thus the Father is assumed to be constituted as a divine person by his relation of
Scotus' derivation of the distinction of the two Trinitarian productions from
e.
paternity, i. because he generates the Son. The relation of origin for the Son is the relation to the his distinction between will and nature has an even further significance for his
Father who generates him (filiatio) ; for the Holy Spirit it is the relation to the Father and the Son who
spirate him ispiratio passiva).
(176)Cf. the Symbol of Constantinople (381), ed.H.DENZIOER-A.SCHONMETZER, Enchiri-
dion Symbolorum, Barcelona-Freiburg i. Br-Rome, Herder, 1976",66-61, Nr. ISO. (l84) Leet.Id. 2 p, 2q.I-4n. 175, Vat. XVI, 171; Ord.ld. 2 p, 2q, 1-4n. 226, Vat. II, 263,
(117) c-« Id, 2 p. 2q, 1-4n. 300, Vat. II, 305. (185)Ord. Id.lOq.un.n. 9, Vat.IV,342.
(178) Ps. DIONYSIUS, De divinis nominibus, c. 13,2, ed. B. R. SUCHLA, Berlin-New York, W, de (l 86) Lect. Id, 13 q. un. n. 29, Vat. XVII, 175; Ord.Id.l3q.un. n. 82, Vat. V. 109. Cf. this brief
Gruyter, 1990 (Patristische Texte und Studien 33), 221-228. expression «Spiritus Sanctus procedit per modum libertatis et Filius per modum naturae", Lect. I
(119) Ord.Id.2p. 2q, 1-4 n. 301, Vat. II, 305. d. 1 q. un. n. 44, Vat. XVI, 488.
(180) Ord. I d.2 p. 2 q. 1-4 n. 30 1, Vat. Il, 306. A similar explanation is given in Ord. I d. 10 (187) Lect. l d. 2p, 2q.l-4n. 205, Vat. XVI, 186;Ord, Id. 2p. 2q. 1-4n, 303, Val. II, 308-309.
q. un. n. 8, Vat. IV, 341. In this text, Scotus adds thai both productive principles (per modumnaturae (I88)Cf.Ord. I d.26 q.un. n,I4, Vat, VI, 4: « ... Quoeumque Pater constituitur in esse
and permodum voluntatisy are pure perfections, personali, eo distinguereturpersonaliter aFilio et Spiritu Sancto »,
(181)« ... Memoria perfecta, sive, quod idem est, istud IOtum 'inrellectus habens obiectum (I89)Cf.n.175.
intelligibile sibipraesens' »,Ord. Id.z p.z q. 1-4n,221, Vat. II, 259. (190) Duns Scotus is very reserved about the constitution and the distinction of the divine
(182) As to the generation ofthe Son, d. Ord. I d. 2 p. 2 q, 1-4 n. 30 I (deleted text), Vat. 1I,308, persons by reason of the relations of origin solely, Ord. I d. 26q. un. n. 32-56, Vat. VI, 10-22.
(183) Lect. I d. 2 p. 2 q.I-4 n. 202, Vat. XVI, 184; Ord. I d. 2 p. 2 q. 1-4 n. 301 (deleted text), (191)Ord. Id.ll q.2n,46, Vat. V,I9-20,
Vat. 1I,308. (l92) Lect: Id.11 q. 2n. 39, Vat. XVII, 143.
222 TOBIAS HOFFMANN THEDlSTlNCTION BEfWEEN NATURE AND WILL IN DUNS seOTUS 223

doctrine of the production ofthe Holy Spirit 193. The Holy Spirit is produced by the hindrance to natural cause/effect relations 200. To characterize the will primarily as
love with which the Father and the Son love the divine essence 194. This love 'indifferent' is misleading, since the will as a pure perfection is always ordered to
necessarily originates in God. The necessity of this origin is by virtue of the the good. Furthermore, the view that what is specifically characteristic ofthe will
infinity of God's will and by virtue of the infinity of the goodness of the will's is its capacity to produce opposite effects is erroneous, because the intellect can
object (God's essence) 195. Since the production of the Holy Spirit occurs in the have opposite contents ofthought201, and even natural things like the sun can have
way of the will iper modum voluntatisi, it is free. If it is true that the Holy Spirit is opposite effects 202. Contrary to modern understanding, the will's freedom is not
produced both necessarily and by free will, we have a further case that shows that restricted to the capacity of decision, since in the mode of necessity there is no
there is no contradiction between a free will and its necessity 196. Even though the decision.
production of the Holy Spirit is necessary, he is not produced by natural necessity, What must be characterized as essential to the will is its capacity to self-
but by free love l97 • In showing this, Scotus is in accordance with Augustine's determination. Even when the will acts necessarily, it is never necessitated from
claim that the Holy Spirit proceeds "like a gift" - quomodo datum - and therefore the outside, but it still determines itself. The self-determination of the will has an
freely 198. For Scorns, there is no contradiction between the gift offree love and the important consequence for the personal character of the will's activity. Both the
necessity ofthis love. responsibility for one's action and the possibility for disinterested love reside in
As we have seen, Scotus' arguments about the nature and function of the will the will's capacity to determine the person's activity; natural agents cannot be
and nature reappear in his discussion of the doctrine of the Trinity. For example, blamed for their actions, nor can they be attributed merit 203. Self-determination is
since the will is most intimately endowed with freedom, this must be most the basis for the self-possession of the human person, because it is in the power of
profoundly so in God. The intellect is considered as a natural agent, and the Son, the will to control human action 204.
who is generated by the memory of the Father - his intellect with the presence of When comparing Scotus' account of the will with that of e. g. Thomas
its object -, is said to be produced permodum naturae. In the spiration of the Holy Aquinas, both medieval authors seem to emphasize different features of the will.
Spirit per modum voluntatis it is manifest that freedom and necessity are not Thomas sees the will first of all as an appetite. In his account of morality as the
contradictory. pursuit of happiness, the issue of whether the will is free or not (in fact it is not free
with regard to the ultimate end, but by "natural necessity" it wills this end)205 is
secondary; what is important is that the will is the potency that pursues happiness.
However, Scotus focuses primarily upon the way the will elicits its acts. For him,
CONCLUSION
the specific feature of the will is to elicit its act freely, even in the mode of
necessity. For Scotus, love being the final perfection of man, the major concern
The most important outcome of the study about the distinction of nature and seems to be how the will is not determined to its act in the way of a natural active
will is a better understanding of Scotus' account of the will's central features. principle, for true love as a natural process is inconceivable206.
Following Scotus' teaching, several misconceptions can be discarded. It is
inadequate to characterize the will by its opposition to necessity, since « the will as
pure perfection is intended to act in the simply perfect mode of necessity» 199. (200) Quodl. q. 16n.9, Viv.XXVr, 195a.Cf. n. 102.
(201) AR!ST.,Metaph. IX, 2, 1046b4-5.
Moreover, it is false to maintain that the will alone is the domain of contingent
(202) Cf. n. 29. '
activity, insofar as, to some extent, contingency can be accounted for as a (203)Ord. II d.42 q.1-4 n.l, Vivo XIII, 448b: « ... Omnis causa activa in universe praeter
volumatem est naturaliter activa: ergo nulla praeter voluntatem est vituperabilis propter suam
actionem ». Cf. Lect. II d. 25 q. un. n. 14, Vat. XIX, 232, where Scotus quotes Augustine (De libero
arbitrio ill, 1, 13, CCSL 29,276): « Motus voluntarius quo voluntas hue atque illuc volutatur, nisi
(193) Cf. more extensively P. SCAPIN, Contingenza e libertadivina in GiovanniDunsScoto, 52- in nostra esset potestate.neque laudandi neque vituperandi essemus », Cf. also Ord. r d. 8 p, 2 q. un.
61 ; L. IAMMARROl'm, «La liberta in S.Tommasoe in G.DunsScoto », Miscellaneafrancescana, 95 n. 285, Vat IV,314;Ord. Id.17n.26, Vat. V, 149.
(1995),25-71, especially 53-56; MOHLE, Ethik als scientia practica, 368-375. (204) For the inference from the will's free act to the self-control of a human being, Rep. II A
(194)Ord. Id.lOq. un.n.P, Vat. IV, 342. d.25 q. un. n. 7, Vivo XXIII, 120b: « Voluntas enim non potest aliis potentiis imperate, nisi per
(195) Ord. Id.IOq. un. n.47, Vat. IV, 359 ;cf. n.108. actum voluntatis, vel nisi veliteis imperate, vel nisi velit ipsasexequi imperium, aquo est iIlud velle
(196) Ord. Id.lOq. un. n. 56-57, Vat.IV, 363 .cf, n.lOO. effective. Aut igitur istum actum causat in se immediate, tunc pari ratione standum est in principio ;
(197) This is in contrast to, among others, Thomas Aquinas: «Spiritus autem Sanctus procedit vel hoc habet aliunde. et tunc imperium suurn non est in sua potestate ».
ut arnor, mquantum Deus amat seipsum. Unde naturaliter procedit, quarnvis per modum voluntatis (205) Cf. THOMA.S AQUiNAS, S. theol. I q. 82 a. 1 in corp., Leon. V, 293b.
procedat », S. theol. Iq. 41 a. 2 ad 3, Leon. IV, 423b. (206)Ord. I d.l7 p.1 q.1-2 n.26, Vat. V, 149: « ... Actus ille non est meus qui non est in
(198) Lect. I d. 18 q. un. n. 17, Vat. XVII, 264 : « Sed tamen aliquid possir dari alicui, praesup- potestate mea; sed actio ipsius habitus non est in potestate mea, quia habitus ipse - si est activus -
ponit aliquid communicatum libere ». non est liber, sed principium naturale; ergo illud 'diligere' non erit meum, sic quod in potestate mea
(199) HOERES, Der Wille als reine Yollkommenheit, 81. sit, et ita non merebor illo actu ».
224 TOBIASHOFFMANN

The distinction between the affection for the advantageous and the affection
for justice helps to account for the fact that something can be loved without being
desired. This applies to the will of God for his creatures: God loves human beings
without desiring them 207.
In the final analysis, the capacity of the will to transcend its own subjective
interest is the reason for the existence of contingent being: God's will freely
decides to create or not to create finite being. The gratuitous character of creation
and grace are in accordance with this notion of contingency. Yet while the actual
existence of creatures is contingent, their intelligibility is necessary. Nature and
will are thus at the base of two different productions ad extra: the possibility of
creatures is produced by the intellect in a natural way, whereas the real existence
of creatures derives from the free activity of God's will.
This distinction of two different types of production ad extra corresponds to
two distinct Trinitarian productions: the Son is generated by a natural act of the
intellect, whereas the Holy Spirit proceeds from an act of the will. Freedom of will
moreover is not contradictory to the necessity of Trinitarian productions: the Holy
Spirit proceeds as an expression of free love, in a necessary production 208.

Ne en 1967, Tobias Hoffmann a fait des etudes de theologie a Fribourg-en-


Brisgau eUI Fribourg (Suisse), entre 1987 et 1993. A termine en 1999 une these
de doctorat de philosophic aFribourg (Suisse), intitulee Creatura intellecta. Die
Ideen und Possibilien bei Duns Scotus mit Ausblick auf Franz von Mayronis,
PonciusundMastrius.
«Individuation bei Duns Scotus und bei dem jungen Leibniz », Medioevo, 24
(1998), 31-87 ; «Ideen der Individuen und intentio naturae: Duns Scotus im
Dialog mit Thomas von Aquin und Heinrich von Gent», Freiburger Zeitschrift
fiir Philosophie undTheologie, 46 (1999),138-152.

(207) Cf.Rep. III d. 26q. un. n.18, Vivo XXIII, 475a.


(208) I am grateful to 1. Berkman, 0, Boulnois and S. Hipp for helpful comments on this article.
I am especially indebted to J. Berkman for reviewing my English.

Das könnte Ihnen auch gefallen